Symposium Introduction

“Why Wollstonecraft?” Emily Dumler-Winckler has frequently fielded this question over the course of developing this book. Mary Wollstonecraft, for all of her undeniable historical import especially for women’s rights and the feminist movement, has received little substantive attention in the fields of Christian ethics and theology—while historians have underappreciated the theological aspects of her thought. Emily Dumler-Winckler’s Modern Virtue effectively introduces Mary Wollstonecraft to Christian ethics and theology and shows the significance of the theological aspects of her thought in this impressive and ambitious work. 

This book is broad-ranging in its scope without ever losing sight of its central focus and purpose: to demonstrate how Wollstonecraft intervened in disputes about the nature of virtue and its exemplars in ways that remain relevant today. Dumler-Winckler shows how Wollstonecraft may be a model for modern virtue theory that is responsive to social-political change and dissension. In Wollstonecraft’s context, this was notably (though not exclusively) centered on demonstrating that women are moral equals to men and that the “feminized” virtues to which their moral landscape is woefully restricted calls for contestation and revision. Thus, Dumler-Winckler suggests that we read Wollstonecraft in a tradition of dissent that she pictures as the ongoing “tailoring” of the “wardrobe” of the moral imagination through constructive critique that allows for subverting and adapting inappropriately conceived virtues. This image, taken from Wollstonecraft, is a guiding metaphor for the book, as it conveys the work of adapting and modifying the moral imagination and its norms. Dumler-Winckler picks up Wollstonecraft’s “tailoring” image as a key term for the ongoing revision of how virtues are conceived. Dumler-Winckler also argues that picking up this image offers a way of reconciling virtue theory and social critique. She situates Wollstonecraft in her eighteenth-century context and her lively political dialogues with contemporaries (for example, the Revolution debates of the 1790s) while showing the older traditions of Christian moral theology in which she stood and bringing her forward into dialogue with contemporary thinkers on virtue, gender and patriarchy, democracy and justice.

While it’s undeniable that the conditions of and opportunities for women’s lives have changed dramatically since Wollstonecraft’s time, the form Wollstonecraft’s dissent takes is all too familiar. She refuted “sexed” virtues and social norms for how women are expected to behave. She claimed that a range of virtues and aspirations are human rather than exclusive to one sex or the other. All of this remains highly relevant, even if it too requires tailoring. Still, “tailoring” the terms of Wollstonecraft’s vindications requires unfortunately all too little altering for contemporary terms. As Kate Manne’s recent work on misogyny has demonstrated,1 sexist expectations for women’s conformity to and performance of gendered social norms remain pervasive and subject to punitive enforcement. We are, alas, not so far from the archetypes of “virtuous virgins or vicious whores, Marys or Jezebels, sacrificial Hannahs or seductress Eves” (135) that Wollstonecraft bemoaned as constraints on women’s agency and that set the terms on which they are accepted or rejected, praised or pilloried. Wollstonecraft’s concerns are also politically embedded in concerns about democracy, abolition, and resistance. At the same time, and as Dumler-Winckler points out, significant alterations are required for our time, notably to encompass intersectional concerns, especially as regards racialized discrimination. This is a key asset that the “tailoring” metaphor and Wollstonecraft’s model offers—a way of integrating ongoing contestation and revision or, in a word, dissent.

Considering Wollstonecraft here and now also leaves us with the sober recognition of how hard it can be to gain receptivity to efforts at tailoring dominant and dominating norms. It is one thing to alter a garment, and another for these alterations to be accepted or embraced. Wollstonecraft understood that women thinking for themselves is a “herculean task” because “social norms create ‘difficulties peculiar to her sex to overcome, which require almost superhuman powers’” (164). Recent work on epistemic and testimonial injustice reveals that these difficulties remain current.2 Yet the way that Wollstonecraft persistently subverts sexist and misogynistic tendencies by focusing her attacks not on women who conform to confining norms but rather on “a masculinized body politic and its deficient social and ethical formation” (164) remains a bracing call—one that contemporary feminists must continue to “tailor” to encompass concerns beyond Wollstonecraft’s own.

The responses to Modern Virtue in this symposium offer a rich and wide range of avenues for further engagement. They also, I think, demonstrate how relevant Dumler-Winckler’s work is for contemporary debates in ethics broadly. Ted Smith suggests that a diachronic mode that situates the tradition of dissent across time and accounts for Wollstonecraft’s place in history—including more attention to the interplay between her ideas and her lived experience—might enrich both the study of Wollstonecraft and of the tradition of dissent in which Dumler-Winckler places her. He asks how to think about the ways in which Wollstonecraft’s thought, embedded as it remains in certain historical structures of domination, interacts with the model Dumler-Winckler wants to draw into the present. Constance Furey places Wollstonecraft in dialogue with an unlikely partner, the medieval mystic Julian of Norwich, on questions around the imitation of Christ as a means of virtue formation. She prompts Dumler-Winckler to say more about what makes Wollstonecraft’s way of interacting with virtue distinctively modern, but also suggests that Wollstonecraft might be better understood as a visionary rather than a moralist. Tal Lewis also raises the question of exemplarity and imitation, particularly as regards a concern about plurality in the forms this might take. Further, he situates Modern Virtue in a line of works looking to dispel the persistent “zombie narratives” of modernity’s decline, but wonders what it will take for this endeavor to succeed – a query that invites us to think alongside Dumler-Winckler about the current shape of the field. Candace Jordan probes the relationship between passions and virtues, questioning whether in fact various passions (anger and sympathy, for example) should be understood as virtues in their own right, rather than passions to be perfected by virtues like love and justice, which might reinforce systems of domination that constrain women, people of color, and LGBTQ+ communities. Madeline Cronin rounds out this set of responses with reflection on the kind of judgment that Wollstonecraft practices: a pluralistic form that is open to disputation without jettisoning appeals to standards or ideals. She also suggests that Sara Ahmed’s attention to how attempts at revision prompt resistance might orient us to the challenges involved in truly incorporating a queer “slant” in relation to dominant garb.

Dumler-Winckler offers a compelling portrait of what Wollstonecraft was up to and what she may offer to contemporary religious ethicists, feminists, virtue theorists, and theologians. But beyond that, she uses her engagement with Wollstonecraft to make an incisive intervention in the debate about how we might think about virtue, modernity, gender, and social critique. Modern Virtue shows us that one woman’s struggle may continue to yield generative insights and discussion on these fronts.


  1. Kate Manne, Down Girl: The Logic of Misogyny (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017).

  2. Miranda Fricker, Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007).

Ted Smith

Response

The Historical Wollstonecraft

On the very first page of Modern Virtue, Emily Dumler-Winckler makes sly and stylish use of two epigraphs to show the significance of the argument that follows. Dumler-Winckler quotes the worries of Samuel Miller and Charles Hodge—two of the defining faculty members of Princeton Theological Seminary in the nineteenth century—that if the views of Mary Wollstonecraft prevailed, then women might hold every kind of office (Miller) and there would be “an end to all social subordination” (Hodge). The impact of what Wollstonecraft called a “revolution in female manners” would be all-encompassing, and, Hodge feared, “all virtue would speedily be banished.” Dumler-Winckler shows that Hodge was wrong on this last point: virtue persisted, even flourished, in Wollstonecraft’s thought. But she hopes that Hodge and Miller will be right in their wider prediction that Wollstonecraft’s influence would lead to greater opportunities for women and an end to domination. The fears of Miller and Hodge define the hopes that animate Modern Virtue. That the book began life as a dissertation at the seminary they once dominated make the irony especially delicious.

Modern Virtue joins a more recent tradition that has flowed through both the university and the seminary in Princeton, especially since the publication of Jeffrey Stout’s Ethics After Babel (1988) and Democracy and Tradition (2004). Stout’s works resisted the twin caricatures that drove the narrative in Alasdair MacIntyre’s After Virtue (1981). MacIntyre described a modernity that renounced tradition, knew nothing of virtue, and so could not resolve moral arguments or form good characters. He contrasted this with pre-modern traditions that offered scant support for notions of rights, equality, or dissent, at least as they play out in modern societies. Against MacIntyre’s narrative of decline, Stout showed resources for moral reasoning within the “Babel” of modernity and sketched a modern democratic tradition with the kind of virtues, exemplars, and practices for resolving disputes MacIntyre’s story said modernity could not sustain. That project has been deepened, expanded, and transformed in myriad ways by a number of scholars who studied in Princeton, including Jennifer Herdt, John Bowlin, David Decosimo, Molly Farneth, and Alda Balthrop-Lewis. Individually and collectively, their work represents some of the finest and most influential scholarship in the field of religious ethics in the last three decades. To say that Dumler-Winckler joins this tradition as a peer with Modern Virtue begins to suggest both the excellence of the book’s scholarship and the nature of its contributions.

Dumler-Winckler frames her argument against those she identifies as “virtue’s defenders,” on the one hand, and “virtue’s despisers,” on the other (“designers” of new lists of virtues occasionally join the despisers). Against defenders like MacIntyre and Hodge who worry that modernity erodes any notion of virtue or tradition, Dumler-Winckler shows how Wollstonecraft had a lively (and decidedly modern) sense of virtue. She further locates Wollstonecraft in a tradition that flowed through Dissenters, Nonconformists, and other free-thinkers who built academies, places of worship, and other institutions in and around Newington Green in what is now North London. Dumler-Winckler presses these same notions of modern virtue and a tradition of dissent against those she calls despisers of virtue, like feminist ethicists Ann Snitow and Sarah Conly. Against despisers’ arguments that notions of virtue reflect sedimented relations of power, and so are inherently patriarchal, Dumler-Winckler shows the emancipatory and feminist potential in Wollstonecraft’s modern virtue and the tradition of dissent in which it comes to life.

If Dumler-Winckler’s representations of virtue’s defenders and virtue’s despisers are always on the edge of tipping into straw men, they still create a strong frame that makes the central argument of the book clear. It is especially strong in extending Stout’s argument against MacIntyre to a new generation of self-appointed defenders, with Brad Gregory’s Unintentional Reformation featured in repeated engagement. In making the case for the centrality of virtue to Wollstonecraft’s thought, Dumler-Winckler does not just find the word “virtue” sprinkled throughout her texts. Through readings that are both very close and nearly comprehensive, she develops a thick account of what Wollstonecraft means by virtue and how virtue functions in her thought. Dumler-Winckler’s depth of knowledge of both Wollstonecraft’s work and the secondary literature in multiple disciplines sets up the book’s most important contribution: establishing Mary Wollstonecraft as a thinker who must be reckoned with in religious ethics. 

Wollstonecraft was hardly unknown before this book. She was already a major figure in the fields of philosophy, English literature, and historical studies. And religious and theological ethicists like Lisa Sowle Cahill, Jean Porter, and Jeffrey Stout had all made reference to her. But Dumler-Winckler reads Wollstonecraft into the conversations of religious ethics in a sustained and purposeful way that is without precedent. She shows what Wollstonecraft might contribute to long-running conversations on topics like love, justice, and the relationship between the two. And she suggests the potential for much more. 

Modern Virtue’s careful work with early modern texts invites a series of questions about the role of historical studies in ethics. I don’t think these questions are unique to Modern Virtue, nor do I think they necessarily grow out of shortcomings of the book. They might be asked of many different works in ethics that engage history—including my own. But the work in Modern Virtue is rich enough to let them arise with particular clarity.

I want to raise three questions in particular. First, how should we construe the temporal relationship between the thoughts of past and present thinkers? There is a tension in Dumler-Winckler’s book around this question. When she is making her case against virtue’s defenders, she needs to speak of Wollstonecraft clearly in the past tense. Wollstonecraft’s location in the latter decades of the eighteenth-century matters, for it shows that notions of virtue survived into this time and flourished as part of a tradition of dissent. To establish that tradition, Dumler-Winckler needs some thinkers to be before Wollstonecraft and others to be after her. She needs a diachronic relationship between the thinkers she is considering. But when she wants to make clear Wollstonecraft’s contributions to contemporary debates, she tends to establish a synchronic relationship between thinkers in a timeless philosophical present. She might write that Wollstonecraft “seems to agree with Dewey” on one page (236) and then, just a few pages later, name Wollstonecraft’s affinities with Augustine (239). A single page might put Wollstonecraft in conversation with Judith Butler, Michel Foucault, Henry David Thoreau, Aristotle, and Thomas Aquinas (127). It’s a rich conversation, but an ahistorical one. The book tends to oscillate between these diachronic and synchronic modes, considering Wollstonecraft in the dense network of her actual early modern interlocutors on one page and then putting her into a timeless conversation with a syllabus of thinkers from many different centuries on the next. 

The synchronic mode is so tempting because it promises contemporary relevance. It’s what lets the work feel like ethics, and not just a history of ethics. But the whole idea of tradition—even a tradition of dissent—requires the diachronic mode. That commitment is what sets the stakes in relation to which Modern Virtue’s core argument for a tradition of dissent matters. It’s too much to leave behind. What would it be like to stay in this diachronic mode—to think about ideas in history, or, more baldly, just to insist that it matters that some thinkers lived before others—even as we aspired to make normative claims upon the present? One way would be to follow Modern Virtue’s pointers towards a tradition of dissent and connect that tradition to the present. Dumler-Winckler makes promising hints at a tradition of interpreting Wollstonecraft that runs through nineteenth- and twentieth-century feminists like “Theodosia Bartow Burr, Lucretia Mott, Emma Rauschenbush-Clough, Sarah and Angelina Grimké, Virginia Woolf, and Emma Goldman” (17). That list might be extended to canonical North Atlantic readers of Wollstonecraft like Simone de Beauvoir (who does get mentioned in the book) and Betty Friedan; it might be broadened with readers like Olive Schreiner of South Africa; it might get more personal with more extensive consideration of Wollstonecraft’s daughter Mary Shelley; it might grow sharper in contrast to detailed assessments of critics like Samuel Miller and Charles Hodge. Pointers to many of the building blocks for such a tradition are already in Dumler-Winckler’s book (and even more are in Eileen M. Hunt’s Portraits of Wollstonecraft: The Making of a Feminist Icon1). The task is to string them together, however loosely, into a tradition of dissent that connects a thoroughly historical Wollstonecraft to contemporary debates. Such a narrative would show the making and remaking of the “wardrobe of the moral imagination” that Dumler-Winckler attributes to Wollstonecraft (and Burke). If a long narrative assumes too much continuity, one could tell shorter stories of moments of bricolage that retain a diachronic relation between thinkers. The challenge might be resolved in still other ways. The main thing is to take it up.

A second question is closely related to the first: How should we think about the relationship between a thinker’s biography and her ideas? Dumler-Winckler is surely right that William Godwin’s publication of his Memoirs of the Author of A Vindication of the Rights of Woman in 1798, not even a year after Wollstonecraft’s death, gave her opponents tools for discounting her thought. The power of Dumler-Winckler’s intellectual portrait of Wollstonecraft helps overcome this marginalization. Dumler-Winckler does not deny the details of Godwin’s account of his wife’s life, including lovers she did not marry, a child born out of wedlock, and a suicide attempt. But she also does not let these biographical details too close to the arguments of Wollstonecraft that she wants to advance. This lets her position Wollstonecraft as the precursor to someone like Ruth Bader Ginsburg (1–2), who was married to one man in an egalitarian but otherwise fairly traditional relationship for more than fifty years. It remakes the wardrobe passed on by Wollstonecraft into the respectable professional feminism of Kamala Harris’s white pantsuit and pussy-bow blouse (310–11).

But if Wollstonecraft’s life is seen as connected to her thoughts—if we assume some degree of agency, courage, and consistency on her part, even under difficult circumstances—we might imagine a more radical legacy. What difference would it make for our understanding of Wollstonecraft’s contributions to debates about sex, love, reproduction, and marriage if we let her own choices count as part of what she has to say, not displacing but supplementing her written work? And what difference would it make to reflections on what it means to live in imitation of Christ (as in Dumler-Winckler’s chapter 3) if we took seriously Wollstonecraft’s attempted suicide and comment afterwards that it was “one of the calmest acts of reason” (cited on p. 25)? What would it mean for how we understand what Wollstonecraft has to say about reason? It is to Dumler-Winckler’s great credit that she lets the embodied life of Wollstonecraft on to the page to open these doors to further thought. Now I’d like to follow her through them.

A third question arises as something of a particular version of the second: How can we make sense of a past thinker’s entanglement with prevailing forms of domination of her time? Wollstonecraft was committed to feminism, democracy, and the abolition of slavery in ways that were remarkable among white Europeans in the eighteenth century. As Dumler-Winckler helpfully acknowledges, she also used orientalist tropes of the subjugation of women to make her case for gender equality. Wollstonecraft was, Dumler-Winckler cites Joyce Zonana as arguing, “at once explicitly feminist and orientalist” (72). Dumler-Winckler further notes Willie James Jennings’s argument that Wollstonecraft saw the Black abolitionist writer Olaudah Equiano in a “middle position”: human, but beneath “those with extra ordinary powers” (72).

Dumler-Winckler acknowledges these “now-obvious unjust prejudices” as parts of Wollstonecraft’s worldview (73). But she argues that Wollstonecraft is still working towards a more democratic taste, especially in her valorization of poor and working-class people. She further argues that Wollstonecraft “provides the resources for an immanent critique of her own work and of the Scottish Enlightenment’s racialized stage-theory of civilization” (73). I think that’s right. The next step is to actually perform a detailed version of that immanent critique. What happens to Wollstonecraft’s arguments for gender equality without an assumed hierarchy of civilizations? What happens to her rhetoric if orientalist tropes are seen for what they are? How do her arguments emerge on the other side of the refining fire of immanent critique? What’s the shape of modern virtue after whiteness?

Pursuing questions like these would strengthen the book’s response to those Dumler-Winckler labels as virtue’s deniers. She can find some thinkers who want to jettison the whole notion of virtue, even normativity itself, and the book’s arguments hold up against these totalizing critics. But arguing that we need some kind of normativity, some notion of virtue, doesn’t really touch Jennings’s argument against Wollstonecraft’s dismissive reading of Equiano in The Christian Imagination.2 Jennings’s critique is fully normative. It does not depend on denying all virtue; it just denies the virtues of a particular imaginary that privileges whiteness. It argues that a particular notion of virtue—one Wollstonecraft shares—is implicated in a pattern of domination that was powerful in her time. Likewise, Judith Butler does not argue against normativity as such in their more recent work. Rather, they argue for an ethic that “is not an ethic that seeks to destroy the constitutive violence of all norms. It is a mobilization of that same violence against a particular violent outcome for the purposes of nonviolence.”3 Here Butler, like Jennings, calls for something like what Dumler-Winckler calls immanent critique. Critics like Butler and Jennings cannot be positioned as deniers, and Dumler-Winckler’s arguments against deniers do not fully answer them. They rather help define the task before one seeking to make a critical retrieval of Mary Wollstonecraft’s modern virtue. 

Each of these questions, at its heart, asks Dumler-Winckler for something more. That is not because this ambitious, learned book does not offer enough. It is because it offers so much: a model of historical research for the sake of ethics, an important argument about modern virtue, and, most of all, a fresh presentation of the thought of Mary Wollstonecraft that significantly enriches the whole field of religious ethics. I am grateful for the book and for the chance to join this early conversation around it.


  1. Eileen M. Hunt, ed., Portraits of Wollstonecraft: The Making of a Feminist Icon, 1785-2020 (London: Bloomsbury, 2021).

  2. Willie James Jennings, The Christian Imagination: Theology and the Origins of Race (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2011), 193.

  3. Judith Butler, “Reply from Judith Butler to Mills and Jenkins,” Differences: A Journal of Feminist Cultural Studies, 18.2 (2007), 187-88. Dumler-Winckler cites the reply on pp. 123–24 of her book/

  • Emily Dumler-Winckler

    Emily Dumler-Winckler

    Reply

    Response to Smith

    Most authors hope to be read, ideally, to be read well. Having written a good deal about taste, I also hoped that readers might enjoy, even relish, the reading. I am delighted that Ted Smith finds my use of the opening quotes “especially delicious.” I have long admired Smith’s work and particularly his ethical engagement with historical movements and figures. Our first conversation began with friendly disagreements about John Brown and fellow abolitionists, and we have had others since then. I have found him to be a generous, rigorous, and critical interlocutor, and no less so, here, with Modern Virtue. I’m grateful.

     How should we construe the temporal relationship between the thoughts of past and present thinkers?” 

    Smith construes the relationship as either diachronic or synchronic and worries that the synchronic mode places thinkers in an ahistorical and “timeless philosophical present.” I want to linger with this construal before offering another. I wrestled with the question of when to use past and present tense throughout the book. Ultimately, I use the present tense far more than the past, even when describing thinkers thoughts and commitments within their historical context. Sometimes that’s quite deliberate, as when I stage the Revolution debates of the 1790s in a dramatic mode that mimics Burke’s and Wollstonecraft’s depictions of the French Revolution (81). Elsewhere, it was simpler to describe various thinkers’ ideas, in context, in the present tense. 

    Smith’s suggestions about staying in a Wollstonecraftian diachronic mode are fertile. As he notes, I provide hints about some of the figures that might appear in such a project: not only those influenced by her work in Europe and America, but also in Jamaica, South America, and eventually many other regions of the globe. I hope that others continue this work.

    Admittedly, my primary aim in Modern Virtue was not to trace traditions of dissent that flow directly from Wollstonecraft to other thinkers. I was not primarily interested in the question of her influence or impact. Rather, I wanted to demonstrate the significance of her work, which has been largely overlooked in religious ethics, within longer and wider traditions of dissent. I hoped to show that such traditions are capacious and porous enough to integrate premodern traditions of the virtues, Christianity, republicanism, and democracy with traditions of feminism, gender and critical theory, liberation, abolition, revolution, and rights in the modern era, indeed, that Wollstonecraft exemplifies this integration (3). 

    With Smith, I agree that diachronic considerations are particularly important for situating any thinker within their historical context and for tracing their inheritance, contributions, and influence. I am also not convinced that synchronicity is the most helpful way of thinking about the constructive work involved in creating a conversation among thinkers in various times, places, and contexts. Importantly, I do not see this latter, constructive task as ahistorical, acontextual, or timeless. 

    Rather than situate my writing within diachronic and synchronic modes, I use what Robert Brandom calls de dicto and de re and Richard Rorty calls “historical reconstruction” and “rational reconstruction” to construe the relation between past and present thinkers (32). De dicto and “historical reconstruction” involve specifying and examining a thinker’s commitments within their historical context. De re or “rational reconstruction” involves imagining what a thinker might say or with whom they might agree or disagree, if they were able to address similar issues and debates in other contexts, given what we know of their commitments (32). When I draw connections between Wollstonecraft and John Dewey or Shawn Copeland, for example—that Wollstonecraft seems to agree with Dewey that “Every generation has to accomplish democracy over again for itself” or that her criticisms of forbearance are akin to Copeland’s criticism of the virtues and “Christianity of the plantation”—I do not imply a timeless or ahistorical conversation that floats above diachronic traditions of dissent (237, 155). Rather, I suggest points of connection or congruence (or discontinuity and disagreement) among various thinkers given their particular commitments in their particular contexts. 

    How should we think about the relationship between a thinker’s biography and her ideas?”

    Smith feels that I do not let the biographical details of Godwin’s Memoirs, which scandalized many nineteenth-century readers, close to the arguments that I advance about Wollstonecraft. Wollstonecraft’s life and work were more radical and scandalous in her time, as I elaborate, than even Smith lets on: two children conceived with two men out of wedlock, a rejected proposal for a ménage-à-trois, two suicide attempts, persuading her postpartum sister to leave an abusive marriage which resulted in the death of her newborn, residing with fellow radicals in Paris during the Reign of Terror, the publication of two political treatises (as a woman!) including the first sustained vindication of women’s rights, a Gothic novel on the oppression or Wrongs of Women that treats class inequalities, prostitution, asylums, and (what we would now call) rape and abortion, and much else besides (18–26). While I am sure that I could have done more, I indicate that I aim to depict her agency and work in precisely the agential, courageous, radical, and integrated terms that Smith commends (18). 

    At the same time, Smith’s question is complex. It is especially complicated in the case of non-male thinkers who are often overly biographized and psychologized in ways that detract from rather than illuminate their substantive contributions. For instance, if seen as a precursor to the monogamy of Ginsburg or the professionalism of Harris, as Smith suggests, Wollstonecraft certainly appears less radical! I worried that referencing these contemporary figures might confuse or distract. Crucially, what connects Wollstonecraft to the fiery dissents of the “notorious RBG” and the abolitionist Sarah Grimké is not their sex lives. Rather, as I note, what connects these women across the centuries is their commitment to justice and the ways they augment traditions of dissent (3). Likewise, the connection with Harris is neither professionalism nor politics (302). She broke a historical-political glass ceiling the same week that the first public statue honoring Wollstonecraft made a dent in England’s public art ceiling. Such “firsts” expose the deficiencies of the social, political, and religious imaginaries that have long fastened and reinforced the ceilings. I use these events to elaborate the sartorial metaphor central to the book: the importance of tailoring rather than dispensing with inherited ethical wardrobes as Hambling does with her “Barbie on a Boulder” statue. I trust that Smith would ask similar questions of a book that focused on Hegel, Barth, Thoreau, Tillich, Yoder, or indeed, John Brown. But many, perhaps most, would not. 

    Specifically, Smith wonders, “What difference would it make for our understanding of Wollstonecraft’s contributions to debates about sex, love, reproduction, and marriage if we [I] let her own choices count as part of what she has to say?” I address that question most directly in the section “A Revolution in Loves: Friendship and Marriage” (262–69). Here, a discussion of her marital ideal of mutual friendship, eros, and sexual pleasure is paired with her insistence that the patriarchal inequalities of eighteenth-century marriage, education, and sexual norms—which render wives property of their husbands—make it virtually impossible to realize that ideal. Wollstonecraft descriptions of marriage various as a form of slavery, prison, and prostitution (267). For this reason, she and Godwin were both principally opposed to the institution of marriage (only marrying for pragmatic reasons three months before her death in childbirth with Mary Shelley). Wollstonecraft’s romantic relationships exemplify, I argue, both (with Imlay) the tumultuous love against which she warned readers in VRW and (with Godwin) the inception of her marital ideal of mutually erotic friendship. Both extremes were “still quite radical in Wollstonecraft’s own time” (269). 

    In the same section, I discuss her vivid refusal of an early marriage proposal. Declining to “prostitute [her] person for a maintenance” she declared in a letter to her suitor, “I am POOR—yet can live without your benevolent exertions” (268). How should we think about the connection between her life, ideas, and work in this instance? Does her refusal reflect her principled thoughts on prostitution and the institution of marriage, or did this specific proposal amid poverty form her thoughts? Or is this a false opposition? How would we know? In any event, this early refusal is integrated with her later arguments that women need more opportunities for economic independence so that they are not forced to resort to marriage as “common or legal prostitution” (VRW 218, MW 137). Her depiction of prostitution in her late novel suggests that Wollstonecraft neither denounced prostitution or sex work nor endorsed it as a marital ideal. As an aside, I relate Wollstonecraft’s own suicide attempts most directly to the suicide attempt in one possible ending of the same unfinished novel (275).

    How can we make sense of a past thinker’s entanglement with prevailing forms of domination of her time?

     My attempt to grapple with this question led me to suggest that recognizing such entanglements should make us more curious and reflective about our own entanglements today. I begin to make sense of Wollstonecraft’s entanglement with the orientalist tropes, as Smith notes, by naming them and suggesting that she provides resources for internal critique. Some of the resources for internal critique described in the book include her sharp rejection of civilizing missions meant to assimilate and romanticizing logics meant to idealize the poor, as well as her abolitions commitments and efforts to expose and censure racist logics (73–74). But the internal critique might take several other forms. I will suggest a few. 

    When Wollstonecraft invokes orientalist tropes about gender inequalities, power, and sexuality—the “seraglio,” “Chinese bands,” “Egyptian taskmasters,” “Turkish bashaws,” and Russian whips—she does so to accentuate her criticisms of the patriarchy, misogyny, and gender inequalities of European pedagogies, practices, and gender norms (VRW 76, 111, 267, 260). Whatever prejudices the English and French may have against these other cultures, she suggests, their own gender norms are just as bad if not worse. For instance, amid her censure of the English educational system, she remarks, “To preserve personal beauty, women’s glory! The limbs and faculties are cramped with worse than Chinese bands” (VRW 111). Her use of such orientalist tropes is troublesome and lamentable. 

    Nevertheless, if the point of such problematic comparisons is to make European gender norms and inequalities appear all the worse, to provoke her readers to see the patriarchy and misogyny of their own culture, to turn the orientalist gaze back on the Occident with freshly critical eyes, or even to blur rather than reinforce the distinction between the two, then the comparisons themselves provide one resource for internal critique. If Wollstonecraft had seen orientalist tropes for what they are would she have still used them to try and advance her criticisms of European gender inequalities? If the rhetorician’s subversive use of sexist European tropes (like “masculine women”) are any indication, she may have (162). Regardless, we can criticizer her use of these tropes while recognizing that the substance of her criticisms of European patriarchy, gender norms, and inequalities do not depend on them. She thoroughly criticizes prominent European pedagogues, philosophers, and politicians on their own terms. 

    Another way of reckoning with such entanglements includes recognizing interpretive disputes about them. As I discuss, some have suggested that like much of nineteenth- and twentieth-century white feminism, Wollstonecraft did not devote as much attention to race, racism, or slavery as she did to other forms of domination (208). Others argue that her unwavering and explicit opposition to the institution of slavery, calls for abolition, and denunciations of racist logics undergird her resistance to all other forms of domination and oppression including her arguments for women’s rights (72, 208–9). 

    No doubt, Wollstonecraft’s life, work, and literary priorities were shaped by her own social location as a white eighteenth-century woman. Between publishing her first and second vindications of human and women’s rights (1790, 1792), an important Abolition Bill was defeated in the House of Commons, signaling a major setback for the antislavery campaign (209). Rather than devoting her energies to the abolitionist cause in London, Wollstonecraft left for France to join fellow revolutionaries, witness the Revolution, and write a work entitled, An Historical and Moral View of the Origin and Progress of the French Revolution (1794). Abolition was not her primary or singular focus. 

    Still, Wollstonecraft grasped the significance of debates about the Revolution in France for revolutionary and abolitionist movements in Europe, Haiti, and beyond. Indeed, an excerpt of her Vindication of the Rights of Men (VRM), including some of her key abolitionist arguments was published in a Kingston, Jamaica, newspaper a few months prior to the inception of the Haitian Revolution (1791) (208). In their respective accounts of the French Revolution, Burke turns the British gaze to the “horrors and monstrosities” of the women’s march in France, the “unutterable abominations of the furies of hell in the abused shaped of the vilest of women”; Wollstonecraft redirects their gaze to the horrors and monstrosities of “the fair ladies” in England who assiduously wed mastery, pseudo-virtue, and a culture of sensibility, as well as to slavery as a veritable hell on earth (105, 110, 111). Because hers was the first book-length radical response to Burke’s Reflections on the Revolution in France, these two became the major European political theorists of the revolutionary era for the Kingston newspaper in 1791.1 

    But there is at least one other resource for internal critique: modern virtue in a Wollstonecraftian vein. Wollstonecraft is committed to an account of the virtues that augments practices of social criticism by rejecting as vicious semblances of virtue imaginaries that privilege hetero-patriarchal whiteness. In this respect, I find her account compatible with the work of Jennings and Butler. Smith reads Jennings as arguing that Wollstonecraft’s “particular notion of virtue… is implicated in a pattern of domination particular to her time.” Modern Virtue demonstrates that there are various accounts of the virtues in modernity and that Wollstonecraft uses virtue discourse to denounce pseudo-virtues and condemn the vicious patterns of domination in her time. As a piercing social critic, she not only denounces various systems of domination and their interrelations—slavery, patriarchy, education, standing armies, penal systems, prisons, the enclosure of the commons, and religious intolerance—she also provides resources to continue that work, even in critical engagement with her own. Because virtue discourse participates in traditions of dissent, we can use the virtues as sources of internal critique and renew the task in our own time.

    I portray Butler as neither a defender nor denier, but rather both at once. They defend a notion of virtue understood as critique and deny a notion of virtue understood as violence. Wollstonecraft provides a more nuanced account of the virtues than these extremes provide. At the same time, I argue that robust criticisms of sham virtues—like the criticisms that Wollstonecraft and Butler offer—depend not merely on a practice of criticism but on the virtues that augment this practice (124).


    1. Eileen Hunt Botting, “Wollstonecraft in Jamaica: The International Reception of A Vindication of the Rights of Men in the Kingston Daily Advertiser in 1791,” History of European Ideas 47, no. 8 (2021): 1304–14.

Constance Furey

Response

An Unruly Tradition

Imitatio Christi, Mary Wollstonecraft, and Julian of Norwich

Emily Dumler-Winckler’s Modern Virtue is a multi-faceted, interdisciplinary book. Prof. Dumler-Winckler is herself a professor of constructive theology, with a PhD from a religion and society program, and the book is about an eighteenth-century philosopher who is known as the mother of first-wave feminism, intriguingly presented here as a guide to rethinking virtue—a term and area of ethics variously maligned or celebrated as synonymous with normative commitments. My own research areas don’t immediately identify me as an obvious contributor to this discussion. I was trained as a historian of Christianity, with a particular focus on medieval and early modern materials, and I’ve never researched or taught Wollstonecraft’s work. I have written on virtue, in an article about Puritan marriage and covenantal theology’s account of obligatory love, yet learned when doing so (from the perplexed responses to that article offered by two ethicists in my department) that my understanding of virtue is idiosyncratic at best and muddled at worst.1 On this account, I am avowedly unqualified to respond to this book. All of my work is, however, animated by what I take to be Modern Virtue’s extraordinary achievement: to demonstrate that traditional sources are often more radical than critics or caretakers allow them to be (radical in the sense of rootedness as well as dissenting: because they draw so deeply from alternative imaginaries that they provide new perspectives on problems and possibilities today). 

Imagine, then, the pleasure I felt reading a book that combines the laudable clarity typical of those trained in virtue ethics with a capacious and generous engagement with feminist, womanist, and queer theory suspicious of virtue talk’s normativity and convincing in their claims that attention to virtue is more likely to inhibit than enable human flourishing, particularly insofar as that flourishing is associated with human freedom and creativity. This is a book that both knows and explains the nuances of traditional accounts of virtue and its modern defenders, and at the same time a work that refuses the boundaries imposed by the canonical—which is to say, almost exclusively Greek, Roman, and Christian male—accounts of tradition. Modern Virtue is, in short, a book urgently concerned with the present, unafraid of contemporary culture’s complexity, and yet convinced that the past offers invaluable lessons we have not yet learned. 

Was it persuasive in arguing that Mary Wollstonecraft is an inspiring guide to a culture of dissent? Did it convince me to follow her lead, to make virtue central to my thinking and teaching and living? I posed these questions to myself the same week I was teaching the English mystic Julian of Norwich in a medieval Christianity class and, in other contexts, listening to  political historian Samuel Moyn discuss his recent book about the crisis of liberalism with a self-described conservative who agreed with Moyn’s diagnosis of the problem although not his solution.2 The difference between Moyn and his interlocutor—self-described as liberal and conservative—turned on the question of how to evaluate what Moyn described as liberalism’s highest value: human creativity, and the conservative, Daniel McCarthy, was inclined to dismiss as liberalism’s pathological hedonism. What do I make of Wollstonecraft’s virtue compared to Julian’s emphasis on compassion and Moyn’s on creativity? Does the nineteenth-century feminist better prepare me to dissent from the destructive norms of contemporary society than does the visionary anchorite? Or the sophisticated, optimistic, male defender of liberalism?

Julian of Norwich is now most famous for a profoundly calm reassurance, “All will be well, all manner of things shall be well.” Julian arrives at this assurance, however, through a long process of interpreting visions she had when, near death, she focused all her attention on a crucifix that an attending priest held before her face. The opening pages of Julian’s short vision, and her longer account written fifteen years later, meditate in extraordinarily visceral detail on Christ’s suffering body, on the appearance of his face, the viscosity of the blood dropping from his pores.3

I teach these passages to students because they dramatize a significant version of medieval Latin Christianity’s understanding of imitatio Christi: to imitate Christ, many Christians thought, with a creative fervor that spread and deepened over the course of the twelfth century and permeated devotional culture in subsequent centuries, is to suffer as Christ suffered, to feel the bond of compassion—shared suffering that is the site and source of shared love. This is not the same imitatio Christi embodied by Francis of Assisi (d. 1226), stripping naked in the middle of the street to rejecting the affluence of his cloth merchant father, or Clare of Assisi (d. 1253), spreading the word about devotion to lady poverty. In the thirteenth-century model exemplified by Francis (and curtailed, because of gender, for Clare) to imitate Christ is to live as Christ lived, like the birds of the field, without care for the morrow, forsaking family and convention to wander and preach as Christ did with his followers, fed by those who are moved to give food to beggars, without even the institutional support provided by monasteries or ecclesial titles. Each of these possibilities differs also from the imitatio Christi of Francis’s stigmata, and then again from yet another authoritative model: the sacramental and quasi-monastic framework of Thomas à Kempis’s popular devotional text, de imitatione Christi (ca. 1418).4 

These examples, each unconventional in its own way, are a far cry from the imitation of Christ interpreted—as Dumler-Winckler points out this devotional model is so often interpreted—in terms of “blind obedience” or “repressive ‘moral realism’” (149). The questions that arise when teaching Julian, or Francis, or Clare of Assisi are not about repression or obedience but about excess and extremes. Is Julian encouraging masochism? Or compassion? Does her text encourage readers to celebrate and seek pain? Or does she reveal that shared vulnerability deepens the mutuality of a loving relationship? For many students, the masochism subsumes the compassion, for reasons that won’t surprise most of you. The voice of the objection was expressed most clearly in my medieval Christianity class this year by a gay ex-evangelical woman, who hears in Julian’s voice her mother’s oppressive dictate, that suffering is one’s lot in life, to be born with silent patience just as Christ bore the burden of humanity’s sins on the cross. This is the perspective that womanist theologian Shawn Copeland critiques, in a line Dumler-Winckler quotes, condemning the way that “Christianity of the plantation…sought to bind the slaves to their condition by inculcating caricatures of the cardinal virtues of patience, long-suffering, forbearance, love, faith, and hope.” Crucially, Wollstonecraft, too, insists on the danger of this version of Christian suffering: “when forbearance confounds right and wrong, it ceases to be a virtue” (VRW 102, quoted in Modern Virtue, 155). 

Elaborating this point, in a remarkable reading of a frontispiece William Blake provided to Wollstonecraft’s Original Stories from Real Life (2nd ed. [London: Joseph Johnson, 1791]), Dumler-Winckler acknowledges the obvious reasons to object to a version of imitatio Christi that focuses on the cross. “Mortification, humility, self-denial, and forbearance unto death, are not these precisely the Stoic virtues exemplified in Christ? Are these not the very divine attributes Wollstonecraft calls girls and women to imitate? Had she not repeatedly praised a “God long-suffering” and insisted “those most resemble him who practice forbearance” (ED 36, 37, quoted in Modern Virtue 154). Yet alert to the oppressive effect of this teaching on women in particular, Wollstonecraft in fact refuses what a casual reader might assume she accepts by defining forbearance in opposition to submission. Praiseworthy gentleness, she says, is godlike. A “submissive demeanour of dependence…silently endur[ing] injuries; smiling under the lash at which it dare not snarl” (VRW 102, quoted in Modern Virtue 154)— all this is only a semblance of the true virtue. 

Julian of Norwich provides nothing like Wollstonecraft’s (and Copeland’s)5 clear-eyed denunciation of how the imitatio Christi tradition might create as well as compound potential dangers. To entice students to consider the ways that Julian’s message was compassionate rather than masochistic, I could not point to a single sentence where the anchorite draws the contrast for us or denounces a form of patient acceptance that “confounds right and wrong.” Instead, we had to linger on the many things she says about love, how God’s love is abundant, infinitely generative even in the smallest thing. That sin is a wound to be healed rather than a fault to be punished.6 That God is as desirous of human love as humans are desirous of God’s. Blood, as Julian experiences it, is as much about birth as death, the fluid that imparts life from mother to child, linking humans to each other and Christ to all humans. Julian experienced her visions as themselves expressions of her godly will, a will that confirms the connection embodied in Christ’s incarnation. We are never separate from God, Julian maintains, and cannot be separate from God. Her image of Christ’s bodily suffering was accompanied by a spiritual sight of his “familiar love.” Christ is “our clothing,” she explains, “wrapping and enveloping us for love, embracing us and guiding us in all things, hanging about us in tender love.7 This is the message of love. “Do you want to know what your Lord meant? Know well that love was what he meant.” The passage concludes by switching back to a confident first-person voice: “And I saw quite certainly in this and in everything that God loved us before he made us; and his love has never diminished and never shall.”8 

Julian is a visionary not a moralist, a fifteenth rather than a nineteenth century Christian, and a recluse whose way of life had liturgical sanction and who lived, quite literally, within a space defined by the walls of the church. Wollstonecraft, by contrast, had no institutional shelter for her unconventional independence (unless we count the school she founded, which could not survive her absence), she lived by her pen, at least intermittently; her poverty was involuntary; and her feminism explicit. Much separates these two women. 

Their accounts of love likewise cannot easily be aligned. What kind of love, and what connection between love and virtue, does Wollstonecraft offer? In her published writing, aligned with her emphasis on virtue, readers encounter the “calm pleasures of affectionate friendship,” description of sublime admiration, a theologically sophisticated account of agapic ascent from earthly to heavenly love, a charitable expansion from devotion to one to care for many, and “solidarity and self-love” that may also “demand self-sacrifice.” In her writing, and indeed in the words that conclude her last published essay, she speaks of how a preference for the “calm pleasures of friendship” rather than the “sensual tumult of love” could be reassured that “reason, mixing her tranquillizing convictions, whispers, that content, not happiness, is the reward of virtue in this world” (12). Anyone reading an account of Wollstonecraft’s life can understand why she herself might have longed for calm pleasures rather than sensual tumult. I was also moved, even inspired, by her extraordinary devotion to friends as well as lovers and the intense suffering, even unto death, that she observed as well as experienced because of these commitments. Perhaps, then, when it comes to love, Wollstonecraft and Julian are not so different after all, each finding in it peace as well as painfully transformative and revelatory intensity. 

This observation, about how Wollstonecraft and Julian might be compared leads me to two questions. First, a question of periodization, perhaps most clearly posed in relation to the following quote: “Wollstonecraft names and addresses a twofold conundrum, which becomes increasingly difficult to ignore in modernity: relations and systems of domination distort our concepts and cultivation of the virtues, and virtues are integral to just sociopolitical transformation” (12) This insistence on the distinctiveness of modernity comes up in a couple of different ways (as also in this reference to “late-modern” purposes: “In denying sexual virtues—specifically ‘gentleness, docility, and a spaniel-like affection’ as the ‘cardinal virtues of the sex’—Wollstonecraft replaces the gendered pseudo virtues of the early-modern virtue tradition with virtues suited to late-modern purposes” (167). How committed is Dumler-Winckler to the idea that modernity poses unique challenges? Is it because the need for sociopolitical transformation is greater now than in the past? Because our conceptions of virtue are disputed now in a way they were not in the past? Is she affirming the idea that social norms were once more hegemonic than they are now? Or is this just a claim that virtues were agreed upon in a way they are no longer? It is of course a difficult thing to measure, but all too easy to assume, I think (with a recent experience of re-reading Emmanuel La Roy Ladurie’s Montaillou in mind, proving that even a very small community of fourteenth-century French peasants could and did disagree on fundamental Christian doctrines and indeed judgments of who should be counted virtuous, and why). 

Second, a query about this book’s commitment to virtue. Ultimately, I think Dumler-Winckler gives us someone better understood as a visionary than a moralist. It is a central contention of Modern Virtue that Wollstonecraft is “an ideal figure to recommend a rapprochement between virtues’ defenders and despisers.” She makes that case with admirable subtlety and thoroughness. Anyone seeking a rapprochement should look to Wollstonecraft. And those (i.e. virtues’ defenders and virtues’ despisers) who have not yet realized that they want to reconcile should be persuaded by reading this book that they do. In that sense, the book is wholly successful. Still, I wonder if positioning Wollstonecraft in this way obscures what is most wondrous in the achievement of this feminist foremother and her modern commentator. In short, the visionary Wollstonecraft seems more important than the mediator, the adventurous and restless writer more enticing than the comprehensive pedagogue, and the passionate friend the truer model than the theorist of virtue formation. My point is not that some of Wollstonecraft’s writings or some facets of her life or personality are more important than others. I am instead contending that Dumler-Winckler made all of it seem extraordinarily important because of the way it exceeded the bounds of virtuous categories and the careful categorization of virtues. 

On the one hand, one could well conclude that this observation affirms the success of Dumler-Winckler’s stated mission. “Precisely,” she might say: “Wollstonecraft breaks the bonds currently constraining defenders as well as critics of virtue. That’s my central claim!” But I wonder if she would be interested in reflecting on what the other hand might hold. This would—or so I’m suggesting—be the true provocation of the reading of the Blake frontispiece and the unsettling implication of Wollstonecraft’s appeals to imitate Christ, and God. The neatly dressed and sprightly teacher, guiding her pupils, is also a figure of humiliation, helplessness, and sorrow, not just one “dependent on God”9 but something queerer, more like Julian’s Christ: mother and father and co-conspirator and fellow sufferer and trinitarian redeemer, all at once. Likewise, the imitation of Christ and God might be characterized by moderation. On this account, for Wollstonecraft, imitating God involved the cultivation of devotional practices, “impressing ‘habits of order on the expanding mind’ through dialectical readings and prayer”; training in the capacity for good judgment—including resistance to unjust laws and relations of domination and adherence to just authorities and norms; and the cultivation of generosity, and sympathy, and friendship. Yet for Wollstonecraft, to imitate God is also to “adore attributes that, softened into virtue may be imitated in kind, though the degree overwhelms the enraptured mind” (VRW 104, quoted in Modern Virtue 141). This imitation of the divine is to remain alive to that which is not “softened into virtue” and to be still and always possessed of an “enraptured mind.” Is this enraptured mind virtuous?

We were asked, when invited to be part of this panel, to consider what new conversations Modern Virtue might open up, and it is with this in mind that I will close by linking together the brief earlier reference to Moyn, the extended description of Julian, and these concluding questions. I asked at the outset whether this book was persuasive in arguing that Mary Wollstonecraft is an inspiring guide to a culture of dissent? Yes! Not, however, because she is readily contained and directed toward the concerns of our moment, as a direct model for the dissenting virtues I might seek to cultivate in myself and my students. Rather, Wollstonecraft seems an inspiring guide because she evades that containment. She is not simply or clearly proto-modern. Above all, the unruly devotional tradition of imitatio Christi creates the context for her engagement with the relatively tame tradition of virtues. This disruptive devotional tradition—constituted by individuals and groups responding to the extraordinary generative energy of the doctrine of the incarnation, the paradox of the duality of Jesus Christ’s singularity, of a Savior who is both human and divine—could never only be conventional or uniform or synchronic. Thus, the possibility of puzzling and enlivening comparisons. It is in the incongruities as well as the alignments between Wollstonecraft and Julian, for example, in the gaps as well as the continuities, that I can glimpse new possibilities, feel the energy of unexpected insights, and confirm that the creativity Moyn hails as liberalism’s highest value cannot be readily aligned with a singular historical moment or one limited political philosophy. 


  1. Constance Furey, “Relational Virtue: Puritan Marriage and Devotional Poetry,” in The Journal of Medieval and Early Modern Studies. 42.1 (2012).

  2. “What Should be Done about the Current State of Liberalism,” featuring Daniel McCarthy and Samuel Moyn, https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=djmqZuK2yn8, viewed on Jan. 30, 2023.

  3. Julian produced two works. The first, A Vision Showed to a Devout Woman, reported on a series of visions she had when she herself was near death and had prayed to see, so she could share in, the suffering of Christ on the cross and the “fellow suffering” of his grieving mother. The second, A Revelation of Divine Love, was written some fifteen years later. This latter work records how Julian had come to understand and interpret these visions while living as an anchorite, or religious recluse, walled off in the church in Norwich from which she took her name, likely in a ceremony supervised by a bishop reciting the Office of the Dead. Julian of Norwich, Revelations of Divine Love, trans. Elizabeth Spearing (New York: Penguin Press, 1998). For the Middle English version see The Writings of Julian of Norwich: A Vision Showed to a Devout Woman and a Revelation of Divine Love, ed. Nicholas Watson and Jacqueline Jenkins (University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press, 2006).

  4. A good discussion of Thomas à Kempis’s work can be found in Nandra Perry, Imitatio Christi: The Poetics of Piety in Early Modern England (South Bend: University of Notre Dame Press, 2014).

  5. And Dolores Williams, “I don’t think we need folks hanging on crosses and blood dripping and stuff,” cited in Kelly Brown Douglas, Stand Your Ground: Black Bodies and the Justice of God (Maryknoll: Orbis Books, 2015), 186.

  6. Love, for Julian, is universal and persistent, regardless of the state of sin or offense. On the ways Julian’s account of divine love turns atonement theology “on its head” see Rowan Williams, Holy Living (New York: Bloomsbury, 2017), 171–72.

  7. Julian, Revelations, The Short Text, chp. 4.

  8. Julian, Revelations, “The Long Text” chp. 86.

  9. As described in chapter 3’s discussion of Mrs. Mason as a Christ-figure.

  • Emily Dumler-Winckler

    Emily Dumler-Winckler

    Reply

    Response to Furey

    I am grateful for this generous and generative engagement with Modern Virtue. Furey is just the sort of scholar/teacher who I hoped might take an interest in this admittedly strange book: someone not particularly interested in virtue ethics but with a keen interest in the radical resources that historical figures and movements provide for “new perspectives on problems and possibilities today.” How wonderful to have a reader who situates Wollstonecraft within the “unruly devotional tradition of imitatio Christi” that runs through Julian of Norwich and, perhaps in some secularized strain, through Samuel Moyn’s emphasis on creaturely creativity. Furey is delightfully attentive to connections and distinctions between thinkers and contexts in this tradition, and thereby Wollstonecraft’s distinct contributions. 

    The connections that Furey draws between Julian the anchorite and Mary the radical dissenter are rich. The distinctions she draws are also apt even if my response below will trouble the contrast between the visionary and moralist. From the fifteenth to the eighteenth century, from voluntary to involuntary poverty, from conventional recluse to unconventional independence, and from ecclesial endorsement to dissent, “much separates these women,” indeed. These comparisons give rise to Furey’s two central questions. 

    First, the distinctiveness of modernity and its challenges. In the book, I do not seek to settle debates about the nature of modernity, multiple modernities, or the various continuities and discontinuities with the pre-modern era. Instead, I offer something of a via negativa (314–15). Modernity is many things. But it is not the dark ages of the virtue tradition. Virtue discourse and practices remain, even as they are radicalized by Wollstonecraft and fellow dissenters. And features of modernity that virtue’s defenders decry—such as pluralism, ethical conflict, and ecclesial disputes—long predate modernity. Neither is modernity best characterized only by the social and systemic evils that have plagued this period. No doubt, this era is littered with new tragedies and challenges of its own devising. Colonization, capitalism, and global empire, new notions of race, racism, and white supremacy, industrialization and extractive economies, and ecological destruction form the tip of the melting iceberg. Still, socio-political evils long predate modernity. And this era has its own advantages, whether scientific, technological, political, or artistic.

    So, while I do think that modernity poses certain unique, as in novel, challenges, I am not convinced that these are uniquely challenging for the virtue tradition, understood as a tradition of dissent. The twofold conundrum that I claim Wollstonecraft identifies, and to which Furey draws our attention, is nothing new. It has always been the case that “relations and systems of domination distort concepts and cultivation of the virtues, and that virtues are integral to just sociopolitical transformation” (12). The need for sociopolitical transformation is ongoing: no greater or less in modernity than in antiquity. Nonetheless, I think this conundrum becomes “increasingly difficult to ignore” in modernity for a host of reasons. What, if anything, sets modernity apart from previous eras may be a more widespread and profound willingness to challenge the authority of certain persons, institutions, political arrangements, social norms, sciences, and dogmas (318).

    Second, Furey poses a set of questions about the book’s commitment to virtue in contrast to seemingly more visionary, excessive, adventurous, and restless modes. Given a choice between visionary and moralist, I am heartened that she identifies my account of Wollstonecraft with the former. Nonetheless, I hope to present Wollstonecraft as a visionary and a virtue theorist, indeed as a visionary virtue theorist, not primarily one or the other. 

    Likewise, far from a “relatively tame tradition,” I understand the virtues as a tradition of dissent. I see this tradition as part and parcel of what Furey aptly calls the “unruly devotional tradition of imitatio Christi.” Wollstonecraft’s work suggests that the imitatio Christi and the virtue traditions intermingle and are both more radical than their reputations often allow. Still, Wollstonecraft further radicalizes and democratizes these inherited traditions.

    In short, I happily receive Furey’s generous offering from each hand. Yes, Wollstonecraft does break the bonds constraining the defenders’ and despisers’ conceptions of virtue. That is my central claim! And yes, the sprightly teacher is perhaps queerer than even I convey, indeed, no less queer than Julian’s Christ. Wollstonecraft and her exemplars do exceed the bounds of careful or tidy conceptions of the virtues in several ways. This excess is arguably a feature of exemplars and examples broadly. They embody certain aspects of an ideal or generalization in ways that exceed its contours.

    This feminist Jesus may be a figure not only of independent dependence, but also a mother and father figure, at once, co-conspirator and “man of sorrows,” trinitarian liberator and fellow sufferer. Like Wollstonecraft’s fictional exemplar of VRW, such a “female father” would become the “father as well as the mother of her children” and so embody a performative theory of parenthood (VRW 119, MW 166). After the birth of her first daughter and abandonment by her lover, Wollstonecraft knew this kenotic form of love all too well. Long before these events, she was acquainted with “the tremendous mountain of woe that thus defaces our globe!” in this “vale of darkness and tears” (VRM 58, 33, MV 111, 114). Such misery, she insists, demands more than tears: not only sorrow, lament, and loving attention, but some admixture of revolution, reform, and resistance (111).

    For Wollstonecraft, as Furey notes, divine imitation involves adoring divine attributes that, “softened into virtue may be imitated in kind, though the degree overwhelms the enraptured mind” (VRW 104, MV 141). So, Furey asks, “Is this enraptured mind virtuous?” 

    Put simply, yes. Only those who have begun to adore and virtuously imitate the attributes of God can be so overwhelmed and enraptured. For Wollstonecraft, devotional taste that culminates in divine adoration is cultivated through habits and practices like walks in nature, contemplation, prayers of gratitude, confession, generosity, and loving attention to the natural world as well as our own fragility and responsibility within it. These virtuous habits are the seedbed, not the antithesis, of the wonder and awe found in the enraptured mind. 

    In the end, Furey suspects that, “the unruly devotional tradition of imitatio Christi creates the context for [Wollstonecraft’s] engagement with the relatively tame tradition of virtues.” As I suggest above, Modern Virtue challenges the idea that the tradition of the virtues is relatively more tame than its unruly counterpart. The virtue tradition is rather quite radical. It includes a tradition of dissent, resistance, and radical nonconformity. This is not only because of the dissent internal to the tradition itself, and not only because dissenting traditions are rife with the resources for their own transformation, but also because virtues are embodied in the lives of exemplars and communities who revolutionize the social norms, institutions, and polities they inhabit through struggles for justice and solidarity amid the “tremendous mountain of woe that thus defaces our globe” (VRM 58, MV 111). 

Thomas A. Lewis

Response

When Emulation and Setting the Historical Record Straight Are Not Enough

Emily Dumler-Winckler sets out her signposts early: her subtitle, Wollstonecraft and a Tradition of Dissent, evokes Jeffrey Stout’s 2004 Democracy and Tradition; and the title of the introduction, “Who’s Wollstonecraft? Which Traditions?,” directly invokes Alasdair MacIntyre’s Whose Justice? Which Rationality?1 MacIntyre is among the most prominent purveyors of the widespread narrative that Western modernity is characterized by the disappearance of attention to virtue and its replacement by deontological and utilitarian moral theories. Against these narratives, Dumler-Winckler argues for the persistence of attention to virtue, or more specifically attention to and valuing of virtue, in Mary Wollstonecraft, whom for many represents the turn to rights that purportedly did away with virtue. In a manner that parallels Stout’s argument that democracy is a tradition—rather than being at odds with tradition—Dumler-Winckler contends that dissent is itself a tradition, not simply a rejection of tradition. Similarly, her main title, Modern Virtue, is—she contends against MacIntyre, Stanley Hauerwas, John Milbank, and Brad Gregory—not an oxymoron. As she pithily states in her conclusion, “Modernity is not the dark ages of the virtue tradition” (314).2

This is an outstanding book that has done much to correct—and I use this strong language deliberately—my own reading of Wollstonecraft. Dumler-Winckler’s knowledge of and engagement with Wollstonecraft extends far beyond Wollstonecraft’s most famous works, A Vindication of the Rights of Men and A Vindication of the Rights of Woman, demonstrating not only deep familiarity with Wollstonecraft’s writings across time periods and very different genres but also why we must attend to this range of materials in order to best interpret Wollstonecraft. Wollstonecraft is both a brilliant rhetorician and, for the same reason, challenging to interpret; her political concerns and the multiple audiences to which she appeals lead her to craft arguments intended to persuade diverse interlocutors in light of their commitments. Dumler-Winckler’s engagement with the broad corpus is vital to judging which are Wollstonecraft’s own driving commitments and which she is ventriloquizing (a point to which I return).

Her interpretation extends that of David Bromwich in centering Wollstonecraft’s appropriation of Edmund Burke’s metaphor of revising a wardrobe: “Like an expert tailor, she used the tools at her disposal to augment the wardrobe of the eighteenth-century moral imagination” (310).3 In Dumler-Winckler’s reading, this metaphor provides an interpretive key to much of her work. Wollstonecraft neither rejects her inheritance nor thinks that we do it justice if we seek to simply replicate it. As Dumler-Winckler writes in relation to justice, “this autodidact weaves together the strands of various traditions to make a coherent whole. She provides a bricolage that innovatively combines elements of her education…” (184). The image of weaving these elements into a new garment contrasts starkly with MacIntyre’s post-apocalyptic vision of incoherent fragments.4

If I read Dumler-Winckler correctly, she can accommodate this point. Nonetheless, passages such as this stress the importance of independence for Wollstonecraft to a greater degree than Dumler-Winckler brings into focus. Moreover, they suggest a keener awareness of the potential dangers of emulation than Dumler-Winckler brings to the fore. The call to “steel” ourselves against those who have done so much to form us is powerful language, and it suggests that the concern is not just with those who would impose themselves upon us by demanding obedience but even those we admire and respect.5

This concern with models of formation that rely too heavily on discipline is also apparent in her concern with professions that thwart genuine virtue and freedom. Wollstonecraft discusses soldiers as well as the clergy. With regard to the latter, she notes that “the blind submission imposed at college to forms of belief serves as a novitiate to the curate, who must obsequiously respect the opinion of his rector or patron, if he mean to rise in his profession.”6 Again, Dumler-Winckler will rightly highlight that Wollstonecraft here focuses on enforced submission, rather than what we might think of as the voluntary emulation of exemplars. Yet I would suggest that part of the reason Wollstonecraft uses the language of “steeling” ourselves against undue influence is that she—like much of the tradition of reflection on habituation on which Dumler-Winckler draws—is keenly aware that the line between forced and chosen submission to authoritative models is not a clear one to draw. My point is not that Wollstonecraft conceives of dependence as a stage to be left behind or as completely overcome but that her concern with its dangers forms a prominent element of project.

On Imitatio Christi

The concern to recognize the extent of Wollstonecraft’s refashioning of the wardrobe she inherits also arises in the prominence that Dumler-Winckler gives to the notion of the imitation of Christ, making it the title of arguably the core chapter on Wollstonecraft’s account of virtue. Dumler-Winckler makes a convincing case for the importance of exemplars for ethical formation. She also identifies numerous instances in which Wollstonecraft at least alludes to the rich traditions of imitatio Christi as she sets out exemplars. She leans heavily on William Blake’s frontispiece for Wollstonecraft’s Original Stories from Real Life (142–47). Even if we follow Dumler-Winckler’s reading of Original Stories by taking Mrs. Mason as a Christ-like figure on whom the children might model themselves, however, this begs the question of the extent to which Wollstonecraft’s refashioning of the tradition entails a perduring normative authority for Christ as such or more transformatively redeploys elements of this tradition in a new outfit. As Dumler-Winckler notes, the imitatio Christi on offer here is pluralistic: “The image is not singular but infinitely diverse, and we are at best flawed approximations” (170). For Dumler-Winckler, “Wollstonecraft democratized and radicalized the imitatio Christi tradition … by inviting her readers to recognize the incarnate Christ among ordinary women, from Mrs. Mason, Mary, Maria, and Jemima to those selling fish and vegetables in French markets” (313). Even if we grant this point, I am still left with a question: Particularly since Wollstonecraft does not generally explicitly link these multiple models to Christ, what is at stake—for Dumler-Winckler—in ordering them and so much of her conception of virtue in relation to Christ? More specifically, does Wollstonecraft actually preserve a notion of these exemplars as “flawed approximations” of an ideal that is associated with Christ? I believe there is a broader issue here about interpreting Wollstonecraft’s use of Christian language, traditions of thought, and tropes.7 Because it implies that others do not understand—or are not being forthright about—what actually motivates them, ideology critique can thwart democracy and we should resort to it sparingly. I share Stout’s concern. Yet I am also profoundly concerned by the role that these zombie narratives play in the world today. I think of the writings of Patrick Deneen and the comfort that he gives to right-wing movements as well as of then-attorney general William Barr’s widely discussed 2019 talk at the University of Notre Dame. Since reams of excellent scholarship demonstrating the historical inadequacy of these narratives of modernity have been unable to stop this current—even in a range of scholarly circles—should we be shifting more of our scholarly energies toward explaining their persistence in relation to the ideological interests they serve? In this moment, when these zombie narratives arguably play such a significant role in our common life, is it perhaps time to call the hermeneutic ambulance?


  1. Jeffrey Stout, Democracy and Tradition (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2004) and Alasdair C. MacIntyre, Whose Justice? Which Rationality? (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1988.

  2. Importantly, she does not simply offer a one-sided celebration of modernity. She draws attention to slavery, colonialism, the marginalized and oppressed yet notes that “these are not the primary concerns of the subset of modernity’s despisers discussed in this chapter” (235).

  3. For instance, “for Wollstonecraft, theology and religion may be best understood as garments of an inherited and ever-revisable wardrobe of the moral imagination, a feature of religious devotional taste” (19). See also David Bromwich, “Wollstonecraft as a Critic of Burke,” Political Theory 23, no. 4 (November 1, 1995): 617–34.

  4. Alasdair C. MacIntyre, After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory, 2nd ed (Notre Dame, Ind: University of Notre Dame Press, 1984), 1–2.[/footnotes]

    Beyond the powerful reading of Wollstonecraft herself, Modern Virtue situates Wollstonecraft’s contributions in relation to a wide range of competing positions. Her engagements with Martha Nussbaum, Saba Mahmood, and Philip Pettit, not to mention Richard Price, Catherine Macauley, and Edmund Burke, are substantial and illuminating—both in relation to her interpretation of Wollstonecraft and her justification of the constructive claims. Moreover, I would be remiss if I did not mention how thoroughly Dumler-Winckler engages the range of Wollstonecraft scholarship across multiple disciplines.

    In addition to these interlocutors, it is also important to call out the range of reference points Dumler-Winckler invokes: “the Southern Christian leadership conference, the civil rights movement, the women’s rights movement, the Poor People’s Campaign, and the United Farm Workers movement,” for instance (117). Or the brief opening of another sentence, “But like the apostle Paul and Erasmus before her and Gustavo Gutierrez after, Wollstonecraft …” (76). Even when brief, these references serve to expand our own horizons as well as the peoples and movements to whom we feel bound to hold ourselves accountable. She implicitly shows what is lost when our range of vision remains limited to more canonical examples.

    Against this backdrop of profound appreciation, I turn now to four points for further discussion: the importance of independence in Wollstonecraft’s vision; Dumler-Winckler’s focus on the Imitatio Christi, the challenge of engaging Wollstonecraft’s rhetorical styles, and what I am calling “zombie narratives” of modernity.

    The Importance of Independence

    Modern Virtue rightly draws attention to Wollstonecraft’s views of formation and of the role of exemplars in this formation. Nonetheless, Wollstonecraft frequently stresses the importance of this formation as a kind of cultivation of independence (as Dumler-Winckler notes on 149). To be sure, that need not mean a simple repudiation of one’s inheritance, but it does have implications for the understanding of formation and the limits in our relationship to exemplars. Wollstonecraft writes:

    The early habit of relying almost implicitly on the opinion of a respected parent is not easily shook, even when matured reason convinces the child that his father is not the wisest man in the world. This weakness, for a weakness it is, though the epithet amiable may be tacked to it, a reasonable man must steel himself against; for the absurd duty, too often inculcated, of obeying a parent only on account of his being a parent, shackles the mind and prepares for it a slavish submission to any power but reason.[footnote]Mary Wollstonecraft, A Vindication of the Rights of Woman, 3rd ed. (New York: W.W. Norton, 2009), 162.

  5. This point might be considered in relation to her claim that we do not kick away the ladder of habits that formed us (150).

  6. Wollstonecraft, Vindication of the Rights of Woman, 20.

  7. The point arises, for instance, in Dumler-Winckler’s interpretation of Wrongs as “a sociopolitical rendering of Job” (277) or what she makes of allusions to Rom 5:5 on 246.[/footnotes] Surely it is important to keep in mind that a project that draws on the past in the manner suggested, that shows piety toward those sources, will make such references no matter how much the project’s refashioning transforms them. How different would it be to suggest that her view of the immanence of divinity, the plurality of exemplars, and the need to also be wary of exemplars entail that the new dress she has fashioned bears limited resemblance to the earlier form, even though it has drawn upon the latter and would not be what it is without it?

    Engaging Wollstonecraft’s Rhetoric

    Questions about what we make of the diverse elements that contribute to Wollstonecraft’s bricolage intersect with questions about how we read a skilled rhetorician writing to persuade a broad audience who themselves hold diverse commitments. To be clear, my dwelling on this point comes largely from my own struggles to do justice to the complexity of Wollstonecraft’s texts. As Dumler-Winckler highlights, Wollstonecraft read voraciously and was deeply engaged in the political debates of the day. Her two most famous works, the Vindications, were written to move diverse readers. Dumler-Winckler suggests that Wollstonecraft does not open Vindication of the Rights of Woman with theological references at least in part because she is appealing to Talleyrand, for whom such arguments would not be persuasive. Yet might the complementary concern play an important role in explaining her invocation of the imitatio Christi tradition or allusions to biblical passages as she seeks to persuade other of her readers? At points, she engages in a form of immanent critique of her opponents, as when she contends that those who think women’s principal roles should be the rearing of children should be particularly concerned with the quality of girls’ education, since it will shape the child-rearing they go on to do. Faced with this situation, Dumler-Winckler does what I think one should when dealing with such a challenge: seek to develop a reading that can encompass the complexity of the texts. Nonetheless, I would like to hear more about the challenge this presents as well as the elements of the text that most resist incorporation into this reading. I think, for instance, of the opening sentence of chapter 1 of Vindication of the Rights of Woman: “In the present state of society it appears necessary to go back to first principles in search of the most simple truths, and to dispute with some prevailing prejudice every inch of ground” (14). Does this prominent sentence fit into her reading?

    Zombie Narratives

    Finally, I would like Dumler-Winckler’s advice regarding the problem of what I have called “zombie narratives.” Modern Virtue mentions this phrase on page 7; it comes from a talk I gave at the Society of Christian Ethics meeting in 2020. I noted then that the narratives of modernity as the downfall of virtue have been powerfully and repeatedly undermined by bodies of scholarship from the last several decades, including the work of Jeffrey Stout, Jennifer Herdt, and Nicholas Wolterstorff to mention just three examples. It bears noting that Stout introduced the notion of “moral bricolage,” which Dumler-Winckler uses, in his Ethics After Babel, from 1988, in which he critiques MacIntyre’s account of modernity. As I noted in that 2020 talk:

    Collectively, such work has soundly and repeatedly demonstrated the historical inadequacy of these narratives. Yet these flattened narratives keep coming. Kant continues to be invoked in a manner that is little more than a caricature. Wollstonecraft and Hegel, to take two examples, are largely rendered invisible. One has the sense that no matter how many times these narratives of a modern moral fall suffer what would seem to be the fatal blow, they stand back up and, like zombies, keep lurching forward.

    Modern Virtue represents another attempt to dispel this narrative of modernity. As powerful as the book is, I am not optimistic that this is the one that will finally put these zombies in the ground. (One reason is that the work is principally a study of one person who died in 1797 and therefore cannot easily serve as a decisive counterexample to MacIntyre’s narrative, though that is not the principal reason with which I am concerned here.) Of course, the book may do tremendous work in helping some to avoid being seduced by MacIntyrean charms; this is certainly important. Yet the persistence of these narratives despite the excellent work that has so profoundly challenged them might be taken to suggest that they are propelled by something more or other than inadequate historical understandings. Should we, I ask Dumler-Winckler, be looking elsewhere for an explanation? 

    Jeffrey Stout has argued for the importance of taking our opponents’ reasons and claims as seriously as possible—of engaging them as reasons. He contrasts this interpretive generosity with “ideology critique,” which he describes as a “hermeneutic ambulance.”[footnote]Stout, Democracy and Tradition, 191.

  • Emily Dumler-Winckler

    Emily Dumler-Winckler

    Reply

    Response to Tal

    Conversations with Lewis over the past decade have given me the rare pleasure of conversing with a fellow religion scholar who shares a keen interest in Wollstonecraft. I am especially happy to engage his questions here and look forward to further conversations on these themes. 

    Independence

    On Lewis’s reading, Wollstonecraft’s emphasis on independence and the dangers of emulation do not quite come into focus in my treatment of virtue, exemplarity, and imitation. I do claim that Virginia Woolf remark that “the staple of [Wollstonecraft’s] doctrine was that nothing mattered save independence” puts it a bit too starkly (74). But I also argue that Wollstonecraft emphasizes independence as a crucial part of the developmental process of critically virtuous maturation and liberation. Her account of independence and emulation receive the most explicit treatment in chapter three. But this chapter is best read in light of the discussion about independence, judgement, madness, and taste (Chapter 1), their elaboration with respect to the French Revolution (Chapter 2), and her notion of liberty as freedom from domination (Chapter 4). In the third chapter, I hoped to emphasize the importance of independence for Wollstonecraft, while also specifying: 

    1. the role of independence in ethical formation
    2. her emphasis on independence from specific forms of dependence and for specific ends
    3. the ways in which independence remains tethered to certain forms of dependence, and
    4. the various but inescapable dangers of emulation. 

    For Wollstonecraft, “independence… the basis of every virtue” and the aim of moral formation is virtuous independence (VRW 65, MV 126). The argument is circular, but not viciously so. Independence is the basis of every virtue because virtuous agency reflects habits, thoughts, and actions that have become one’s own. The aim of ethical formation, for this proto-feminist, is to gain some measure of independence or freedom from various forms of dependence (especially women’s dependence on men), habits of unthinking obedience and acquiescence, relations and systems of domination, unjust laws, and exemplars, as well as to gain independence or freedom for critically virtuous agency. Accordingly, Wollstonecraft criticizes institutions and systems—from the Church and slavery to standing armies and girls’ education—that deter the independent judgement and action so indispensable for the exercise of true virtues (162). 

    Given her attention to various audiences and rhetorical modes, it is no surprise that Wollstonecraft’s emphasis on imitation, emulation, and independence is somewhat distinct in her various works. Yet, I argue, she consistently describes a process of moral formation that begins in imitation and dependence and eventually requires putting one’s exemplars to the test of critical examination—steeling oneself against or discarding some, adopting others, and emulating the virtues of each (123). 

    This developmental approach to critically virtuous independence, I argue, differs from many critical theorists’ suspicions about virtue and its relation to social criticism: for instance, Judith Butler’s views of virtue as either reducible or antithetical to critique. For Wollstonecraft, formation in critically virtuous independence always depends, to some extent, on the sources of that formation, on the very habits of virtue that bestow a measure of critical independence (74). At the same time, independence remains in tension with various forms of dependence on and cooperation with inherited traditions, God, others, and the natural world (137). 

    For Wollstonecraft, emulation entails many liabilities: the gravitational pull to “servilely copy” those we fear and admire and the paucity of admirable models. She insists on distinguishing true virtues from their sexed semblances because emulating the latter is so politically, socially, and morally fraught. Even class dynamics evince the dangers of emulation. The rich oppress the lower classes not only through systemic exploitation but by encouraging them to ape their manners and tastes rather than to cultivate more revolutionary political virtues (73, 164, 188, 245). 

    In short, emulation is rife with danger. But there’s no alternative. We are mimetic creatures. In the quest for virtuous independence, the more discerning we can be about our own exemplars and the dangers of excessive emulation the better. 

    Imitatio Christ

    Lewis’s wonders about “the extent to which Wollstonecraft’s refashioning of the [imitatio Christi] tradition entails a perduring normative authority for Christ as such or more transformatively redeploys certain elements of this tradition in a new outfit.” My first response is to suggest that this question presents a false choice, or at least that the tradition is far more complex than a dichotomy between normative authority and transformatively tailored garb allows. This is one point of the wardrobe metaphor. There are infinitely diverse ways to put on Christ in one’s context, many of which transform the tradition. This “unruly devotional tradition” (to borrow Furey’s term), or “eclectic legacy” (to use my own), encompassed an array of imitative types and modes even before the modern forms of democratization and radicalization that I attribute to Wollstonecraft (122). In this sense, Wollstonecraft’s garb resembles the prophetic tendencies and garments in this eclectic tradition, from the Hebrew prophets and the early church to the religious dissenters in Newington Green. Nonetheless, her garb also represents distinctively modern, feminist, and abolitionist sartorial modes. 

     What is at stake, Lewis asks, in connecting Wollstonecraft’s conception of the virtues to this imitatio Christi tradition? I do not see myself as making this particular connection so much as making explicit significant connections, which have, like Blake’s frontispiece, been largely ignored or misunderstood. There are warrants for reading Wollstonecraft’s fictional exemplars as part of her effort to democratize and radicalize the imitatio Christi tradition. Aside from the obvious allusions with Mrs. Mason, Wollstonecraft draws on tropes and motifs of ancient and early modern Christian martyr-acts and courtroom scenes in her novel, The Wrongs of Woman (36). By figuring Maria before the Judge like Christ before Pontius Pilate, she seeks to transform the wardrobe of the theological and moral imagination in her own time, especially regarding notions of gender, justice, divorce, criminality, madness, and domination (76). 

    Wollstonecraft’s Rhetoric

    Because Wollstonecraft was a brilliant rhetorician who wrote for diverse audiences, interpreting her work well does pose challenges. When do we read her arguments as her own full-throated views? What passages contain a whiff of wit, parody, or satire? What lines signal appeasement or internal critiques meant to convince her audience on their own terms, terms she may not share or may reject altogether? 

    For instance, I read Wollstonecraft as writing firmly tongue-in-cheek when she wishes that women “may every day grow more and more masculine” (VRW 74, MV 161–63). With a wink, she turns the supposed insult “masculine women” into a pseudo-ideal. After all, “the word masculine is only a bugbear;” so-called “manly virtues,” are human virtues (VRW 76, MV 163). Thus, her cheeky conclusion that we might wish for women to grow all the more masculine. 

    I am not sure what elements of the text would “resist incorporation,” as Lewis suggests, into this rhetorically attuned reading. Rhetorical attunement is the key for meeting the rhetorical challenge. In the book, I read the passage he references as yet another rhetorical mode of argumentation: “In the present state of society it appears necessary to go back to first principles…” (VRW 81, MV 62). Wollstonecraft seems to agree with Burke that first principles or “natural taste” form the basis of agreement about taste—salt is salty—but not a standard to adjudicate disagreements about “acquired tastes” (51, 62, 216). Arguments from first principles provide one mode of rhetorical persuasion, one premise from which she can begin to “dispute with some prevailing prejudice every inch of ground” (62). 

    Zombie Narratives

    Finally, zombie narratives: is it time to call the hermeneutical ambulance? If Lewis is right to suspect that virtues’ defenders are propelled by ideology rather than or in addition to an inadequate historical understanding, we might justly think of them as patients. But I am not convinced that ideology critique, as a hermeneutical ambulance, gets them to the hospital in time to treat their malaise. Rather, to stick with the metaphor, the ambulance may be most effective in sounding the alarm to everyone else—patient coming through. Steer clear. Perhaps my book serves better as an alarm than as a vehicle of rescue and remedy. 

    In this respect, I do hope that Modern Virtue is one effort to call the hermeneutic ambulance. I share Jeffrey Stout’s concerns about the overuse of ideology critique as the first resort. Charity and rigor require a hermeneutic of generosity. While I strive to engage defenders charitably, I am aware that my book is not the first resort, not the first effort to challenge defenders’ narratives of doom and gloom. My criticism may be more shrill, more ambulance-like. Still, I am under no illusion that my book will put the zombies to rest. 

    Perhaps what virtues’ defender-zombie-patients need most is ongoing therapy. In this case, Modern Virtue might be understood as one more in a series of therapeutic interventions. The defenders are held captive by a picture, or rather a narrative, of the virtues’ modern demise and its ideological and economic entailments. From ambulance to psychotherapy, Modern Virtue is one effort to both sound the alarm and to treat the patients. 

Candace Jordan

Response

Passions Among the Virtues

Having had the good fortune to hear Dr. Emily Dumler-Winckler present an earlier version of this work—on virtues, their semblances, and the practices of discernment that help discriminate between them in the context of movements toward just social change, it is a pleasure to read and respond to the final publication. I am excited to continue the dialogue with Dr. Dumler-Winckler and the symposia contributors.

Dumler-Winckler’s beautiful book chronicles how eighteenth-century proto-feminist thinker Mary Wollstonecraft deftly navigates an intractable modern debate between what Dumler-Winckler calls virtues’ “defenders” and virtues’ “despisers” or “designers.” Briefly, according to Dumler-Winckler, defenders charge modernity with abandoning virtue, subordinating the good to the right, and eliminating the theological precepts that give rights discourse coherency. Enter catastrophic pluralism, relativism, and skepticism. Despisers worry that standards of virtue, among other shortcomings, naturalize virtues that are in fact contingent, close critique into the best kind of life, and exclude would-be exemplars based on concealed prejudice. Extending the critique of despisers, designers offer constructive proposals for virtues of their own design, manifest in exemplars from their own religious and philosophical communities.

Wollstonecraft, for her part, charts a third way, embodying what Dumler-Winckler calls a “tradition of dissent,” that avoids getting mired in “culture war” style debates. Demonstrating Wollstoncraft’s refashioning of her inheritance from pre-moderns and her contributions to modern and late-modern debates, Dumler-Winckler’s masterfully rehabilitates Wollstonecraft as a resource for contemporary ethical debates surrounding, virtues and rights, critique, and the common good. Specifically, Dumler-Winckler’s Wollstonecraft argues unequivocally for a nonsexed account of the virtues, endeavoring to help her largely Christian readership distinguish between true virtues and their (sexed) semblances. Cultivation of and contestation about virtues, Dumler-Winckler argues, is essential to Christian communities and democratic societies.

Dumler-Winckler argues that Wollstonecraft does not set out to provide her readers with a detailed analytic account of the virtues, rather the rich moral vocabulary imbuing her writing insists that virtues are good habits, acquired through habituation, education, and mimesis of exemplars. Virtuous independence follows. Rather than offering such a thoroughgoing account, like Aquinas before her, Wollstonecraft was more intent on using her premodern inheritance to aid in distinguishing true virtues from their sexed semblances.

Questions on which I invite further discussion from Dumler-Winckler are related to claims throughout Modern Virtue that virtues such as love and charity perfect passions. It would be helpful to hear Dumler-Winckler say more about the moral psychological picture that leads Wollstonecraft to distinguish among passions and the virtues that perfect them. In addition to considering the upshots and impetus behind her particular moral psychological picture, I’m curious to engage potential pitfalls, on which I conjecture below. 

Wollstonecraft’s moral psychology, following Burke’s, suggests that passions (such as anger and sympathy, for example) rather than being considered virtues themselves are better understood as passions that can be shaped by vices or virtues such as justice and love. Thinking with the Womanist and feminist ethicists (several of whom Dumler-Winckler draws our attention toward), what might be the upshot of considering such passions as virtues themselves rather than passions to be perfected by love? What practical and moral reasons might there be for considering such things virtues in themselves? Why resist the enumeration of a class of “burdened virtues”? What is the significance of calling things like anger and sympathy passions, that can be perfected by virtues, rather than virtues themselves? Might training the passions according to love and charity lead those struggling under systems of domination (women, persons of color, queer and gender non-conforming persons) to temper that which might aid in their recognition of themselves as competent judges and legitimate authorities? What are potential costs in naming something a passion to be made vicious or virtuous (via love and justice)?

Dumler-Winckler argues, and I agree, that virtues (on Wollstonecraft’s and Burke’s moral psychological picture) are sometimes in danger of (and never exempt from) becoming corrupted. Dumler-Winckler illustrates well, via contemporary example and adept interpretation of Wollstonecraft’s oeuvre, that semblances of virtue, exercised toward unjust ends, are vicious. This is not only because of their unjust ends, but also because groups that lie outside dominate cultural paradigms are vulnerable to aping those vicious habits. And yet, consider the potential danger of tempering what Wollstonecraft calls passions by virtues such as love and charity. In contexts of domination, exploitation, and oppression, considering anger as a virtue itself rather than a passion to be moderated by virtue might better befit a particular community. For example, those suffering under the weight of systemic oppression, such as women, persons of color, or LGBTQ folks, might be well-practiced in the virtues of forbearance, charity, and love. 

Educating and habituating these communities in virtues that they may be well formed in already may be pernicious to the imaginative, creative, and critical impulses that are less exhorted within these various communities. Tempering anger or contempt, for example, with love is a familiar refrain. There may be value also in tempering charity and mercy with anger. Consider historical examples (many of which Dumler-Winckler herself acknowledges) of dominant classes aiming to preserve the status quo by exhorting forbearance, charity, and love. We see such rhetoric aimed at movements articulating the value of Black lives, where concerns arise over anger’s potential fracturing of civic bonds, among other ills. Women, too, when working in resistance to sex and gender subordination continue to be exhorted to temper their anger with charity. Consider also the shift in protest tactics among gay and lesbian persons in the United States in the 1980s. Memorial practices of grief and mourning gave way to confrontational activism, which not only helped inaugurate various legislative victories, but also helped protestors recognize their capacity for and claim to pride (rather than shame surrounding their sexual identities) and righteous anger (at prejudice-fueled systemic failures in and beyond public health). Dumler-Winckler compelling argues that Wollstonecraft contends not only with recognitional defects of those perpetrating and advocating for eighteenth-century women’s continued subordination, but also Wollstonecraft didn’t take for granted that women themselves would recognize the capacity for virtuous judgment among their own ranks. Perhaps viewing anger as itself virtuous, rather than as enhanced by virtue, might go some way in the important achievement of self-recognition. Regarding self-authorship and self-recognition, it matters what a group calls themselves. Dumler-Winckler’s rich analysis of Maria: Or, The Wrongs of Woman Illustrated illustrates Wollstonecraft’s creative effort to enable her readers to recognize as qualified judges those who may not be recognized as such. Dumler-Winckler herself notes that the virtuous female critic will appear “quite mad” (76). She interprets this madness as akin to genius, and yet I wonder just how pregnant is this account of madness? Might it include fury?

Terms that Wollstonecraft favors, such as “taste,” “manners,” and “modesty,” might be particularly fitting for her readership. Might these values give pause to those with Womanist, feminist, or queer sympathies in a similar way that love and charity as tempering the passions of anger and sympathy might have? I’m deeply sympathetic to Dumler-Winckler’s desire to hold together premodern inheritances with Wollstonecraft’s tradition of dissent. I think Dumler-Winckler is right that no virtues are beyond critique, and there is always the danger that virtue might become vicious or semblance may masquerade as true virtue. And yet, persons working for social change in their communities, based on their experiences and needs, I think, are at varying risk for developing such deformities. Why is it that, according to Dumler-Winckler’s Wollstonecraft, without love the oppressed is doomed to become the oppressor (155)? Dumler-Winckler aptly notes that Christian masters instilled in enslaved persons caricatures of the cardinal virtues to have them endure their condition (155). Exalting love and friendship as perfecting potentially hostile passions may not be a fitting tailoring of the dissenting garment, especially for communities living under conditions of domination and systemic oppression. The virtues required to moderate passions that have grown excessive may not be the same virtues needed to augment passions that have been woefully (and violently) diminished.

  • Emily Dumler-Winckler

    Emily Dumler-Winckler

    Reply

    Response to Jordan

    Virginia Woolf wrote, “If Jane Austen had lain as a child on the landing to prevent her father from thrashing her mother [as Wollstonecraft had done], her soul might have burnt with such a passion against tyranny that all her novels might have been consumed in one cry for justice” (178). I like this quote because I think Woolf gets it right. Austen’s sensibilities aside, beginning to end, Wollstonecraft’s work represents a resounding cry for justice and freedom from domination. 

    I find it helpful to keep this context in view while exploring Jordan’s rich set of questions: how does Wollstonecraft understand and how should we think about distinctions between and relations among passions and virtues, specifically anger, sympathy, justice, and charity, and especially among groups plagued by various forms of oppression and domination? These are some of the questions that inspired Wollstonecraft’s work and my own efforts to read her within modern traditions of dissent. I too have had the good fortune of encountering some of Jordan’s work and look forward to reading more of her important reflections on these questions and themes. 

    Jordan is rightly concerned about how ethical distinctions are parsed and deployed amid contexts of oppression, domination, and struggles for justice. These are precisely the concerns and contexts that animate Wollstonecraft’s work. In the thick of the Age of Revolution, her denunciations of the trans-Atlantic slave trade, slavery, patriarchal laws, norms, and educational systems, the enclosure of the commons, the rise of the division of labor and industrial economies, the militarization of states with standing armies, prisons, and various European polities are unequivocal; her attempt to further struggles for justice, unwavering. As a poor white woman with little formal education, Wollstonecraft experienced various forms of privilege and oppression amid these systems. Still, she draws distinctions between passions and virtues, as between true virtues and their sexed semblances, for the sake of just and liberatory ends. 

    Given these contexts and aims, it is one thing to consider why Wollstonecraft seemed to view anger and fury as passions to be perfected by virtues of charity and justice and what she made of this distinction. It’s another to say whether thinking in similar terms is useful or detrimental for those struggling under systems of domination such as “women, persons of color, and LGBTQ folks” today. It’s yet another to say why I resist thinking about a special class of “burdened virtues.” I will offer a few reflections about each. 

    Wollstonecraft’s Moral Psychology:

    Wollstonecraft was no Stoic (67, 153). She distinguishes passions from virtues. But unlike some of her Stoic contemporaries, she contends that virtue and reason often strengthen rather than moderate or temper the passions (67). I argue that Wollstonecraft’s complex moral psychology, which involves the mutual refinement and strengthening of the passions, reason, judgement, imagination, and taste, serves as an important alternative to the forms of Humean sentimentalism and Kantian reason that characterize much of modern moral philosophy and theology (66). For her, passions such as sympathy, pity, fear, anger, and love are vital for the cultivation of the virtues, which in turn refine, direct, and even strengthen these passions. 

    Wollstonecraft uses various metaphors to convey her moral psychology. Consider the sailboat. Whether acquired by experience or taught by example, virtue is cultivated when passion and reason, “perfected by reflection,” work together toward a desired end: reason guides and directs the rudder while the passions (like heat or wind) provide the necessary motivational force to arrive at the intended port (153). As the wind and heat metaphors suggests, Wollstonecraft thinks that the passions are ethically essential but ambivalent. They can be directed by virtuous or vicious habits toward better and worse ends. 

    Distinguishing Passions and Virtues…

    Still, this moral psychology does not tell us much about how or why Wollstonecraft considered particular traits such as love, anger, and sympathy to be passions, and others like justice and charity to be virtues. And these distinctions are murky at points. Take love. She often depicts love not just as a passion, but as an “arbitrary passion,” indeed “the most evanescent of all passions,” pitting love against the virtue of friendship which blends habitual affection and respect (264). Elsewhere she speaks of love in more glowing terms (265). Conversely, she uses the “charity” to refer to the virtue of loving God and others, distinguishing it sharply from common associations with a “condescending distribution of alms” (171). 

    Why distinguish the passion of “love” from the virtues that perfect it, “friendship” and “charity”? One response is that concepts like passions, virtues, and their specifications are merely tools that Wollstonecraft uses, and we may use, to make sense of our ethical experiences and observations. If one does not agree with Wollstonecraft’s distinctions or descriptions, then one can suggest that others make better sense. In this vein, Jordan wonders if passions like anger would be better described as virtues.

    …like anger:

    By the examples she provides, readers can infer that Wollstonecraft thinks of anger and fury as passions that can be shaped by virtues and vices and directed to virtuous or vicious ends. These are related but distinct matters. I’ll explain my own view and then say why I think this fits with Wollstonecraft’s examples. 

    I think that anger can be just or unjust with respect to its object, degree, and/or end. (1) As for the object, anger can be fitting or misplaced. Put simply, anger is just or righteous when it regards injustice; but it may be unjust and misplaced if it is rooted in ignorance, bigotry, a lack of awareness about one’s own privilege, or a mistaken sense of entitlement or grievance. (2) Whether fitting or misplaced, anger comes in various degrees and kinds: for example, excessive and insufficient, hot and cold, indignation and fury. A person might have either excessive or insufficient anger with respect to particular slights, offenses, or injustices. (3) But even when someone is justly angered about injustices in a degree proportionate to the injustice, a question remains about whether they will direct that anger to virtuous or vicious acts and ends. 

    Jordan asks whether my account of Wollstonecraft’s virtuous female social critic or genius who appears “quite mad” might include fury? Indeed! Maria who appears “quite mad” in the novel The Wrongs of Women is introduced in the asylum in a whirlwind of rage. For the other female social critic, Jemima, “rage gives place to despair” as she aborts a fetus conceived through rape. Well aware that rage and anger have long been seen as heroic in men and monstrous in women, Wollstonecraft had already rejected Edmund Burke’s tragi-comic rendering of the French Revolution. He depicts the villain, the women (and crossdressing men) who marched on Versailles, as a monstrous, raging, murderous Medusa or Medea manifesting “unutterable abominations of the furies of hell, in the abused shape of the vilest of women” (95-95). She humanizes these ostensible furies and thereby their fury as legitimate and justified (95). She agrees with Burke that beheading guards and parading their heads on sticks is horrific. But “What were the outrages of [this] day to… the tremendous mountain of woe that thus defaces our globe!” More affected by the downfall of queens than “the distress of many industrious mothers… and the hungry cry of helpless babes,” Burke is insufficiently outraged about the systemic injustices that plague the masses (91). Regardless of whether the marchers’ anger and fury are directed to just acts, they have a righteous object—systemic injustice, oppression, and domination. If the female social critic and genius in Wrongs appears “quite mad,” in VRM, they appear as “furies of hell.” 

    Anger as vice, virtue, or passion:

    Still, Jordan asks whether such distinctions and terms are useful or detrimental to those struggling under systems of domination then and now. What might be the advantages of thinking of passions as virtues rather than as passions to be perfected by justice or love? 

    As I understand historical and contemporary views on anger, there are three central options. First, on certain Stoic views, like those found in Martha Nussbaum’s book Anger and Forgiveness, anger is a vice. For reasons I discuss elsewhere, I disagree with this view. Second, for others, anger is a virtue or something akin to a virtue, always good, or particularly so in contexts of systemic oppression and domination. Brittany Cooper’s Eloquent Rage, which I cite, might appear to share this view (190). But following Audre Lorde’s classic essay “The Uses of Anger: Women Responding to Racism,” Cooper also views anger as a “legitimate political emotion…. ‘Focused with precision, it can become a powerful source of energy serving progress and change.’”1 Both black feminists seem to fit better with the third option, with those like Aristotle, Aquinas, Wollstonecraft, and Martin Luther King Jr., for whom anger is something like a passion or emotion, a powerful source of energy that contains great promises, liabilities, and limitations for flourishing, justice, organizing work, and struggles for liberation. 

    To be clear, I think that one could theorize anger as a virtue. Here’s how I would do so. As a virtue, anger is the good habit of being angry about the right things (injustice, slights, oppression, domination), or toward the right persons, in the right ways and degrees, at the right times, to achieve just ends. I can imagine vicious extremes on either side of this virtuous mean. Anger could be vicious on one extreme through a misplaced object or excess in degree or expression. Think of “Karens” or January 6th MAGAs. On the other extreme, we would ascribe a deficit of anger to those who should be angry, or more angered, about injustices. Think of Burke, Martin Luther King Jr.’s “white moderate” or to those who acquiesce under systems of domination (107, 110). 

    The practical and moral upshot of considering passions like anger as virtues might be to thoroughly undermine Stoic tendencies by affirming that these emotions and expressions are ethical and practical goods for agents. For those who suffer under intersecting forms of oppression it is perfectly just or right to experience and express anger, rage, and fury about injustice. As Cooper puts it, “Black women have the right to be mad as hell” (5). Considering anger as a virtue might be one way to affirm their righteous anger, fuel struggles for justice, and diminish acquiescence with oppressive systems. Theorizing anger as a virtue rather than a more evanescent passion may be particularly fitting given community organizers’ insights about the role of habitual or “cold anger” in struggles for justice. 

    I wonder, however, whether considering passions as virtues is a double-edged sword. Would Jordan want to affirm anger as a virtue for everyone or just for some? Is it best to get rid of the distinction between passions and virtues altogether, as Jordan queries? If so, is fear a virtue? For everyone? Even those with their backs against the wall? 

    Burdened Virtues:

    For many reasons, some of which I discuss in the book, I do not find it helpful to delineate a special class of “burdened virtues” as Lisa Tessman has done (10–11, 101, 170, 252, 274–75). I suggest that Wollstonecraft serves as a precursor for Tessman’s fitting lament, anger, and grief at the ethical burdens endured by those who resist systems of domination (10–11). But I think that we can, and Wollstonecraft did, better account for virtues and burdens amid intersectional injustices by understanding virtues as human dispositions (rather than a dispositions for a particular subset of humanity) and then attending to the complex socio-political contexts, roles, systems, and relations of agents in all their intersectionality. 

    Tessman describes the “burdened virtues” as a distinct set of virtues for a distinct set of people, namely the oppressed. But her own account seems to resist this classification where she admits the complexity and intersectionality of various forms of oppression, power, and privilege. Wollstonecraft seems more attuned to these intersections in her own time, as when she criticizes white women oppressed by patriarchal systems who, having unjustly gained some measure of power, use it to tyrannize over others (110, 139, 221). She rejects distinctly sexed lists of the virtues, which give women all of the “submissive charms” (156). But rather than delineating a new or distinct set of virtues for women as an oppressed class or for the oppressed broadly, as if either is uniform, she suggests that all people and groups cultivate human virtues, like justice, with respect to their particular socio-political position, contexts, systems, roles, and relations (170). Will those struggling under various forms of oppression bear additional burdens? Absolutely. But if such virtues are necessary for survival and for resisting domination then the alternative is likely to be just as costly and burdensome.

    In the end, I find it useful to think of anger as a complex passion that can be formed and directed by virtues and vices for just and unjust objects, degrees, and ends. Considering anger as a passion that can be used for liberatory or oppressive purposes provides feminists and womanists with a critical foothold to affirm the former and denounce the latter. On this view, the relation between anger and virtues of love and justice is complex. I think that just or righteous anger is rooted in love, in the perceived threat or reality of injustice to things and people one loves, and aimed at justice. 

    The only themes more prominent than justice and rights in Wollstonecraft’s work may be love and friendship (239). Her criticisms of forbearance and treatment of love and charity demonstrate that she is keenly attentive to their dangers, especially for those ensnared by systems of oppression (79, 154–56, 230–32). Forbearance is a semblance of virtue, she insists, in contexts of domination and dependence where it leads one to “silently endure injuries; smiling under the lash at which it dare not snarl” (154). Her criticism resonates, I suggest, with Shawn Copeland’s keen censure of the “Christianity of the plantation [which] sought to bind the slaves to their condition by inculcating caricatures of the cardinal virtues of patience, long-suffering, forbearance, love, faith, and hope” (155). In Wollstonecraft’s terms: “when forbearance confounds right and wrong, it ceases to be a virtue” (155–56). 

    Chapter five elaborates other dangers and prospects that attend love and rage in contexts of domination. The friendships of Thelma and Louise as well as Maria and Jemima provide fodder to further explore these themes (273–79). All four women are plagued by systemic and relational forms of patriarchal and misogynistic injustice. Both friendships are fashioned in the morass of crushing and violent patriarchy. Each woman becomes an outlaw by breaking gendered norms and legal codes. I hope to continue the conversation with Jordan about these examples and the supposed “furies of hell,” or some of her own. 


    1. Brittney Cooper, Eloquent Rage: A Black Feminist Discovers Her Superpower, Reprint edition (Picador, 2019), 5.

Madeline Cronin

Response

Everyone’s a Critic

Democratized Taste and Judgement in Emily Dumler-Winckler’s Modern Virtue

To a contemporary audience, Mary Wollstonecraft can come off as—what I can only describe as—judgey. If we define judgey as a readiness to share one’s judgment about what is right or fitting in a given situation, then yes, Wollstonecraft is judgey. She puts forth a robust account of moral virtue and offers specific examples of what these virtues might look like. She is not a fan of pajamas at the breakfast table (preferring a person come to the table indicating their readiness to meet the challenges of the day); she strongly favors breast feeding over the exploitations of wet nursing. Furthermore, she often relies on a sharp sense of humor to castigate ladies who appear to have internalized what we would call sexist notions of femininity. As a scholar and teacher, I have often wondered why I’m not more bothered by my disagreement with certain practical recommendations that Wollstonecraft makes. If I find her account of virtue to have so many merits, why can I dismiss the practical applications with which I disagree? Am I simply utilizing the historically situated assumptions of my own epoch to reject the parts of Wollstonecraft which my own society cannot accept? What is my method of extraction? These are just a narrow sub-set of questions to which Emily Dumler-Winckler’s Modern Virtue offers promising answers. This substantial volume does significant work to evidence not only what Wollstonecraft says, but also how Wollstonecraft’s own method of proceeding answers readers’ suspicions about the limits of her moral exemplars. Her practical examples are not intended to be dogma in a Wollstonecraftian program, so much as invitations to critical consideration and to revision of these models—especially over time. In other words, Wollstonecraft shows us how to critically engage her own examples. She does not suggest that hers “will be our examples, nor that any given set of exemplars could identify once and for all the standards of refined taste” (71) or virtues in practice. If we define judginess as a lack of humility or openness to alternative views—then Wollstonecraft is not so judgey after all. Furthermore, in our own moment, plagued as we are by our own culture wars and the readiness to judgment that they bring, such an account of judgment is incredibly welcome. 

This notion of Wollstonecraftian judgment as well as the broader argument of Modern Virtue has substantial implications for a variety of concerns and audiences. In addition to being the first sustained treatment of Wollstonecraft in theology, Dumler-Winckler speaks directly to current debates about virtue and virtue theory in a quite compelling way. The book is presented as “an alternative to two influential and competing narratives about the virtues in modernity”—virtues’ overzealous defenders and virtues’ despisers (6). The overzealous defenders treat modernity as a story about the demise of the conditions for the practice of virtue (Alasdair MacIntyre and Brad Gregory to name a few). Virtues’ despisers worry that virtue theory tends toward a rejection of modern pluralism and presents standards that “tend to naturalize the contingent, deny the disputable, and conceal prejudices that should be abandoned” (9). Here Dumler-Winckler looks especially closely at Judith Butler’s 2000 lecture, “What is Critique? An Essay on Foucault’s Virtue.” In response to such poles, Modern Virtue quite convincingly points out a Wollstonecraftian via negativa out of such divisions. For instance, like virtues defenders, Wollstonecraft is interested in elaborating moral exemplars and in existing traditions that might be drawn from to do so. However, her notion of refinement renders these moral exemplars less immutable pillars and more invitations to critical engagement.1 These models specifically call on a person to exercise their own judgment—to assess, revise, and embody the virtues in new contexts. Indeed, one of her primary concerns about the status of women in her society is the way in which they have been encouraged to merely ape the behaviors of elites, rather than to engage their own judgment in examining the exemplars they are given. To this end Dumler-Winckler offers a quite compelling and original interpretation of Wollstonecraft’s pedagogical writings—especially as they illuminate the frontispiece to Wollstonecraft’s Original Stories by William Blake. She is, to my knowledge, the first to recognize the illuminating parallels between this illustration of Wollstonecraft’s call to independent judgment, her notion of the imitatio Christi, and Blake’s “The Crucifixion: ‘Behold Thy Mother’” (147). 

One of the ways that Modern Virtue evidences this more pluralistic theory of judgement is through a consideration of Wollstonecraft’s contributions to eighteenth-century debates about a so-called standard of taste. Much like contemporary readers navigating a public discourse in which one person’s noble protestor is another person’s vicious rioter, eighteenth-century disputes tended to focus on how disagreements of taste might be resolved. Like Hume and Burke, Wollstonecraft concludes there is a firm distinction between true and false taste, between qualified and unqualified judges. However, she emphasizes the ways that an oppressive society fails to recognize those most qualified to judge. Furthermore, Wollstonecraft resists an overly foundationalist account of what a “standard of taste” might entail. This is one of the places that Dumler-Winckler’s emphasis on Wollstonecraft’s theology proves especially helpful. For instance, she underscores that when Wollstonecraft refers to God’s attributes as a standard, she is doing so within a dissenting tradition and consequently an understanding of the many ways that these attributes are disputed and disputable.2 Citing Wollstonecraft’s “repeated insistence that ‘the High and Lofty One…doubtless possesses many attributes of which we can form no conception’” (42), Modern Virtue makes a convincing case that, for Wollstonecraft, principles derived from God’s nature are “a matter of good religious taste, not an indisputable foundation” (42).

Though Wollstonecraft offers potential orientations that might aid us in refining taste—orientations toward God, nature, and simplicity—Modern Virtue emphasizes that these are starting points rather than rigid standards.3 When Wollstonecraft appeals to “the immutable attributes of God” as a “standard” for moral development she is not presenting these principles as “given in advance of dispute or ethical inquiry” (41). Instead, these are invitations to judgement and hence to dispute. Wollstonecraft’s frequent references to God’s nature have led many to see her as having “precisely the sort of naturalized and universalized standards that many contemporary feminists and gender theorists find troubling” (60). However, Dumler-Winckler illustrates that this appeal is not quite so universal by emphasizing the distinction between first and second nature as Wollstonecraft would have understood them. First nature—something that is a given—and second nature—something that is acquired. In an Aristotelian sense—we are born with certain inclinations and capacities—a certain telos. However, the attainment of a virtue is importantly a matter of second nature—a matter of the habits that support living out and practicing certain virtues of which we are capable.4 Such a reading supports a more pluralistic and less Kantian reading of Wollstonecraftian principles. The ramifications of this more open-ended Wollstonecraft are apparent if we return to the initial question of “judginess.” When Wollstonecraft puts forth an example of a virtue, like modesty, she is not claiming to know for certain that the exterior garments a person wears are (or are not) an indication of true modesty. She is not “judgey” in this way. On the contrary, “she views modesty as a virtue like any other that can be cultivated through a variety of bodily and social practices” (174). Furthermore, this notion of virtue is bolstered by her theology. “All human beings are invited to grow in the image and likeness of God (VRW 104), yet we each do so in our own particular way” (170). In a deep sense, I cannot know a person’s virtue—or whether their self-presentation is the result of true taste or judgment simply by looking at them. Furthermore, attempts to do so are likely to be foiled by the many semblances of virtue. For instance, Wollstonecraft worries about the “priestly collar” (174), religious garb more broadly, and other uniforms that can hide a myriad of vices.

Modern Virtue is compelling both as interpretation of Wollstonecraft and as an effort to present a better story about virtues in modernity. It is, therefore, as a reader quite convinced by Dumler-Winckler’s arguments, that I point toward some added considerations. I wonder whether, in addition to Judith Butler, the voice of a contemporary feminist and queer theorist like Sara Ahmed, might illuminate some nuanced concerns about modern virtue? Take for instance worries about an over-reliance on mere habits. Dumler-Winckler suggests that “Wollstonecraft has other anxieties, …but habit and habituation are not among them” (130). This might overstate the case, given the extent to which Wollstonecraft worries about a historical pattern of educating women into the mimicry devoid of either reason or sentiment. She is, to my mind, quite concerned about mere habituation. Nevertheless, Wollstonecraft does lack certain anxieties about habituation that contemporary authors might better draw out. For example, the queer phenomenology of Sara Ahmed is attentive to the ways in which existing habits—more broadly the ways we are already situated—absorb what is different, distinct, what she refers to as “slanted” in the sense of what does not conform to—for instance—heteronormative binaries.5 In this sense, existing structures and narratives often swallow new critical revisions, silencing by co-opting such distinct presences.6 For example, Ahmed points out the way in which norms operate to push the jagged edges of queer family into a framework that can be understood—and so elided into existing “family lines.”7 For this reason, Ahmed’s framework suggests that a Wollstonecraftian call to revise tradition likely necessitates a more vigorous “call to disorientation” if it is to succeed.8

In the last lines of Modern Virtue, Dumler-Winckler appreciates challenges implied by Wollstonecraftian pluralism. She suggests that taking up Wollstonecraft’s call will require carrying the pieces of our history “whole and shattered” and to “feel their weight” (Sabrina Orah Mark as cited on 326). As an added challenge, Ahmed underscores what is required to ensure that we do actually feel the weight—specifically of the shattered pieces. To use the guiding metaphor of the book, Ahmed helps us to consider in what ways our existing garb—the inherited garb of the moral imagination—resists our attempts at editing. In what ways might this inheritance be creating path-dependencies that make it very difficult for us even to see the “slant” as a slant, as a possible existence, or way of living? How will a new revision of a tradition be reduced to a prior fashion, a return of the same? Wollstonecraft can’t offer us the certainty we might crave, but as a starting point she does appreciate the double-edged quality of the aesthetic, moral, and social formation she is proposing. “Habits, she understands, can be deliberate or thoughtless, virtuous or vicious” (130). Vigilance to these dual possibilities is vital as, more often, it is the original and the jagged adaptations of the wardrobe that get watered down. Ahmed therefore offers a helpful qualifier; be sure to seek out the rough edges and to weigh more heavily the shattered parts. 


  1. One especially strong piece of textual evidence that Dumler-Winckler brings out includes her argument in Original Stories, that “[t]o attain anything great, a model must be held up to exercise our understanding, and engage our affections.”(as cited on 133) Also, from her travel writings: “The best use of travel literature, Wollstonecraft reflects, ‘would be to promote inquiry and discussion, instead of making those dogmatical assertions which only appear calculated to gird the human mind round with imaginary circles, like the paper globe which represents the one he inhabits.’”(Letters Written in Sweden, Norway, and Denmark, 266 was cited on 78).

  2. For instance, Dumler-Winckler points out that Wollstonecraft sides with Catherine Macaulay in the intellectualist as opposed to voluntarist position. (Modern Virtue, 42).

  3. For a detailed consideration of nature and simplicity as components of Wollstonecraftian true taste see: Ahmed Cronin, Madeline. “Mary Wollstonecraft’s Conception of ‘True Taste’ and Its Role in Egalitarian Education and Citizenship.” European Journal of Political Theory 18, no. 4 (October 1, 2019): 508–28.

  4. Wollstonecraft’s uses of the word nature are many and varied. In addition to appeals to first and second nature, Wollstonecraft often describes exposure to the natural world as a resource that might aid a person in correcting social prejudices. Dumler-Winckler gives one especially compelling piece of evidence that Wollstonecraft sometimes means second nature; in Vindication of the Rights of Woman, when discussing the natural affections, Wollstonecraft refers to “natural (habitual is the proper word) affection” (63). Acquired, second nature, habits are a resource with which to correct vicious social patterns. However, experience of the natural world, devoid of socially informed cultivation, are also needed as part of sound judgement. For example, in “On Poetry,” she worries: “a taste for rural scenes, in the present state of society, appears to be very often an artificial sentiment, rather inspired by poetry and romances, than a real perception of the beauties of nature” (7). In some cases cultivating judgment requires access to society and education, and in other cases it requires a respite from society, especially in nature. In this sense, Wollstonecraft deals in both positive and negative education. For further discussion of the role of nature in Wollstonecraftian “true taste” see: Ahmed Cronin, “Mary Wollstonecraft’s Conception of ‘True Taste,’ 518.

  5. Sara Ahmed, “Orientations: Toward a Queer Phenomenology.” GLQ: A Journal of Lesbian and Gay Studies 12, no. 4 (2006): 543–74.

  6. In one especially striking example she describes walking into her home, where she lives with her female partner, and having a neighbor suddenly demand, “[i]s that your sister, or your husband?” (562). At bottom, Ahmed points out how this comment reflects an inability to deal with a family of two women—either pushing the female partner into the role sister, into a male partner, or perhaps into a sufficiently male presenting female.

  7. Ahmed, 557.

  8. Ahmed, 565.

  • Emily Dumler-Winckler

    Emily Dumler-Winckler

    Reply

    Response to Madeline Cronin

    As with the other responses in this forum, Cronin’s response to the book is generous, thoughtful, and delightful. Wollstonecraft is judgey! Cronin perfectly describes a tension that I have also felt reading and teaching Wollstonecraft as a woman at once of and critically beyond her time. I do not take for granted the gift of such a careful and charitable reader and interlocutor. I’m grateful. 

    Cronin seems to agree with much of the book but thinks that I may overstate the case that Wollstonecraft is not anxious about habits or habituation. In her view, the feminist is quite concerned about mere habituation. From post-structuralists like Butler and hyper-Augustinians to psychologists and social scientists, many scholars today have anxieties about habits and habituation (129–30). Habits have been associated with unthinking, uncritical, rote, inauthentic, and imitative patterns of behavior or with static and fixed traits of character. By “mere habituation,” I suspect that Cronin reflects similar anxieties. 

    I think that Wollstonecraft is not anxious about habits or habituation because, for her, these concepts do not carry these negative assumptions or associations. Habits can be better and worse, virtuous or vicious, critical or unthinking, revolutionary or rote: none more basic or “mere” than the others (130). And there’s no alternative. For better and for worse, we’re habitual or habitually performative creatures (140). She does think that habits have a cumulative effect, becoming more ingrained in our ways of thinking, feeling, and acting over time. For this reason, early attention to their formative role is vital (130). If better and worse habits become hard to break, all the more reason to cultivate better habits early. 

    In the book, I argue that radical social criticism or dissent is rooted in and refined by habits of critical judgement and liberatory practice (125, 128–32). Habits and criticism are not, as many suspect, necessarily at odds. And just criticism is necessarily rooted in habits.

    In other words, the sort of radical social criticism that profoundly concerns Judith Butler and Sarah Ahmed, and this feminist dissenter—the sort that could however gradually revolutionize and not merely revise or reform the status quo or socio-political norms—is rooted in and refined by deeply ingrained habits of critical judgement, reflection, and imagination that empower what Ashon Crawley calls “‘otherwise possibilities’” (318). 

    There are two points that I would like to draw out. This view of habituation—as at once a necessary, shared aspect of our humanity and potentially either conventional or non-conventional, homogenizing or radical, conservative or revolutionary—lends itself to certain post-structuralist insights that Butler and Ahmed, as I read them, share in common, even while it challenges others. 

    First, the challenge. Unlike Butler and perhaps Ahmed in their more post-structuralist moments, Wollstonecraft does not think that all norms, including language and habits, participate in normative regimes that are inherently illegitimate or violent. Butler’s description of virtue as disobedience to one’s formation, which requires that we “break the habits of judgment” and risk “the field of reason itself” threatens to undermine their insight in the same essay that subjectivity is always at once formed and forming, making it difficult to draw a line between the two (128–29). The latter insight, which Wollstonecraft’s view of habit affirms, challenges the former claim that virtue requires breaking rather than using and refining habits of critical judgement. There is no unformed point from which to purely disobey, no unformed former. 

    If a self is formed by habits of critical judgment then virtue entails devotion rather than disobedience to this critical practice. Reducing virtue to critique or disobedience conceals the legitimate habits and principles of formation by which one rightly disobeys the illegitimate.

    Wollstonecraft, rather, describes the cultivation of virtue as a formation in critical judgments that foster resistance to unjust laws, illegitimate authorities, and relations of domination, as well as self-conscious adherence to just authorities and norms, and the ability to distinguish the two (129).

    Second, the similarity. I read Butler and Ahmed as sharing similar phenomenological and post-structuralist affinities. I engage Butler’s essays on virtue and critique in greater depth than Ahmed’s works such as The Promise of Happiness (2010) and Living a Feminist Life (2017) (123–29, 150-157 and 33, 154, 254). Butler and Ahmed, as I read them, are both concerned about the ways that norms such as heteronormative binaries tend to co-opt, silence, occlude, or render illegible what is different, distinct, or other, even and especially performative ways of playing with or resisting those norms. Ahmed’s neighbor’s question about her lesbian partner is a vivid example: “Is that your sister, or your husband?”1

    Wollstonecraft shares similar concerns and her view of habit, traditions, dissent, and revolution lends similar conclusions. There’s no outside. We can only work with or struggle against the norms, traditions, discourses, institutions, and polities that we inherit. Insofar, as persons and groups try to radically discard, tailor, revolutionize, and queer the shared “wardrobe of a moral imagination” it will always be in response to inherited norms and standards that will indeed resist such efforts. Co-option and failures of recognition are inevitable. 

    For Ahmed’s neighbor, her lesbian partner was simply illegible, unrecognizable according to their heteronormative lens. Thus, the effort to assimilate. The book is full of similar examples. Wollstonecraft’s gothic novel, The Wrongs of Women, concludes with a courtroom scene that exemplifies a similar failure of recognition (36, 74–77). The only person qualified to judge about the case is not the jurors, lawyers, or official judge, but rather the novel’s heroine, Maria, a recent detainee of an insane asylum. According to the legal and social norms of her time, the one person qualified to judge the injustice of marital laws is neither recognized as such nor authorized to do so. In the patriarchal lens of the jurors and judge, this social critic, especially because she’s a woman, can only appear mad. Likewise, in Edmund Burke’s lens, the women marching on Versailles can only appear as a “swinish multitude,” as monstrous “furies of hell in the abused shape of the vilest of women” (94–95).    

    Does Ahmed’s framework necessitate a more vigorous “call to disorientation” than Wollstonecraft’s account of virtuous dissent, social criticism, and revolutionary practice provide? Because of our own lenses, I suspect, talk of habits and habituation sound conventional rather than radical, orienting rather than disorienting. Nonetheless, I argue that Wollstonecraft’s dissenting clarion call for a “revolution in female manners,” a denial of “sexual virtues,” women’s rights as human rights, and social criticism constitutes a thoroughly vigorous “call to disorientation” (121, 159, 240). Wollstonecraft’s dissenting call was in fact disorienting to many, perhaps most, in her time. Her own illegibility as a female social critic is illuminated by Horace Walpole’s vivid depiction. To him, she could only appear as a monstrous “philosophizing serpent” or “hyena in petticoats.” 


    1. Sara Ahmed, “Orientations: Toward a Queer Phenomenology,” GLQ: A Journal of Lesbian and Gay Studies 12, no. 4 (2006): 562.

Shares
Verified by ExactMetrics