Symposium Introduction

The title of Mary-Jane Rubenstein’s newest book is both enlightening and baroque and is worth reproducing in full:

Worlds without end: the many lives of the multiverse…in which are discussed pre-, early-, and postmodern multiple-worlds cosmologies; the sundry arguments for and against them; the striking peculiarities of their adherents and detractors; the shifting boundaries of science, philosophy and religion; and the stubbornly persistent question of whether creation has been “designed.”

Such is this impressive and graceful book in nuce, and so let us use the full title to crack this book open.

The lives of the multiverse. As Rubenstein notes in her Introduction, the multiverse, a term coined by William James, has become mainstream. To cite only a few examples, the multiverse has been depicted in television shows such as Community and Family Guy, presented in popular science books like Brian Greene’s The Hidden Reality or Michio Kaku’s Parallel Worlds, and even used a backdrop as in Neil Gaiman and Michael Reaves’ Young Adult trilogy InterWorld. One may have even run across the meme of the ‘Darkest Timeline’, or suspect that one is currently within it. Yet long before twentieth-century cosmology, quantum mechanics, or string theory all came to propose in their own ways different multiverses, and even longer before its adaptations in entertainment, the provocative and startling idea of multiple or parallel universes has had a long pedigree.

The pre-, early-, and postmodern multiple-world cosmologies. Most of Rubenstein’s book is dedicated to tracing the proposals of (and reactions to) the multiverse, or a multiple-world cosmology, within western cosmology, philosophy, and theology, and Rubenstein shows herself to be an able and agreeable guide. The reader is led through the kosmoi of Plato’s Timaeus, Aristotle’s de caelo and Metaphysics, the ancient Atomists, the Stoics, and Augustine and Origen make brief appearances as well (Chapter 1). We read about Thomas Aquinas’ cosmology and the stunning and radical cosmotheological visions of Nicholas of Cusa and Giordano Bruno (Chapter 3). Despite the premature demise of the wayward Dominican Bruno, the seventeenth century witnessed a blossoming of interest in other worlds which was somewhat tempered by Kepler, Descartes, and Newton. Nevertheless even Newton’s more occasional and wilder suggestions and the early Kant’s Universal Natural History and Theory of the Heavens continued upon and expanded theorization/speculation regarding the multiverse (Chapter 4). We then leap into the twentieth century and the various reincarnations of the multiverse meditated to us through inflation and string theory run amok and through different cyclical models of the birth and demise of universes (Chapter 5). This bewildering carnival of multiverses is then ended with descriptions of quantum multiverses (provided by both the Copenhagen and Many-Worlds Interpretations of quantum mechanics), black holes, manufactured and virtual multiverses, and Max Tegmark’s impossibly daring ‘Mathematical Universe Hypothesis’. The reader can easily stagger not only before the cosmological speculations being offered, but also before the sheer time, effort, and erudition necessary on behalf of this book’s author to present so capably these speculations.

The sundry arguments for and against them; the striking peculiarities of their adherents and detractors. Why a multiverse? Why not? The arguments for and against the different multiverses come from every which way. The arguments, both for and against, run the gamut from the scientific (the empirical, deductive, and speculative), to the aesthetic, to the theological, and even to the existential. It is as fascinating to witness the entirely sympathetic reactions of some physicists to the more bewildering and admittedly terrifying implications of twentieth-century cosmology as it is to watch some others definitively rule out the existence of any creator. These brief reports of and looks into the responses, intuitions, and agendas behind the arguments for and against interject a refreshingly human element into the multiverse controversies.

The shifting boundaries of science, philosophy, and religion. That the boundaries between the scientific, philosophical, and religious are porous is clear throughout the book, but nowhere clearer than in ‘Unendings’, the book’s final chapter. Here we meet the likes of Christoph Cardinal Schönborn, who opposes the multiverse hypothesis not directly on behalf of God, but on behalf of reason (and here the Cardinal could potentially invoke some physicists as allies) and Dietrich Bonhoeffer, whose God not of the gaps of our knowledge but of the center of our quotidian lives seems to resonate with Rubenstein. We are also given Friedrich Nietzche’s remarks on ‘the scientists’ from On the Genealogy of Moral, that third and last class of ascetics still within the thrall of Hume’s ‘monkish virtues’. Rubenstein nicely sums up these shifting boundaries when noting, ‘every multiverse hypothesis opens in one way or another onto uncannily metaphysical—even theological—terrain. Each scenario requires us to assent to worlds, gods, or generative principles that remain, in the words of an old English hymn, “in light inaccessible hid from our eyes”’ (220).

The stubbornly persistent question of whether the creation has been “designed”. The perennial question of universe, now multiverse’s ‘design’ also surfaces at various points throughout the book. Alongside the reflections on Hume, Kant, Paley, there is also discussion of what folk think is to be done about the staggering degree of our universe’s ‘fine-tuning’ and the anthropic principle (in both its Weak and Strong versions), which is arguably design come-of-age.

Worlds without end. What, then, of the phrase which begins the book’s title? Is this play on a doxology merely playful?1 Is it an amused rejoinder to the hymn or a spontaneous participation in awe before the starry skies above us? To whom or to what, for Rubenstein, might sung a hymn be sung?

As this all too brief reading of the book’s full title makes clear, Rubenstein’s has offered us much and much to learn and discuss. Nancy Frankenberry begins our symposium by boldly tackling the problem of fine-tuning, while Noreen Khawaja asks questions regarding the modern and recent shifts within science and between science and religion detailed in the book. Graham Ward considers the ‘scientific imagination’, and its subject, at work in these breathtaking cosmological discoveries and speculations. Oliver Davies returns to the question of the boundaries of science and religion and wonders what resources allowed medieval theologians to anticipate such a lively and enthralling cosmos. Ted Peters directly addresses the question of God in conversations about the multiverse, and ends by noting that more important than knowing whether God exists, is knowing whether God is a gracious God. A hearty thanks to Mary-Jane Rubenstein for writing such a wonderful book, for her participation, and to our panelists for their thoughtful contributions.


  1. While ‘world without end’ is perhaps most famous as the final phrase of the Gloria Patri as rendered in Thomas Cranmer’s Book of Common Prayer, it also appeared in the slightly translation of Ephesians 3:21 given in “Cranmer’s Bible”, the Great Bible, although the phrase has been documented as early as the start of fourteenth century.

Avatar

Response

All the Light We Cannot See

COINCIDENTALLY, MARY-JANE RUBENSTEIN’S Worlds Without End: The Many Lives of the Multiverse came to me at the same time I was reading Marcelo Gleiser’s latest book, The Island of Knowledge: The Limits of Science and the Search for Meaning. Cross-reading both together crystallized a question that has long haunted me. How should we non-theists account for the way the universe looks disturbingly “fine-tuned” (an already loaded label) for life? Rubenstein and Gleiser offer engaging, overlapping perspectives on this question, which I shall develop in my own way in this brief commentary.

One of the pleasures of reading Rubenstein’s brilliant, buoyant, and unsettling book is the underlying irony, to which she is ever-alert, of scientific cosmology’s flight from God and into the arms of the multiverse theory, a hypothesis no less speculative, unproven, and untestable than that of a Designer-God who determined the fundamental physical constants that make our corner of the cosmos unusually hospitable to conscious life. In Rubenstein’s recounting of recent scientific developments, it is chiefly dark matter, inflationary cosmology, and string theory that have conspired to make the multiverse hypothesis more and more plausible in the last decade, at the same time providing a way out of the fine-tuning problem without invoking a theistic explanation. For if there are vast numbers of other universes, perhaps an infinite number, all with different properties, odds are that at least one of them will have the right combination of conditions to bring forth stars, planets, and living things. As cosmologist Bernard Carr put it: “If you don’t want God, you’d better have a multiverse.”1

Astrophysicist Marcelo Gleiser, friend and colleague, is as agnostic as I about Ultimate Concerns, but also awed by the human impulse to shine a bit more light ahead of us, and by the beauty of the universe’s striking harmony and order. With the image of an Island of Knowledge, he depicts the shores of ignorance expanding as the island of our knowledge grows. The ocean of the unknown feeds on the successes of science. In particular, two fundamental kinds of limits to knowledge constrain our epistemological quests, according to Gleiser. First, science is increasingly tool driven, but the telescopes, the cosmic microwave background measurements, the mathematically calibrated tools used in cosmology are always imprecise; and second, nature itself works in ways that impose insurmountable barriers on what we can know—bounded as we are by the speed of light, by time’s arrow, and by an irrevocable randomness.

Juxtaposing Gleiser’s island-image with Rubenstein’s quilted multiverse, inflationary multiverse, landscape multiverse, and so forth, produces a dizzying effect. Our eyes see less than half of the total light that the Sun sends our way; to extend our limited vision, we use scientific tools and we propose theoretical models, some highly speculative, like the multiverse. The instruments have only a finite reach and the theoretical models frequently boil off like so many gases leaking into the imaginary. The more we see, the more we know there is to see. The “more” that we cannot see is far, far in the past. As every school child knows, when we look out into space, we are looking back at the past, collecting light that left its source millions, even billions, of years ago. Information from any object or region of the cosmos takes time to reach us, and there is an upper limit to that. Both the 13.8 billion year age of the universe and the speed of light impose a horizon, beyond which it is impossible to receive signals. If further and further expansion is indeed the trending fate of the universe and space continues to stretch, galaxies we now see may be carried away from us, like raisins on an expanding dough. A new cosmic horizon would swim into place, beyond which the light of those lost galaxies will no longer reach us.

I find this astonishing, humbling, and slightly frightening. Could there be some truths known to us that will not be knowable to our distant descendants, not because all records will be erased, but because unrepeatable, random cosmic conditions will not recur? Keep in mind the fact that 95 percent of the cosmos is filled with dark matter and dark energy. Here is an even more mind-boggling thought: all the light we cannot see is far more vast than the tiny 5 percent that is the very stuff of which we are made.

The multiverse hypothesis, however, brings us to an entirely different order of magnitude in the mind-boggling department. It is, in principle, permanently beyond the scope of human knowledge. Never is a hard word in science, as Gleiser says, but “even if convincing observational signatures of neighboring universes could be found within our cosmic horizon, they would not confirm the existence of the multiverse.” Some physicists might, in detecting the existence of another universe, find it natural to generalize to the existence of the multiverse, but Gleiser stresses that “the data would not support this conceptual jump. Two or three neighboring homes don’t make a country. The existence of a multiverse, even if not of infinite extent, is an unknowable.”2 And this is precisely Rubenstein’s point—to show that every multiverse hypothesis opens onto metaphysical, even theological, terrain. “Each scenario,” she says, “requires us to assent to worlds, gods, or generative principles that remain, in the words of the old English hymn, ‘in light inaccessible hid from our eyes.’”3

Returning to the question about the improbable constants of nature, such as the strength of the gravitational force or the mass of the electron, it is hard to shake the idea that we do indeed live in a Goldilocks universe, as physicist Paul Davies put it, not too cold, not too warm, where the physical constants seem perfectly and improbably aligned. If our universe had more than four dimensions, atoms would not stick together. If the relative strength of gravity were greater than it is, it would rip matter apart. In the past, I have contended that the Why-question remains irresistible, but that the range of possible answers leaves something to be desired in each case. I have hesitated to come down in favor of any one answer before, and with most metaphysical or theological arguments, I have been more interested in framing a logically exhaustive matrix of positions, eliminating one by one any that do not withstand critical scrutiny, seeing what, if anything, is left. It is hard to improve on the advice of Sherlock Holmes that, when you have eliminated the impossible, whatever remains, however improbable, must be the truth. Here, however, I want to side with the fourth position below, even though in this space I am barely able to adumbrate the reasons why I believe this little-discussed option is correct.

As far as I can see, there are four positions one may take on the matter of fine-tuning. (1) The fine-tuning is exquisitely improbable, an improbability that can only be explained by God. (2) The fine-tuning is exquisitely improbable, an improbability that can be best explained if ours is only one of many actually existing universes in a multiverse. (3) The fine-tuning may be exquisitely improbable, but it is the sort of improbability that requires no explanation. Because we are here it is inevitable that the constants and conditions would be right for us. (4) Probabilities cannot properly be applied to the values of the fundamental constants and initial conditions.

The fourth position, if correct, rules out both the first and the second, eliminating the need for either a Fine-Tuner or a Multiverse. That leaves the third position as the chief contender to the fourth. Why do its proponents say that no positive probability, however low, for the constants and initial conditions essential to human life is surprising or in need of explanation? The reason is the famous “anthropic principle.” Correctly stated, this principle asserts that nothing that is essential to our existence should be surprising, unless of truly zero probability. Because we are the very ones looking, we are bound to look out at a universe with conditions that permit our existence. Now, I realize that the proper and improper applications of this intriguing principle are much debated. What is wrong with it? In my view, the semi-agnosticism of this position is right to a certain extent, but only so far. It is right that an event or circumstance with ultra-low probability does not, by itself, need a special explanation. And it is right that the fact that a circumstance is necessary to our existence should not, by itself, be seen as promoting it to a status that requires such special explanation. The question that the anthropic principle leaves unsettled is when other features of an improbable circumstance are such that we should want to dig deeper. If we concluded, for example, that the conditions for production of carbon existed only in stars located within one hundred light years of Earth, that would beg for explanation. This question of what requires an explanation beyond the anthropic principle is confounding and confusing.

As Rubenstein knows, the problem with the anthropic principle in its weak form (WAP) is that it can only assert the truism that “the world as we observe it must be consistent with our existence, insofar as we are observing it,” and in its strong form (SAP) not only invites theism in the front door but seats it at the head of the table. The multiverse hypothesis makes the weak form seem less anemic, for it proclaims that our precisely calibrated universe is neither wildly improbable nor divinely produced, but rather to be expected as one out of many, given an infinity of space, time, and material. Some proponents of position 1 seek to downplay the success of the multiverse hypothesis as physics by pushing back the claims of “fine tuning” to the conditions necessary for an inflationary Bang to get started in the first place. However, this strikes me as nothing more than dressing up the traditional cosmological, or “first cause,” argument in teleological costume.

I conclude that the fine-tuning argument fails as an argument for theism because its key “low probability” premise is technically unsupportable. Moreover, even were the argument to establish low probability, it would founder on the anthropic principle unless it could establish that the fact that we are here is not enough to eliminate any need for further explanation of the “tunings.” Finally, the fine-tuning argument would have to show that the fact that ours is only one of many actual universes is not enough to explain any improbability of our universe’s having the values that it does. All this leaves fine-tuning as a justification for theism in pretty bad shape. Although skeptical about position 1 above, I urge caution at each of the other steps. We can’t entirely rule out the possibility that someone will come up with something better than hand waving about the probability of the electron’s having the charge it does. Perhaps there is a technically sound response to the probability skepticism expressed in position 4. There may be better arguments against the third position’s use of the anthropic principle than misleading analogies to familiar circumstances. Perhaps fine-tuning can be pushed back so that inflationary cosmologies are not a satisfactory alternative to a designer, or perhaps the physics of the multiverse will run into problems. In fact, it already has, as Gleiser’s resistance shows. The fact that the physics of the multiverse are such that it is completely uncheckable, in principle, not just in practice, makes it more of a metaphysical postulate than a scientific one.

Finally, Rubenstein’s provocative claim that we may be witnessing a radical “reconfiguration” of physics, philosophy, and religion in our time deserves comment. She says relatively little about what that reconfiguration will look like. I can’t help but think that “replacement” of religion by science is the more likely result, where “religion” means classical Christian theism, the traditional Faith of Our Fathers. What if all of the existence-claims of metaphysical theology (including apophatic theology and recent theopoetics) had to face the tribunal of scientific cosmology, and be framed in terms of the physical universe? Mary-Jane Rubenstein owes us another book, as rich as this one.


  1. Quoted in Rubenstein, Worlds Without Ends: The Many Lives of the Multiverse (New York: Columbia University Press, 2014), 17.

  2. Gleiser, The Island of Knowledge: The Limits of Science and the Search for Meaning (New York: Basic, 2014), 127.

  3. Rubenstein, Worlds Without End, 220.

  • Avatar

    Mary-Jane Rubenstein

    Reply

    Questioning the Question: Response to Nancy Frankenberry

    In the face of the energetic reprise of “natural religion” in a multiversal key, Nancy Frankenberry plays Hume’s Philo, skeptical of the whole mess and seeking to unsettle its fundament. Said fundament is composed of the burgeoning throng of universal “fine-tunings,” which Frankenberry with characteristic understatement calls “a loaded label.” Loaded, at the very least, because the grammar alone implies that something has done the tuning—or more narrowly, someone, since even the most agential of “things” don’t tend to tune other things. So there’s an anthropomorphic, godlike power already implied in the question, “why is the universe so finely-tuned to our existence?”

    But even more fundamentally, Frankenberry suggests there is something strange about the thinking that produces the question in the first place. What is it, she asks, that prompts physicists or theologians to call the fundamental constants surprising, or unlikely, such that their values would constitute “fine-tunings” at all? Surprising or unlikely in relation to what? No one knows, and yet despite—or perhaps because of—its inability to account for itself, “fine-tuning” becomes the major premise of the argument from design and the argument for the multiverse. So the latter’s claim to invalidate the former is really just a usurpation: the same theo-logic stays in plays in order to enthrone an infinite number of worlds, right where the infinite God used to sit.

    Depending on our estimation of the integrity of the premise, then, Frankenberry offers four possibilities. Either:

    1. Fine-tuning is “exquisitely improbable” and the explanation is God; or
    2. Fine-tuning is “exquisitely improbable” and the explanation is the multiverse; or
    3. Fine-tuning may or may not be improbable, but it “requires no explanation”; nor, presumably, does it permit one, insofar as the only universe in which we could find ourselves would be one consistent with our existence (this would be a very “weak” version of the anthropic principle); or
    4. It makes no sense to speak of constants as finely-tuned.

    Frankenberry is betting on the fourth; in her words, “probabilities cannot properly be applied to the values of fundamental constants and initial conditions.”

    My only real response here is total agreement. I think it is bizarre indeed to call something for which we have no embodied alternative—the gravitational constant, for example—“improbable.” But I would love to hear more from Nancy (hi, Nancy, and thank you so much for your thrilling response) about why this is the case. Why is the notion of low probability “technically insupportable” when it comes to fundamental constants? Is it because we have no other universes to which we might compare this one in order to proclaim its improbability? Is it because we have never seen initial conditions, except from the vantage point of 13.7 billion years later, on a mountaintop or a satellite in a remote corner of a single galaxy? Which Philonic objection ought we to marshal against the “loaded label” of fine-tuning?

    As I have suggested toward the end of Worlds, the moment one asks why the universe is this way and not another, one is already thinking metaphysically, and can therefore only produce metaphysical answers. Hence the uncanny mirroring of the multiverse and the God it displaces. Frankenberry goes easier on the theorists, conceding that “the why-question remains irresistible.” So like the theoretical physicist, the philosophical theologian, and the four-year-old, I am left wondering why. Why the inexorable why, and to whom is it inexorable? Being more level-headed than I, Frankenberry doesn’t wade in these waters, heading instead for pragmatic shores. Insofar as we don’t seem to be able to stop asking why, she suggest, we should at the very least ask it in a well-informed manner. To wit, “all the existence-claims of metaphysical theology [ought] to face the tribunal of scientific cosmology, and be framed in terms of the physical universe.”

    While I agree with the sentiment, however, I become perplexed here, insofar as the new natural theologies emerging in the face of the multiverse are framed in terms of the physical universe. Whether the metaphysical theology in question produces the God of classical theism or an infinite number of universes, it can fairly claim to be grounded in highly sophisticated observational evidence. The question, as Frankenberry helps us to see, is of what is the evidence evidence? This is a large part of the reason Gleiser is right to say we will never have a consensus about the multiverse. Being in principle unobservable, other worlds can only be detected from evidence that rival physicists can interpret as space-dust, or simple abnormality, or as evidence of a different sort of multiverse from the one whose existence the team in question believes it has “demonstrated.”

    As Frankenberry shows, the argument from design and the argument for the multiverse both arise out of an uninterrogated faith in probability, specifically low probability, which is to say a faith in human exceptionalism extended out to the level of the universe itself. So in addition to calling theology to stand before the tribunal of modern science—which more and more of it does these days, anyway (Bauman, Keller, Crockett, etc.)—I think Frankenberry is also calling scientific cosmology before the tribunal of basic metaphysics, and the result is a reconsideration of the assumptions that undergird each of them. What if it really doesn’t make any sense to talk about universal properties as unlikely? In other words, what if there is no question to which either God or the multiverse would provide an answer?

    • Avatar

      Nancy Frankenberry

      Reply

      A Philonic Postscript

      “Fine-tuning” is to physics what “intelligent design” is to biology. At this late hour for the human race, I would like to think that we can dispense with both. Mary-Jane Rubenstein is right to spot my “Philonic” tendencies, just as Noreen Khawaja is right to consider Hume’s Dialogues “a formal template of [Rubenstein’s] book as a whole,” with the same sparkling wit, we might add. But my Philonic skepticism is crossed with a dose of Kantian modesty. I tend to think that something about our basic cognitive connection to the world invites certain questions, which are, however, in tension with those very cognitive capacities. Call these ineluctable metaphysical questions. Kant concluded that “eternal frustration is our lot,” and Kant scholar Terry Godlove refers to “unavoidable questions, unacceptable answers.” Buddhism files these questions under the category of “Questions Which Tend Not To Edification.”

      What are the why-questions that get filed this way? Not the question, as both Rubenstein and I have tried to indicate, What breathes fire into the equations? Not the question, Why are the constants of nature so finely-tuned for the appearance of humans? Both the inapplicability of probability reasoning (which always needs a comparative), and the broadly verificationist objection (I am thinking Dummett and Peirce, not Hume or Ayer) are enough to make us suspect that, as questions go, there’s no there there in anthropic or multiversal reasoning. Rather, I have in mind a questions such as, Why is there something, and not nothing? Far from being unprofitable, I find this question unavoidable, in most if not all human lives, and also unanswerable. At least, all the “answers” with which I am familiar fall short, and wind up removing the awe and wonder that prompts the question in the first place by finessing an answer that tries to tidy up the loose ends. I suspect that Rubenstein has arrived at the same judgment. All I plug for is the irresistibility of certain questions, as well as the unacceptability of all attempted answers, whether scientific, theological, or metaphysical.

      Surprisingly (to me), Rubenstein finds that “more and more” theology does indeed “stand before the tribunal of modern science” that I more or less demanded (she cites “Bauman, Keller, Crockett, etc.”) But as I read these provocative and tremendously creative authors, I can’t help but think of that moment at the very beginning of the fourth Dialogue where Cleanthes and Demea trade epithets (you mystic! you anthropomorphite!) only to play into Philo’s skeptical hands. The scene is skillfully orchestrated by Hume to bring out the classic dilemma that haunted the God-question in his day, and now in our century dogs the multiverse-question as well as the exigencies of apophatic theology: how to escape from agnosticism without slipping into anthropomorphism, and how to evade anthropomorphism without sacrificing the possibility of intelligibility that is the only defense against sheer agnosticism? How does something about which nothing can be said differ from nothing at all? How can that which is lost in a “cloud of impossibility” become available for speech?

Avatar

Response

Narrative Anxieties

WORLDS WITHOUT END IS a book about connections: how our cosmos is connected to other cosmoi, how cosmology itself is connected to ethics and to aesthetics, how scientific cosmologies are connected to theological cosmologies (not only from a historical point of view), and, thanks to a quantum twist, how thinking about the cosmos is connected to the cosmos itself, to the shape and the structure that we observe, speculate about, entertain. Centering on what she calls the “stubbornly persistent” question of whether the universe is the result of “design,” Rubenstein’s work unfolds as a treasure trove of the historical ironies of speculative philosophy. Dark matter, it turns out, may imply a form of pantheism. The Copernican revolution may have been a restoration of pre-Socratic cosmology. And the argument Lucretius formulates against design (and against the project of a theistic cosmogony) appears to be much the same as that used by David Hume’s Demea (a most vocal proponent of a devotional monotheism). In fact Hume’s Dialogues on Natural Religion could be seen not only as one particular source within Rubenstein’s historical study but also a formal template of the book as a whole. At its strongest, Worlds Without End does for the history of cosmology something like what Hume’s Dialogues did for the idea of a natural religion––demonstrating the consistency of views that appear to be opposed, reordering the apprehensions as well as the comforts of reasoned disagreement.

The broadest arc of the book tells a story about the reappearance of cosmology within mainstream scientific discourse. For several hundred years, cosmology remained on the sidelines of experimental science. “Whereas every other secular discipline studies objects within the world,” Rubenstein explains, “cosmology studies the universe itself.”1 Relative to these other modern sciences, cosmology was considered to be insufficiently objective. But in the twentieth century things changed. Technological developments made it possible to gather empirical evidence about the structure and age of the universe (and even to ascertain that it is expanding in size). These discoveries, in turn, fueled interest in a problem that had concerned scientists at least since Einstein’s theory of general relativity: the physical conditions necessary for the development of life are extraordinarily, perhaps even troublingly, specific. As Rubenstein puts it: “The constants of nature––which, among others, include the strength of gravity, the mass of the electron, and the strength of the nuclear forces––have values that seem precisely calculated to allow life to emerge somewhere in the universe.”2

This, Rubenstein argues, is where the idea of a multiverse comes in. For while such precise calibration is difficult to account for if we consider the universe on its own, it becomes much less bewildering if we suppose that the universe is actually just this universe––one of an infinity of universes, that is, each of which with its own particular orchestration of physical forces. In some, gravity is stronger and the universe implodes. In others it is weaker and matter is too quickly dispersed to form things like planets. But in a very, very small fraction of universes, things are simply bound to go “right.” In the shadow of the multiverse hypothesis, in other words, life goes from being virtually inconceivable to being statistically necessary. So while physicists may have come to admit something like the premise of the old design argument, they now have no need for its conclusion.

One of the most fascinating subplots in Rubenstein’s story involves the work performed by ideas of “religion” and of the “biblical” (which latter term she consistently keeps between quotes). In the language of scientists struggling to reflect on the broad implications of the recent turn to cosmology, such terms operate almost defensively, recharging this unfamiliar terrain in the terms of a conventional opposition. If the big bang hypothesis ushered in a “return of the mythological at the heart of modern science,”3 in Rubenstein’s succinct phrase, then it also gave rise to a renewed sense of urgency to mark off the border between the legitimate, scientific mythoi and the illegitimate, religious ones. Up until the first few decades of the twentieth century, there seems to have been little reason to doubt the quintessential modern view of religion as that which science does, should, and will undermine. Then suddenly physicists begin to debate––and in no small measure to accept––the possibility that the universe began with something like a “primeval atom” that exploded in a burst of light. As astronomer Robert Jastrow summarizes: “For the scientist who has lived by his faith in the power of reason, the story ends like a bad dream.”4

As it turns out, story is the operative word in that sentence. The renewal of mythology at the heart of science does not simply mean a resurgence of speculative stories about the origin and nature of the cosmos; it also means a greater consciousness about the role that stories play in the work of modern science.5 “The resemblance between modern science and what physicists considered a ‘biblical’ mythos was so strong and so disturbing that it prompted the renegade British astronomer Fred Hoyle [who first coined the term “big bang” during a BBC radio broadcast in 1949) to look for a different story to tell—preferably one that did not ‘aid and abet’ religion.”6 Or, regarding the three reigning theories about the end of the universe (“a continually expanding void, an infernal implosion, or a great cosmic shredding”): “Faced with the equally awful possibilities of the whimper, the crunch, and the rip, it seems that some physicists are looking for a different story to tell.”7 The narrative also appears with the rise of the “new ekpyrotic” model of the cosmos (continual destruction and rebirth): “Rather than relying on a host of extracosmic kosmoi to explain the one we are in, Steinhardt and Turok therefore set out to find a different story to tell.”8 In one sense the final two chapters of Worlds Without End read as a lively summary of key ideas and debates within contemporary scientific discussions of the multiverse. Seen from another angle, they also read as an account of the rise of metanarrative anxieties within late modern science.

Rubenstein sees these anxieties as one indication of a potentially profound shift in the relation religion and science in the modern period. Around the theory of the multiverse we discover that the analytical integrity of the “world” is considerably less secure than it seems, and we find that the border between physics and metaphysics, heavily policed at least since the time of the Enlightenment, has in fact become quite porous.9 The result of such changes, Rubenstein asks us to consider, is that the old antagonism between science and religion may at last be giving way to a new relation, one of “multiplicity” and “persistent entanglement” rather than of binary opposition.10 As she observes in the conclusion, both inflationary theory and string theory––two of theoretical physics’ most promising areas for those hoping to thwart the return of the design argument––“have ended up postulating a host of invisible kosmoi in the very process of delivering the world in which we live from an invisible god.”11 “If science can be regarded as the self-overcoming of a particular form of religion,” Rubenstein provocatively asks, “might multiverse cosmologies be something like the self-overcoming of science? Might they not mark the end of the fantasy that ‘science’ has wrested itself free from ‘religion,’ ‘objectivity’ free from subjectivity, and matter free from meaning?”12

The scare-quotes in this passage are telling. They point to one of the most consequential tensions at work in the history Rubenstein has set out to relate. In contemporary culture, as well as in Rubenstein’s book, the word “religion” holds together two utterly distinct sets of things: (1) the concrete and historically demonstrable “religions”—concrete religious traditions and the practicing religionists, who may or may not have a reaction to the new scientific cosmo-mythologies, and (2) the methodological (perhaps even mythical) construct of “religion” that operates in much scientific as well as much popular discourse, which refers to that specific form of mythological thinking that science is meant to disrupt. Reimagining the role that “the religious” might play in modern science requires us first getting clearer about which of these we are talking about, or at least about what the relation between them might look like in a given case. When Lawrence Krauss quotes Thomas Paine in his Twitter feed, writing, “scientists should be prepared to offend religious sensibilities,”13 is there any systematic way of understanding the connection between this methodological application of the “religious” with the “religion” of Cardinal Christoph Schönborn? Schönborn, we might recall, charges multiverse theorists not with a violation of faith or dogma, but with an “abdication of human intelligence,” with having abandoned the modern scientific project of explaining the world “as it appears to us.”14 And supposing Rubenstein is right about the self-overcoming of science, with which sort of “religion” are we to imagine it as being newly caught up?

I would wager that Rubenstein’s answer to this question would be some version of “Both.” I would not challenge such a reply on descriptive grounds. Analytically, however, it is worth exploring the diverse investments that this ambiguity might protect. The less specific we are about the distinction between the ideal methodological construct of religion (defined categorically as non-science) and the variety of empirical phenomena that fall under the name “religion” (which may have any or no particular relation to science), the more we leave ourselves open to a variety of questionable narratives. For one thing, this ambiguity facilitates the familiar idea that by undermining the features of some specific religious account of the universe (e.g., that all was born from nothing in a flash of light), science will be able to avoid doing religion (i.e., dogmatism). The ambiguity of “religion” also supports the converse expectation: science, if only it is able effectively to combat religious modes of thinking, will eventually be able to dislodge that pesky phenomenon called “religion.” Perhaps most surprising, however, is the fact that we can discern parallel investments on the religious side of this antagonism: If science is more dogmatic and less objective than it likes to believe, then on what grounds might a critique of “religions” proceed? Moreover, if after several millennia of concerted effort, science has come around to a picture of the universe that corroborates some ancient religious story, might this not speak to the legitimacy of religion itself? To put it simply: the persistent ambiguity between the discursive ideal of religion and the empirical varieties of religious experience is sustaining the sense of the antagonism between science and religion. And as I have been suggesting, this antagonism is something in which scientists and religionists alike may have a stake.

As an argument about disciplinary entanglement, Worlds Without End builds on these ambiguities more than it addresses them. At nearly every turn, I found myself compelled by the story it weaves and roused by the questions it asks. At the same time, by the end of the book, I came to wonder whether the narrative anxieties Rubenstein so perspicaciously tracks might not point to a different conclusion than the one she draws from this material. For the last few centuries, it has seemed as though the battle between religion and science turned on the question of knowledge, of whether faith and tradition could be viewed as legitimate forms of information about the world. In the context of a battle with “faith” over the rights to speak about the things we could know, science seemed content to leave to religion the metaphysical and speculative matters, indeed to cast them as more or less synonymous (and equally unattractive). The “end” of metaphysics, the “death” of God, modernity, secularization––all seemed to be pointing to roughly the same historical object. Now myth has returned to science and physics has begun to dabble in metaphysics. But does this mean that science and religion are entangled? Or might we see this as an indication that the empirical thing called “religion” is now also being asked to relinquish its claim on metaphysics? That quite the opposite of acknowledging its entanglement with religion, science is no longer content with only knowledge, and is now also waging a battle for cultural rights to the speculative imagination?

Schönborn’s criticism of the multiverse hypothesis, for one, becomes more comprehensible when seen in this light. The Cardinal’s call to respect the boundaries of “modern science” is also a call to respect the boundaries of modern “religion.” As long as we do not try to differentiate between myth, metaphysics, and the religious, “religion” retains the rights to the cosmological imagination. Once physicists begin to speak about manufactured universes and eternal generation and destruction and primordial seas, however, it is not easy to decide whether what we are witnessing is the discovery that science and religion are more connected than they seemed or that what looked like an antagonism for all these years was in fact a suppressed symbiosis.


  1. Rubenstein, Worlds Without End: The Many Lives of the Multiverse (New York: Columbia University Press, 2014), 231. Henceforth WWE.

  2. WWE, 7f.

  3. WWE, 146.

  4. WWE, 148.

  5. Donna Haraway has been arguing something like this for many years. See especially her discussion of fact and fiction in the introduction to Primate Visions: Gender, Race, and Nature in the World of Modern Science (New York: Routledge, 1989).

  6. WWE, 147.

  7. WWE, 151.

  8. WWE, 169.

  9. WWE, 227.

  10. WWE, 234.

  11. WWE, 214.

  12. WWE, 234. One might also note, as many historians of science have shown, that this fantasy was never quite as effective as it took itself to be. See, e.g., Lorraine Daston and Peter Galison, Objectivity (Cambridge: MIT Press, 2007).

  13. https://twitter.com/LKrauss1/status/638977353872347136.

  14. WWE, 208.

  • Avatar

    Mary-Jane Rubenstein

    Reply

    On Science and Religion(s): Response to Noreen Khawaja

    I am delighted and humbled by Noreen Khawaja’s naming of Hume’s Dialogues as “a formal template of the book as a whole.” Throughout this investigation, I have tried to analyze the assumptions and structures of a slew of arguments in differential relation to one another, without siding with any of them. To the extent that I do have preferences, they are strictly aesthetic—which is also to say ethical—but I have no commitment to demonstrating the “truth” of any theological or cosmological scenario, either in isolation from or in consonance with its pair across the vexed division of “science and religion.” I will come back to this attempted non- or multi-partisanship in response to what I take to be this essay’s most pressing question. But I need to address some penultimate ones in order to get there.

    Khawaja attunes us to some increasingly fervent border-policing in the wake of the “recent turn to cosmology,” which seems at each turn to threaten scientific integrity with, well, religion. It is here that Khawaja begins to ask what exactly we’re talking about. When we (okay, I) claim that multiverse cosmologies stage a dramatic entanglement of science and religion, am I referring to “religion” in the sense of “the concrete and historically demonstrable ‘religions,’” or “the methodological . . . construct of ‘religion’ that operates in most scientific as well as much popular discourse”?

    Khawaja imagines my response would likely be “both,” and seems unhappy with that answer. She is worried that such ambiguity, from one direction, facilitates the scientific fantasy of progressively unseating “religion”; and that from the other direction, it threatens the integrity of science in its capacity to marshal a “critique of religions.” While she does not name the motivation for such critique, I am imaginatively extending it to encompass any number of well-funded anti-scientific political endeavors: biology textbooks in Texas, for example, or climate change deniers in the Senate, or efforts to dismantle the Affordable Care Act in the name of “religious freedom.” Khawaja’s question is a multifaceted and complicated one, so first, let me ask: Noreen, am I reading you correctly? Please let me know if I’ve misunderstood, and in the meantime, I will respond as well as I can.

    Am I referring to “religion” historically or methodologically? Right, you’ve got it, both. But it’s a very specific “both.” The methodological construct of “religion” as it shows up in popular and scientific discourse about the multiverse is not the product of the multiplicity of what we now call “world religions,” but of a particular “religion” that (1) coined the term and (2) configures it primarily in terms of truth-claims. So the “religion” that Lawrence Krauss or Stephen Hawking says he’s invalidating forever is a “methodological construct” that entails something like belief in an extra-cosmic Creator. But this methodological construct is the product of a platonized and then protestantized Christianity—and of increasingly protestantizing Judaisms and Islams—which is to say, the methodological construct is a product of the specific “concrete religion” that configures “religion” this way in the first place.

    Other practices, texts, stories, and teachings that (under the intra-active influence of indigenous and secular-Christian politics and scholarship) have been coded as “religious” do not revolve primarily around metaphysical truth-claims, but around embodiment, say, or affect, or getting the rain to fall. And, it is important to note, many of those traditions have produced extensive meditations on scadzillions of other worlds, spatial or temporal, actual or possible. But they have not produced the epistemic controversy that such worlds continue to foment among Christian theologies and post-Christian science, because “truth”—understood as unperspectival correspondence to an objective Real—is not fundamentally at stake in these non-Christian and non-post-Christian contexts.

    So to the question, “with which sort of ‘religion’ are we to imagine [science] as being newly caught up,” my answer is: with the historical “religion” of Christianity that has produced the methodological notion of “religion” as a set of transcendental truth-claims. But a quick clarification: I am not saying this bound-uppedness is new. Multiverse cosmologies are not creating an entanglement between modern science and Western religion; they are revealing an old, even perennial entanglement (Aristotle’s physics, Islamic medicine, devotional empiricism) that only goes latent for a few quick centuries before the advent of the big bang hypothesis. And of course, if we do the work of demonstrating the historical entanglement of the traditions we continue, horribly, to call Western with those we horribly call Eastern (Akira Sadakata suggests the Greek atomists most likely influenced early Buddhist cosmology),1 then all of these distinctions start collapsing pretty quickly.

    And here, I think, is where Khawaja gets really concerned. Am I saying that science and religion are somehow equivalent? “If after several millennia of concerted effort, science has come around to a picture of the universe that corroborates some ancient religious story, might this not speak to a legitimacy of religion itself?” This, I think, is Oliver Davies’ position, and to be sure, it produces a “religion” that promisingly refuses to insulate itself against scientific claims. But it is not my position, for two reasons.

    First, I don’t think there will ever be “a picture of the universe,” at least not now that the multiverse is on the table. Rather, some teams of physicists will interpret dark splotches on the Cosmic Microwave Background as evidence of other universes beyond our own; others will say they’re evidence of a universe before our own; and others will say they’re just irregularities in galactic formation, which is to say, there are no other universes. Insofar as we will likely never have one picture of the multiverse (see Nancy Frankenberry on Marcelo Gleiser), there will never be one “ancient religious story” to legitimate. What is resurging in this new chapter of an ancient entanglement is not so much one of these stories (pace Davies), but rather the irreducible multiplicity of them.

    So this is the second reason that the science-religion entanglement isn’t simply legitimating “religion itself”: their sheer multiplicity means that none of them has a legitimate claim to the truth. As I have tried to show, most contemporary multiverse cosmologies have philo-theological forerunners (inflation with the atomists, ekpyrosis with Vedanta or the Stoics, many-worlds with Leibniz, mathematical universe with Plato). But these resonances are a function not of both scenarios’ being “correct,” but of their having asked similar questions, which reliably produce similar answers. Any resemblances between science and religion, then, are produced by their shared discursive framing—not by their shared correspondence to some extra-cosmic truth.

    To return to the Dialogues (which I’m always reading through Nietzsche), I am not at all prepared to stand up for an extra-cosmic truth, or an unperspectival truth, whether religious or scientific. My hope in bringing these manifold and conflicting cosmologies into conversation is not to endorse any of them, but rather to allow each of them to interrogate the claims of the other, and to show that “truth” only emerges under particular microscopes, through situated telescopes, within unconscious metaphysical frameworks. Change the apparatus and you’ve changed the “truth.”

    My thanks to Noreen for this profoundly generative essay.


    1. Akira Sadakata, Buddhist Cosmology: Philosophy and Origins (Tokyo: Kosei, 2004), 20–23.

Avatar

Response

On the Multiplicity of the Imagination

 

IF, IN RESPONDING TO Mary-Jane Rubenstein’s Worlds Without End, I begin with the anthropological, that is because the persistence of the anthropic principle (strong or weak) is fascinating and significant. If, in the same response, I also begin with the theological, that is because of the sense throughout this book that we are listening to what the Psalmist describes as “the deep calling to the deep” (Ps 42:7). The psalm, as numerous biblical scholars affirm, is cosmological in that it draws upon the ancient structure of the cosmos as the Hebrews conceived it: with waters above the firmament and waters below.

Augustine, commenting on this psalm, focuses on the anthropology this cosmology figures. Transposing “deep” into “abyss” (with its suggestive echoes on Genesis 1:2 and the Spirit hovering over the dark materials of the void prior to creation), Augustine reflects: “If by ‘abyss’ we understand a great depth, is not man’s heart, do you not suppose, ‘an abyss’? For what is there more profound than that ‘abyss’? Men may speak, may be seen by the operations of their members, may be heard speaking in conversation: but whose thought is penetrated, whose heart seen into? What he is inwardly engaged on, what he is inwardly capable of, what he is inwardly doing or what purposing, what he is inwardly wishing to happen, or not to happen, who shall comprehend?” Human beings are a question to themselves, the question installed by our unplumbed and unplumbable depths. For Augustine this question, which cannot be answered while insisting it must be asked, incites a ceaseless longing or desire or love or exilic pilgrimage. In the opening of his Confessions the restlessness only ends when it comes to rest in God. But in Gregory of Nyssa, in the afterlife, desire itself deepens in an eternal anagogē from glory to glory. Human beings proceeding from one dark flow in being created move towards the all-comprehensive dark flow of the God beyond being, the God the English poet Henry Vaughan (in his poem “The Night”) describes as a “deep, but dazzling darkness.” Theologically put, the depths of the human mind plumb the depths of the mind of God. Or, as St. Paul puts it: our “lives are hidden with Christ in God” (Col 3:3).

So, in reading Worlds Without End, I am drawn into reflecting upon the human mind—only 3–5 percent of which, neuroscientists tell us, is accessible or well lit enough to be called “consciousness.” And, in particular, I am drawn to its capacity to imagine. True this is a cognitive capacity, but it pulls into its electro-chemical energy fields resources deep, and inaccessible, in the prefrontal and parietal cortex, the temporal lobe and the limbic area of the right-hemisphere. Imagination is a profoundly embodied cognition, as Marcel Proust understood: “Imagination and sensibility are interchangeable qualities and . . . the latter may without any great inconvenience be substituted for the former.” It emerges prior to language acquisition, as child psychologists have shown, though language greatly enhances the powers of the imagination that subtends symbolic thinking. It is libidinal. Like our senses, which are not at all passive but continually active, foraging our environments for information, communication, desire reaches for what it cannot understand. Desire gropes not grasps, and it bears imagination into all that groping . . . for “truth,” say, for a knowledge of what is true, “science.” Rubenstein, in her concluding remarks, observes the way “scientists believe that there is a truth outside themselves and . . . they devote themselves to the unconditional pursuit of that unconditioned truth” (230). And that pursuit is as much imaginative as it is empirical and libidinal.

Imagination and desire are complicit in belief-formation. Rubenstein demonstrates this so clearly in her persistent recognition that multiverses “demand[ing] just as much ‘faith’ in the invisible as does the design hypothesis” (220), that “physics [opens] onto metaphysics at more or less every turn” (224), and so how “modern science believes” (230). What is both so intriguing and apposite in this book is the permission for different discourses (scientific, metaphysical, theological) to overlap and enrich each other’s perceptions (and interpretations) of the world. Imagination, desire, belief-formation, all rooted deeply in the enfleshment of our minds, are fundamental processes in the continual human negotiation of the invisible in and beyond the visible: this is what I take from Worlds Without End. And this is why it is such a different book to the many books out there on the history of cosmology.

With this book, I plumb the scientific imagination as it possibly overreaches itself. But that overreaching is also significant because the imagination is always overreaching itself in its groping beyond the sensed and visible to that which is hidden and gives them a depth of meaning beyond the surfaces of any single phenomenon. The imagination draws no lines between the physical and the metaphysical, the immanent and the transcendent. Like believing and desiring, imagining is always both anticipating and projecting. The persistent presence (for some) or shadow (for others) of the anthropic principle, marks how we can never transcend our own minds. The anthropic principle is only a case of Feuerbach reading cosmology. While we may get away from its strong, design version, we will always have to live with its weak version. Grafting Barad’s understanding of the participatory universe—“that the observer, the observed, and the instrument of observing ‘intra-act’ to produce the universe ‘itself’ as a set of provisional and shifting intra-actions” (219)—can be supported from quantum physics, but it can also find support in the philosophy of Merleau-Ponty or the scientist Michael Polyani. We create the instruments to see and we only ever see as, and seeing as reveals the “shifting intra-actions” of imagination, desire and belief.

The scientific imagination is governed by certain conceptual parameters, which is why some scientists see the exponents of multiverses as “overreaching.” The concepts are drawn mostly from mathematics: probability, calculus, repeatability, predictability, modal logic, non-contradiction, calibration, consistency, constancy. It is also governed by certain disciplinary or procedural principles: to explain, to move inductively from cause to effect, to observe the evident and demonstrate the laws ordering the evident, to test hypotheses. If both these conceptual parameters and procedural principles aim at a God’s eye view (objectivity), it is an “aim.” For as Rubenstein’s history demonstrates, cosmology is pursued in very human contexts that produce fear, excitement, wonder, controversy, fashion, passionate defense, and equally passionate denunciations. Conceptual parameters, procedural principles and socio-historical contexts all impact seeing as, acting as boundary markers upon where imagination might roam, what is desirable, and the limits of the believable.

I wonder then how the scientific imagination differs from, say, the literary imagination. If Mary Midgley has exposed the mythic in scientific discourse in her book The Myths We Live By, if George Lakoff and Mark Johnston have treated the metaphors by which our physical and social existence is examined and organized in their book The Metaphors We Live By, and if, as Marcelo Gleiser proposes, that science “remains ‘under the mythic spell of the One’” (231 of Rubenstein), then a comparison between the scientific and the literary imagination becomes important. After all, many of the older cosmologies and many of the new could be categorized as “science fiction.” And some of the new cosmologies have been used in the creation of sci-fi, either in literary or cinematic form. Interstellar is just one example. Most of the popular appeal of these cosmologies, and the appeal of writers who make them popular, lies in their imaginative appeal. Illustrations of a quilted multiverse, the inflationary multiverse, the cyclic universe and “the birth of universes from the landscape multiverse” (187), become the front-covers selling Nature and New Scientist. And it wouldn’t surprise me to find their illustrators also illustrate Lord of the Rings or design the sets for Game of Thrones.

Every act of the imagination is informed by its the socio-historical context, and the literary imagination might, at first glance, seem to take no regard of parameters set by mathematic categories or procedural principles. But the Proust quotation shows that imagination works with and upon the materially sensed. Taking Proust as a particular, albeit distinctive, example, we find him, like many painters engaged on a large work, composing experimental sketches of characters, backgrounds and scenes that eventually fit suitably with the overall “world” he creates in his multivolume À la recherche. He tests the effect of these sketches on his friends and, when published as shorter pieces, the public. The mathematics that govern this “world” have to accord with the probable otherwise he can’t make that world believable. For similar reasons, like a continuity assistant on a film or TV set, he has to erase contradictions and implausibilities to ensure consistency in the plot and characterization. Scenes and themes are replayed, albeit differently, across generations in the novel composing a certain rhythm, proportionality and balance. The narrator of the novel often pays attention to the architectural structure and details of cathedrals, and the novel displays a similar elegance and design. As for procedural principles, Proust too needs to explain (though his explanations of human relations and the events they trigger are often magnificently subtle in their complexity) and he needs to abide in his plotting to the deductive logics of cause and effect. When the narrator in the final volume, Le Temps retrouvé, reflects upon his novelistic art he too speaks about seeking through all the plethora of social material, the universal, the laws governing the drama and the behavior. These laws are simultaneously: psychological, sociological, natural and (given this is the creation of a “world” and much concerned with the concept of Time) cosmological. “We suffer what is sensed and in remembering it grope towards what lies beneath the surface,” he tells us. “Reality has its hidden existence”; a reality a great writer seeks to “extract.”

The “laws” (if one can call them that since, like multiverses, we have no access to them) governing the imagination, then, both scientific and literary lies at least analogically close to each other. These laws also extend to the production of treatises and theses, for Worlds Without End is not without its own literary and scientific qualities. Mary-Jane Rubenstein writes with flair, humour, and ironic brio; conscious herself that this book is, besides all else, a literary and imaginative construction. Her literary style engages; engages in a similar way to the creation of a new cosmology or the emergence of a new solution to an equation. These are all creative acts that return us to the anthropological—what it is to be human. Being human, we are dwarfed by the enormities conceived by the scientific imagination. They are sublime in a Kantian mathematic sense. They humble us, and yet we have generated them. Although, maybe on certain readings of the simulated kosmos we might say they have been generated within us. Either way, when we come to terms with our justified Pascalian fears, we return to a profoundly theological trope: deep calling to deep. We return also to that ineradicable anthropic principle that Christian theology can embrace in terms of an incarnational logos Christology and a Pauline attention to all things being en Christō. The Orthodox Church has always understood this, and its continuous appeal to the apophatic, dazzling darkness, has meant that this theology does not and cannot lead to any argument to or from design. Thomas Aquinas only concurs: since we can only treat secondary causality, not the primary cause, then we will never be able to see as God sees. We can only see the natural world as. That does not stop though, in fact it demands, the exercise of imagination, desire and belief-formation. If Rubenstein is right in thinking that “Christianity produces modern science” (234), then to believe, with the cosmologist Andrei Linde, that “we are now entering ‘the age of anthropic reasoning’” (222 in Rubenstein), sounds very promising to a Christian theologian. The mystery of God—whatever is meant by that noun, and certainly not the name of a Grand Architect—just got more mysterious. To cite the title of Rubenstein’s previous book, this would indeed be a Strange Wonder, and the Opening of Awe. Thank you Mary-Jane.

  • Avatar

    Mary-Jane Rubenstein

    Reply

    Calling to the Deep: Response to Graham Ward

    In the village of Crawick, near Sanquhar in Dumfries and Galloway, Scotland, the architect Charles Jencks has created a multiverse.1 Out of the ruins of an exhausted mine, he and an enormous crew of diggers and builders have turned fifty-five acres of post-industrial wasteland into a vibrant enactment of planetary motion, astral glow, galactic spirals, and universal comings and goings. Seriously, he’s made a multiverse.

    One might be inclined to see such a project as an artistic representation of science: modern cosmology tells us what the cosmos is, and then art shows us what it means, what it looks like, how it feels. But Jencks’ work does more than merely translate science into art; it exposes their shared operations. Meandering through the multiverse, one is flabbergasted by the scientific precision of his landscape: this boulder here, at exactly this angle, spaced at Fibonaccic remove from the others. Conversely, one begins to appreciate the creative operations of science itself: the trial and error, the dreaming and testing, the aesthetic propulsion through those “beautiful” equations, reactions, and models it makes more than it discovers.

    This sort of methodological entanglement of art and science takes shape in Graham Ward’s essay through the oft-neglected category of “imagination.” The pursuit of science, he reminds us, “is as much imaginative as it is empirical and libidinal.” Empirical—well, that’s clear. Libidinal because imagination operates by means of desire, at once discursive and material. Conversely, art—Ward’s chief example is Proust—operates empirically as well as imaginatively, negotiating the physically and mathematically possible and probable even as it dreams up alternatives. This sort of artistic-literary-imaginative work is perhaps nowhere more clearly enacted than in the ongoing proliferation of multiversal musings, each of them the complex product of data and daydreaming, revulsion and compulsion, calculation and the incalculable.

    Such persistence of the stubbornly embodied imagination demands that we ask, among other things, what it is that science is discovering. Not, to be sure, “whatever it wants”: to say that science depends constitutively on imagination is not to say it just makes things up. But neither is, say, astrophysics discovering what is simply “out there,” independent of our own complex intra-action with it. “Every act of the imagination is informed by its socio-historical context,” Ward reminds us, which is also to say by its spatio-temporal, cosmic context, as well as the telescopes, spectrometers, and computers we use to discern those contexts. “We create the instruments to see and we only ever see as.”

    Here, then, Ward is throwing his hat into the “correlationist” ring (and reluctant as I am to come down anywhere, I’ll join him; hi, Graham), siding with those philosophers from Kant to Bohr who insist that we can only see the world as we see it; that, pushing more radically into Barad and Connolly, the “world” as such is continually produced by open, intra-active systems of materiality, measurement, narrative, interpretation, and more materiality. So it is not just that we have no access to things-in-themselves; it’s that things aren’t themselves, or are themselves only as both more and less than “themselves.” Contemplating the cosmos as a “whole,” we are faced with imponderable mysteries: untold zillions of galaxies with their however-many trillions of stars, and all of that just 4 percent of the matter-energy in the universe, which might, incidentally, be just one of an infinite number of universes. . . . Ward channels Pascal: “we are dwarfed by the enormities conceived by the scientific imagination.” And here comes the punchline: “they humble us, and yet we have generated them” (emphasis added). So at this moment, the universe begins to look like Marx’s commodity . . . or like Feuerbach’s God.

    From here on out, I imagine Graham will be both with me and not-at-all-with-me, but here for better or worse is where his thinking sends mine. Cosmology, he suggests, participates in the erotic-investigative work of “deep calling to the deep”: of the “vast and infinite profundity” of Augustine’s memory, contemplating the unfathomable God who both indwells and exceeds it. Of Gregory’s intensifying desire and Eckhart’s abyss-in-abyss. Facing this ever-present absence, Ward points out that only 3–5 percent of the human mind is accessible to consciousness (“I cannot grasp the totality of what I am2)—a number that eerily mirrors, not the amount of God we know (how could we know how much God we know?), but the amount of the cosmos we know: 73ish percent dark energy, 23ish percent dark matter, and 4ish percent baryonic, which is to say visible, detectible, experimentable matter. Consciousness calling to cosmos.

    If “God” is the name of the deep unto which the depths of our imagination call, then what are we to make of the resemblances of this human abyss with the cosmic abyss? Have we, in our inescapable “seeing-as,” created a universe in our image, only to reverse the direction and say it’s created us? And as it gets increasingly difficult to distinguish what we say about the cosmos from what we say about God, as it becomes clearer that “whatever is meant by that noun” is “certainly not . . . a Grand Architect,” what is it that allows us to separate the God with whom we are constitutively entangled, whom we can only see as, from the universe that works the same way?

    Here, I think, the choice comes down to Cusa or Bruno: to an apophatic panentheism that both meets and strains the limits of right teaching, or to a transcarnational pantheism that no one in her right mind would endorse . . . and in this either/or lies the good or bad news for “a Christian theologian.” Many thanks to this particular theologian for his celebratory dance through these magnificent cosmic mysteries, and for pushing my thinking in very helpful directions, indeed.

Avatar

Response

Upsetting the Apple Cart

ONE OF THE PRIMARY challenges for theology and the study of religion today is that the assumption in our society—long held—that religion and science are at odds with one another is slowly giving way to an understanding that contemporary science, which is very different from classical Newtonianism, is in fact presently converging with religious perspectives and concerns in significant ways. Of course, as we know from our own history in the early modern period, scientific advances in knowledge have to be internalized over time and in ways that allow their cultural and philosophical meanings to come into view. This is not at all a straightforward process but rather a sporadic and multilayered one. But it is a process which we should receive as potentially a very exciting challenge. It is a historical moment to which we should pay careful attention.

In her book, Mary-Jane Rubenstein does pay it careful attention and in a way that makes an evident contribution to this encounter and dialogue. Perhaps sensibly, the book is itself framed as a narrative which begins with the cosmological thinking of Plato and Aristotle, the classical Atomists and the Stoics, before passing on to the Christian cosmologists, Aquinas, Cusa and Bruno. Seventeenth-century cosmologists and Immanuel Kant on cosmology set the scene for an analysis of contemporary cosmological theory, both seen from an “inflationary,” infinity-centred perspective and a quantum multiverse one. This narrative signals what this book is seeking to do historically, placing ancient, medieval, early modern and contemporary together in a meaningful setting which allows us to identify the reemergence of ancient debates and insights with the passage of time. I certainly benefited from the juxtaposition of thinking about the ancient kosmoi and modern multiverse theory: each illumines the other. The historical detail was everywhere quite gripping and of great value for anyone who is concerned to know the history of the “multiverse” better. Scientific and philosophical-cosmological sources are both dealt with here with very high levels of competence.

But the overall narrative focus also tells us, I think, what the book is not about. There are quite fundamental methodological questions here to do with how scientific and religious, or indeed philosophical, discourses overlap with one another, and how they can be meaningfully reconciled in certain contexts, where they seem to be motivated by the same kinds of questions. A case in point is the scientist’s use of “infinity” in mathematical terms in contrast with the Christian (or “Abrahamic”) use of the word “God.” Now “God” cannot be “God” unless she is also infinite, but the word “God” not only evokes what the scientist means by “infinity.” It also predicates a participative relation of the self in the world. Scientific knowledge is hard-won from the perspective of the “observer” who—marvellously—finds that her mind is so adapted to what is, that she can gain deep and reliable knowledge about the universe in which she finds herself. The religious person, on the other hand, thinks like an agent: what do I have to do in order to be a good or even true human being? What do I need to do in this situation to be a good Catholic or Muslim? Religions and science are separated by principles and practices of law which are encoded within religious cultures as demanding repeated personal commitment and so become constitutive in some degree of religious identity. It is the characteristic mistake of religion’s current detractors to think that science and religion are in competition with one another as two different ways of describing the world as observers, who are ourselves somehow outside the world and looking in. Sooner or later then, if we think about science and religion, we are going to come face-to-face with the problem of how can we integrate what makes sense to someone who observes as if from without and someone who already knows themselves to be intrinsically part of the world and an agent within it? Or to put this in more traditional terms, how do we integrate theoretical with practical and social reason?

This problematic appears in Mary-Jane Rubenstein’s book at several points where she makes reference to the Christian doctrine of the Trinity. In the case of Thomas, for instance, God appears as “eternally pluri-singular” (73–74), or again in Nicholas of Cusa where “the unity of God is therefore not different from plurality, but a ‘unity to which neither otherness nor plurality nor multiplicity is opposed.’ To say that creation is ‘one . . . since it takes its being from the One‘ is therefore not to say that creation is not also many, because the One itself is not ‘not many‘” (85–86). It is precisely here, in these fleeting references to the Trinity, that the two worlds of science and religion potentially collide in ways that could cast light on both. Here we have a stark choice between two possibilities. The first is simply to accommodate the Christian affirmation within an overall scientific-philosophical optic whereby we think about the world as being enclosed by an infinity which somehow relates to our space and time. Here both the scientific and religious positions are arrived at, we may suppose, through parallel processes of reasoning, which already appeared in thinkers from the pre-Christian classical period. Alternatively, we can take at face value the normative account that Thomas Aquinas himself gives for the source of this knowledge of the Trinity, which is divine revelation. Aquinas is clear that the unity of one-ness and three-ness in divinity is made known to us through revelation and cannot be arrived at purely through processes of natural reasoning.

To allow that alternative perspective is already to shift the juxtaposition of science and religion to different and less hospitable terrain, since now we will have to deal with the deep differences between them in terms of their contrasting understanding of the credibility of revelation as source of knowledge. The scientist qua scientist will not be able to follow the theologian when the latter turns to divine disclosure to justify belief in the oneness and threeness of God as ultimate reality. And there are further significant distinctions here. After all, with the claim to revelation a further claim is made, which is that the acceptance of revelation is in some sense a matter of binding obligation. It affects how we are to live. The extensive divide between theoretical and practical reason alluded to above reappears here with some force. Can we really believe that someone who ceases to live as a Christian might nevertheless wish to hold on to a belief in the Trinity: in the ultimate understanding of reality as a unity of oneness and threeness? Or is it not rather the case that Christians hold to a belief in the Trinity because—however we understand this—Christian life and Christian identity seem to make sense for us though not as “philosophers” but rather as people who have, as community, stumbled upon or discovered compelling meaning in the experience of being alive in this world? From this internal perspective, the ultimate meaning of Christian communitarian life is fundamentally bound up with the threeness and oneness of God. If one stands outside the Christian community however, with its “discovered” meaning, then there is no reason to think that the symmetry between Christian belief in a Triune God and contemporary cosmology is anything more than a coincidence. It can’t be explained. It simply happens.

But Mary-Jane Rubenstein’s case is that it doesn’t just happen: there is in fact a deep resonance between Aquinas, Cusa and Bruno, and our contemporary cosmology. And in this respect she is very successful. We conclude that in fact there are all kinds of overlap, also with classical thinkers. It is reasonable to ask then what it was about medieval Christianity—here under discussion—which allowed such thinking to emerge: perceptions which genuinely seem to anticipate the highly sophisticated reasoning of later generations in a more scientific age?

Allowing revelation to enter in at this point in the dialogue, with its very different understanding of epistemic authority to that of science, may upset the apple cart but it does give us the opportunity to think a little more about the underlying rationality of Rubenstein’s depiction of this symmetry across the centuries. We need to return to the difference between practical and theoretical reason again. These two very obviously have elements which are not in common: practical reasoning generally reasons towards changes in bodily states, advantages or needs (how can I get what I need?). The process of reasoning is resolved when the final, desired state is reached. We might say that reasoning towards what we feel we need is reasoning in its “natural” state. But there is more to practical reasoning than just this. As “motive reasoning,” practical reasoning includes not only how can I get from A to B but also should I be wanting to get from A to B in the first place (Paul Janz, The Command of Grace, 2009)? What about the social effects of my acts and their consequences for others? At this point practical reason becomes more complex, for how can I factor in the effects of something from the point of view of the other or others? How can I come to decision from their point of view as well as my own?

Although we are a social animal, there is something not natural in one sense, or at least effortful, in our social reasoning. It takes training and perhaps also the habit of “virtue” to do it well. In a parallel way, we might say that the “scientific gaze” is not natural and has to be learned. It is very difficult to set aside our own preferences and to be wholly objective. A scientific training can be long and hard. Are there not see parallels here?

We are confident that the scientific mind of the observer is so measured to this fine-tuned universe (which allows itself to be known) that there is every possibility that we will come to understand some of the deepest mechanisms of our universe. In terms of science then, the human mind is “adequate” to its object. But if the adequacy of the human mind, in its scientific “observer mode,” to the universe can be affirmed, then why not also the human mind, in its “agent mode” as “participant” in the world? If we can grasp the fine-tuning through theory, then why should we not be able to reason practically in ways which are to a greater or lesser degree in tune with that fine-tuning? And in fact, just as scientific reasoning can point to its fruits in technology, so too the great world religions can point to the fruits of their acquired and specialised social reasoning in the longevity and unparalleled dissemination of their communitarian identities. It is not a given that a religious identity should thrive for three thousand years. If such longevity exists, then whatever other factors may be in play in the pro-social flourishing of religions, it is reasonable to conclude that many within that community must be reasoning socially and practically in exceptional ways.

And here perhaps some kind of explanation comes into view of how the Christian doctrine of the Trinity may have come about. If we can say that the rational lives of many members of the “body of Christ” as a pro-social community may in fact be a reflection of or even participation in the cohesion of our fine-tuned universe (of which we are all intrinsically a part), then it may in fact be unsurprising that the community should come to intuit something of the nature of the fine-tuned universe taken as a whole. This would then not be directly the product of an adequation between the scientific “observer” mind and our fine-tuned universe, but rather of our practical and social mind, as this engages with and pro-socially enhances societal cohesion, inclusiveness and the resilience of community life.

  • Avatar

    Mary-Jane Rubenstein

    Reply

    On Unity in Difference: Response to Oliver Davies

    Like each of the other panelists, Oliver Davies is concerned in this essay to ask “fundamental methodological questions” about “how scientific and religious . . . discourses overlap with one another.” Ultimately, Davies also wants to ask “how they can be meaningfully reconciled with one another,” which is a goal I should clarify I do not quite share, insofar as neither “science” nor “religion” is sufficiently self-identical to be brought into a higher-level identity with the other. But Davies is right to point out that I am listening in Worlds for resonances, echoes, and in that sense, perhaps I do tend to thematize continuity more than discontinuity. And while Davies might ultimately be looking for a unification, he dwells at length in this essay upon differences—in order, perhaps, to show what it is that calls for reconciliation.

    Davies draws this essay’s primary distinction between the figures of the scientific observer and the religious agent. According to Davies, the former measures while the latter participates; the former gives distanced reflection while the latter offers “repeated personal commitment”; in short, the former “observes [the world] from without,” while the latter “knows [her/himself] to be intrinsically part of the world and an agent within it.”

    While I understand the difference as it takes shape here, I think I would want to push on it from both directions; first, “science” in its manifold discourses and practices is utterly participatory. It may not always admit this, but as Nietzsche, Latour, Stengers, and Haraway have each argued differently, and as the quantum continues to reveal, scientific measurement participates in the production of the phenomena it records and experiments upon. And I’m not sure what we would call all those hyper-caffeinated all-nighters in labs and at telescopes fifteen thousand feet in the air if not “repeated personal commitment.”

    Conversely, some religious practitioners eschew participation in the world as such. I am thinking in particular of Christians of various persuasions who claim to be “in” the world but not “of” it, to belong fundamentally elsewhere, and to be somehow “covered” by the sacrifice of their savior so that their “religiousness” requires simple belief and acceptance, rather than any sort of “repeated personal commitment.” To be sure, this is not the sort of Christianity that Davies has in mind, nor would he stand behind it theoretically or (I imagine) personally. Yet one need only summon the discursive targets of Kierkegaard’s Attack upon Christendom or Bonhoeffer’s “religionless Christianity” to see this sort of otherworldly passivity as at least one major strand within the Christian tradition. Of course, such expressions of Christianity do act and participate, even if they claim merely to receive—just as science actively produces the world it often claims merely to measure. Both, then, participate in co-constructing the reality they discern (see Graham Ward’s essay), whether they admit it or not.

    This shared cosmogonic capacity complicates what Davies calls a “symmetry between Christian belief in a triune God and contemporary cosmology.” First, it is not clear where such symmetry would reside. Certainly not at the level of specific doctrinal formulations, which, as Davies notes, rely on revelation through a particular interpretation of scripture rather than Ward’s dance of reason and imagination. To be sure, there may be a certain “symmetry” between one or another (but not all) of the models of the multiverse and the broadly Trinitarian coincidence of unity-in-multiplicity, but this would be a resonance with the logic of the Trinity rather than the doctrine-itself. It is not clear, for example, that an attempted reconciliation here could count on cosmology’s stopping at three in its functional or numeric account of the multiple.

    Second, to the extent that any cosmic scenario does resonate in part with a theology we have seen before (say Cusa or Bruno, whose models bear crucial differences despite their structural similarities), such resemblance is a function, not of their shared access to a transcendent real, or even of the medieval period’s having “anticipated” scientific developments. The resemblance would rather be a function of their working with similar sets of questions on the one hand and explanatory possibilities on the other. In short, insofar as they both help produce the reality they see (which isn’t the same thing as just making it up; see again the conversation with Ward), their synchronicities can be traced to their methodological, theoretical, and narrative similarities, rather than to a shared correspondence to, say, the truth (see the conversation with Khawaja).

    Insofar as I am hoping in Worlds to bracket all claims to truth—whether scientific, religious, or philosophical—I am neither asking whether the multiverse (for example) can be squared with orthodox Christian revelation, nor whether orthodox Christian revelation can fit itself into the boundless bounds of the multiverse. Instead, I am trying to show how cosmology is actively constructing its own metaphysic, which is fascinatingly entangled with variously Jewish and Christian and Hindu and Buddhist cosmologies, but which is not finally reducible to any of them. If there is theology going on here, it is both borrowed and new, and if we try to “reconcile” it with any existing theology, I fear we miss the new part. To attend to such newness would be, in part, to take seriously what Davies calls the participation of scientific knowledge in the universe itself—both at the practical level (ecologically, socially, politically) and on a theoretical level, insofar as it, just like our older metaphysics, co-constructs the universe it discerns. And concerning the ethical significance of recognizing such participation, I think Davies and I agree completely. My sincere thanks to him for this thoughtful and compelling essay.

Avatar

Response

The Logic of Self Sabotage

THE THESIS OF Mary-Jane Rubenstein’s comprehensive and insightful treatment of multiverse theory looks like this: “If science can be regarded as the self-overcoming of a particular form of religion, might the multiverse cosmologies be something like the self-overcoming of science?”1 The irony here is that multiverse theory in physical cosmology is based not on science but rather on anti-theology, on a scientific opposition to appropriating God as an explanation for the big bang. Multiverse or M theorists especially oppose invoking a creating God to explain the fine-tuning of the anthropic principle, the initial conditions which make the evolution of life possible. But, argues Rubenstein with uncanny perceptivity, the appeal to anti-theology to sustain science’s opposition to theology functions to supplement physics with metaphysics. Science voluntarily becomes non-science.

Rubenstein, alluding to Friedrich Nietzsche, describes Christian theology’s own intellectual suicide. When Christian intellectuals insisted on commitment to the truth, they surrendered totally to the take-no-prisoners approach to scientific truth. Then, when scientists denied the existence of God, the theologians were left empty-handed. “Christianity produces modern science, in a staggering gesture of self-sabotage, as its consummation and its destruction.”2 With this in mind, Rubenstein asks: now, have the scientists followed the same path to self-sabotage?

As Mark Twain suggested a century ago, reports of his suicide were premature. The suicide of the theologian and of the scientist is also premature, in my judgment. Neither are dead. Nevertheless, the logic of self-sabotage is well worth examining.

The Theology of Big Bang Cosmogony

Even before the controversy over the anthropic principle which arose in the 1970s, some theologians had seen in big bang cosmogony support for the biblical doctrine of creation. This includes Pope Pius XII when addressing the Pontifical Academy of Sciences in 1951. “Thus, with the concreteness which is characteristic of physical proofs [science] has affirmed the contingency of the universe and also the well-founded deduction as to the epoch when the world came forth from the hands of the Creator. Hence, Creation took place. We say, therefore, there is a Creator. Therefore, God exists.”3 When time was zero (t = 0), our world began, just as Genesis 1:1—2:4a describes.

Scientists too. Founder and former director of NASA’s Goddard Institute for Space Studies, Robert Jastrow, announced he was startled to see how big bang cosmology supports the biblical view of creation. “The astronomical evidence leads to a biblical view of the origin of the world. The details differ, but the essential elements in the astronomical and biblical accounts of Genesis are the same: the chain of events leading to man commenced suddenly and sharply at a definite moment in time, in a flash of light and energy.”4 One of his more ironic comments has oft been repeated. “At this moment it seems as though science will never be able to raise the curtain on the mystery of creation. For the scientist who has lived by his faith in the power of reason, the story ends like a bad dream. He has scaled the mountains of ignorance; he is about to conquer the highest peak; as he pulls himself over the final rock, he is greeted by a band of theologians who have been sitting there for centuries.”5

Big bang has been the scientist’s nightmare. It looks like the physical cosmologist has provided a view of reality which is consonant with that of the theologian. So, if one wants to conscript science into the atheist army, affirming big bang as the origin of a single universe looks like turning the atomic bomb over to the religious enemy. And with the arrival of the anthropic principle, it’s now the H-bomb. How can a materialist scientist muster a defense? Answer: M theory.

The Anti-Theology of M Theory: Martin Rees

I’ve been thinking about these issues for some time now. It appears to me that Martin Rees and Stephen Hawking provide the most vivid examples that illustrate Rubenstein’s thesis: by appealing to anti-theology in support of M theory, scientists are actually subordinating their empirically based physics to metaphysics.

When Templeton laureate physicist and cosmologist Martin Rees is faced with the facts describing the role of the anthropic principle in making our biophilic universe, he offers three parallel interpretations of the data. First, the data describing the initial conditions, no matter how astounding, are merely a matter of happenstance. Second, the universe was designed by God so that God’s providential plan for life, mind, and spiritual community could be fulfilled. Third, the multiverse. Rees says he finds the first option unreasonable and the second one unnecessarily religious, so he opts for the third. “We can conjecture that our universe is a specially favored domain in a still vaster multiverse.”6

Let’s examine the Rees logic. We note that this third alternative, the multiverse, is selected for an extra-scientific reason. M theory avoids observable contingency as implied in the happenstance option; so, the M theorist can support determinism. M theory similarly avoids divine design, because that would be religious. So, almost in frustration, Rees searches and finds a deterministic explanation that avoids religious implications. Whew. That was a close call!

It appears to me—as it appears to Rubenstein—that the postulation of multiple universes is based upon a philosophical assumption that denies the finality of contingent events for defining nature, while it denies divine design. Ironically, these assumptions are built on a previous theological axiom, the principle of plenitude. Basically, the principle of plenitude says that every potential becomes actualized. Translated into contemporary physical cosmology, the resulting multiverse hypothesis posits that all mathematically possible universes become actualized. Even though empirical scientists find contingency in natural processes, M theorists posit a rigid determinism that contrasts with the evidence. Oddly, a now discarded medieval theological axiom has been dusted off and silently invoked in secular circles to support M theory. The dramatic contingency displayed by the anthropic principle is flatly rejected; and the rejecting scientist discretely invokes a long outdated theological principle to justify its rejection, namely, every potential gets actualized. Anti-theology invokes theology to deny theology.

What scientists actually observe within our physical universe is not the principle of plenitude, but rather contingency. The principle of contingency, in contrast to the principle of plenitude, assumes that some potentials become actualized but others do not. If one desires to postulate determinism to describe reality, then contingency must be eschewed and something like the principle of plenitude invoked. This principle provides the basis for the theory of multiple universes or M theory. Here is the argument: because each potential pathway of a subatomic particle is taken, and because only one of these paths is taken in our universe, it follows that there must exist other universes where the other potentials are actualized. The collection of all of these universes could be called the multiverse. As one might imagine, this number of universes within the multiverse would be very large, unfathomably large.

Just a brief excursus on contingency. Contingency refers to two things: global and local contingency. First, global contingency is what Rees called “happenstance.” This is global contingency in the sense that the initial conditions at the big bang—the fine-tuning which has made the evolution of life possible—could have been different and we Homo sapiens would not be here to ask these questions. This term also acknowledges local contingency. Local contingency is what is observable every day in laboratory experiments, namely, natural processes especially at the subatomic level that are not predetermined. Individual events are not predicable; they are contingent. Robert John Russell clarifies the vocabulary here. “In my typology I first distinguish between global contingency, which applies to the universe as a whole, and local contingency, which applies to a process or property within the universe. Each of these can have two forms: ontological contingency, namely why something exists per se, and existential contingency, that is, why it exists in the particular way it does. . . . For example, t = 0 addresses global ontological contingency, and the fine-tuning arguments about nature’s fundamental constants are related to global existential contingency.”7

It turns out that theistic scientists such as Harvard’s Owen Gingerich like contingency; because with contingency the world becomes a comfortable nest for God. “To a theistic scientist, and perhaps even to God, a world with contingency is far more interesting than one devoid of it. Seen with the eyes of faith, the world seems to be organized with purpose, direction, a pervasive sense of movement toward higher organization, but not necessarily with a total blueprint.”8

The Anti-Theology of M Theory: Stephen Hawking

M theorists believe they are assembling evidence for the multiverse idea, even if as yet their argument has not proven broadly persuasive. What I observe is how postulating the existence of multiple universes brings comfort to an anxious determinist wringing his or her hands over the anthropic principle. By dumping our universe into a larger mechanistic box of many universes, our own universe loses its remarkable status. All that remains is for M theorists to prove this idea by mustering evidence.

Along with Rees, Stephen Hawking enthusiastically embraces a version of M theory. We might ask: just what is M theory? “No one seems to know what the ‘M’ stands for,” writes Hawking; “but it may be ‘master,’ ‘miracle,’ or ‘mystery.’ It seems to be all three.”9 After this apparent nonsense he proceeds to assert that “the Laws of M-Theory therefore allow for different universes with different apparent laws.”10

More relevant for our discussion here is what Hawking says about determinism. Following Pierre-Simon, Marquis de Laplace (1749–1827), Hawking advocates what he calls “scientific determinism” this way: “Given the state of the universe at one time, a complete set of laws fully determines both the future and the past. This would exclude the possibility of miracles or an active role for God. . . . A scientific law is not a scientific law if it holds only when some supernatural being decides not to intervene.”11 The cosmic determinism espoused by Hawking applies to the earliest big bang universe as well as to everyday mental activity. It derives not from scientific evidence but rather from Hawking’s theology or, better said, anti-theology.

In her acute analysis of the very concept of multiple worlds from ancient atomists to contemporary M theorists, Rubenstein uncloaks the extra-scientific anti-theology of purported multiverse science. “There is, then, a profoundly nontheistic (sometimes even antitheistic) motivation behind the scientific turn to many-worlds scenarios.”12 Because “the multiverse does away with the need for a creator-god—at least as an explanatory principle,” she surmises that desperate atheism is at work here plugging scientific holes with extra-scientific metaphysics.13 “Such theories represent a total violation of the principles of falsifiability, testability, and, above all, economy that undergird the scientific project.”14

God Regardless

It appears to both Rees and Hawking that the idea of a big bang combined with an anthropic principle in a single universe makes plausible religious belief in a creating God. As Pope Pius XII illustrates, some theologians would agree: big bang cosmogony implies the existence of a divine designer.

Now, how might a theologian respond to M theory? Must a theologian agree with Rees and Hawking? Here is the logic: if M theory is successful scientifically then a creator God would be out of a job. However, surmises Rubenstein, M theory does not forbid the theologian from positing the existence of God. “Simply put, a Christian can easily affirm that God created the multiverse that created the universe.”15 If Rubenstein is correct, this will give Rees and Hawking another nightmare.

Conclusion

As a trinitarian theist, it appears to me that the logic of Rees and Hawking is correct: big bang cosmogony accompanied by fine-tuning makes plausible the existence of a creating God. These physicists deny the existence of such a God, while I affirm it. Yet, I’m not confident that this argument alone suffices for the theologian.

In my judgment, demonstrating that the designer of the big bang exists is less important than knowing whether or not God is gracious. Just any ol’ deity will not do for my Christian faith. What is decisive is the character of this deity. Is the God who creates the world loving, caring, and compassionate, or not? If God is not gracious, then I hardly care whether a big bang God exists.

 


  1. Rubenstein, Worlds Without End: The Many Lives of the Multiverse (New York: Columbia University Press, 2014), 234.

  2. Ibid.

  3. Pope Pius XII, cited in Helge Kragh, Cosmology and Controversy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1960), 257.

  4. Robert Jastrow, God and the Astronomers (New York: Norton, 1978), 14.

  5. Ibid., 116.

  6. Martin J. Rees, “Living in a Multiverse,” in The Far Future Universe: Eschatology from a Cosmic Perspective, ed. George F. R. Ellis (Philadelphia: Templeton Foundation, 2002), 66.

  7. Robert John Russell, Cosmology from Alpha to Omega: The Creative Mutual Interaction of Theology and Science (Minneapolis: Fortress, 2008), 15.

  8. Owen Gingerich, “Is There Design and Purpose in the Universe?,” in Science and Religion in Search of Cosmic Purpose, edited by John F. Haught (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2000), 129.

  9. Stephen Hawking and Leonard Mlodinow, The Grand Design (New York: Bantam, 2010), 117.

  10. Ibid., 118.

  11. Ibid., 30.

  12. Rubenstein, Worlds Without End, 17.

  13. Ibid., 207.

  14. Ibid., 233–34.

  15. Ibid., 210.

  • Avatar

    Mary-Jane Rubenstein

    Reply

    Contingency Plans: Response to Ted Peters

    Ted Peters’ energetic response takes off where Worlds leaves off: with the multiverse’s uncanny recapitulation of the very theology it is designed to avoid. Peters puts the matter a bit more boldly than I would, and it sets his essay on fascinating terrain: “Multiverse theory,” he argues, “is based not on science but rather anti-theology.”

    This recent bout of anti-theology can be traced along Peters’ account to two mid-century developments in particular: the big bang hypothesis that established (or, for many theologians, confirmed) the contingency of the universe and the anthropic principle that increased our wonder at its unlikely biophilia. Horrified by its neo-theological progeny, modern cosmology seems to have only three means of explaining the anthropic big bang. Following Martin Rees’ schema, Peters lists them as:

    1. “Happenstance”
    2. God
    3. The multiverse.

    Insofar as (1) is said to be “unreasonable” and (2) is scientifically inadmissible, the only remaining possibility is a primordial multiverse that mitigates our contingency (whether by means of the hyper-determinate wavefunction, the inexorability of inflation, or the eternal necessity of mathematics) and annuls our singularity, rendering the universe one of those things that just happens from time to time. If I’m reading Peters correctly, he is among those theologians who would call the multiverse “the last resort of the desperate atheist,”1 reducible to primarily anti-theological commitments, which it then seeks both to justify and cover over with subsequent scientific evidence.

    Having gone on at length about the multiversal effort to run away from an infinite God only to reinstall him in the form of infinite kosmoi, I would like to follow Peters’ more interesting lead and examine with him the modern cosmological flight from contingency. In rejecting Rees’ options 1 and 2 (which, incidentally, map onto Nancy Frankenberry’s options 3 and 1—more on this in a moment), multiverse theorists reject what Robert John Russell calls “global” contingency, which is to say the non-necessity of our entire universe, or indeed of any universe at all.

    Having “dusted off” the old medieval “principle of plenitude,” says Peters, multiverse theorists give us a cosmos in which “every potential becomes actualized.” I would want to add here that different scenarios put different limits on “potentiality,” a category whose physical properties expand progressively as we move from the many worlds interpretation to the inflationary hypothesis to the string landscape and mathematical universe. (I should also say quickly for clarity’s sake that I won’t follow Peters in his abbreviation of “multiverse theory” to “M theory,” to avoid confusion with string theory). But in each of these multiverses, yes, every possibility is actualized somewhere, so nothing is truly decided, lost, or frankly, possible at all; a sea of actual infinities and infinite actualities assures the ontological determinism of not just this, but all possible (actual) worlds. This happens because everything happens. Somewhere.

    Deeply critical of this flight from contingency, Peters is in good company. Physicists like John Barrow, Paul Davies, and Burton Richter have insisted that until inflationary or string theorists can calculate the probability of any particular universe nucleating out of the multiversal sea, they will not have accounted for any of the “fine-tunings” that have reportedly driven them to the multiverse.2 More diagnostically, philosophers of physics like Evelyn Fox Keller and Karen Barad have exposed the many-worlds hypothesis as a longing for the determinism of classical physics.3 It is in this sense, I think, that Peters tags the multiverse theorist as a modern-day Laplace, eliminating the space of contingency (which is also, along this line of thinking, the space for God) by means of a neo-Newtonianism in the form, to name one, of the oddly anti-quantum Many Worlds Interpretation. What seems unbearable for this hypothesis in particular is the threatened ultimacy, not only of indeterminate subatomic behavior, but also of our everyday experience of the world: in Peters’ words, “some probabilities get actualized but others do not.”

    Somewhere between the stark contingency of a haphazard cosmos (Rees option 1 / Frankenberry 3) and the stark determinism of the multiverse (Rees 3 / Frankenberry 2), Peters finds a livable explanatory principle in a loving, compassionate, trinitarian God. As he reminds us, the mere existence of a first principle is of little interest to the theologian independently of its essence, and such a God’s essence and existence are fully compatible either with a single universe or an infinite multiverse. So the theist has little to fear either way. And we could just leave it here.

    But I wonder if I might nudge Ted a bit (hello, Ted!)—really out of curiosity, and because I think the conversation might be a fun one to have—in order to ask about the ground on which this whole God-and/or-multiverse “debate” is taking place: namely, the anthropic principle. In short, I’m wondering if we should buy it.

    In “All the Light We Cannot See,” Nancy Frankenberry enumerates four possible solutions to the “fine-tuning problem” that generates the anthropic principle. There are Martin Rees’ three (God, the multiverse, accident) and then there is one more: the possibility that “probabilities cannot properly be applied to the values of fundamental constants and initial conditions.” In other words, there is no fine-tuning problem. In the spirit of David Hume’s Philo, Frankenberry opts for this fourth “solution,” which is to say, she rejects the problem from the outset.

    Along with Nancy, I find myself wondering, in what sense is it coherent to speak of our universe as “felicitiously arranged” (Weinberg), or to speak of any particular constant as “surprising” or “improbable,” when we don’t have any other observable, indisputably existent universes with which to compare them? We are told that the question is, “why is the universe so well-suited to life,” and that the answer is either God or the multiverse. But isn’t the question, in fact, the product of the answer it seems to precede? Doesn’t the question emerge from an anterior belief in, say, answers? Or what Nietzsche would call truth? Doesn’t the answer, in short, prompt us to ask the very sort of question that then prompts us to seek out the truth that generated it in the first place?

    This conclusive anteriority is perhaps not a problem for theologians, who can say with St. Augustine that it is God who causes me to desire the God who alone is the end of that desire.4 But it would seem to be a problem for a purportedly secular, strictly physical cosmology, which presumably ought not to be asking its questions in the inescapably metaphysical terms of their answers. It is for this reason that I am asking whether “science” might be edging constitutively into something else the moment it begins to ask “why.” Something that’s not not-science, but that’s also not not-philosophy or religion.

    It is my sense that the answers our contemporary not-quite-secular cosmology produces will always be compatible with, say, a personal God, whether loving or not, omnipotent or not, trinitarian or not. But there are also all these other, less expected divine-ish principles emerging from the multiverse—from the Manichaean battle between dark energy and gravity to the godly imperturbability of the wavefunction to the tehomic maternality of the multiversal sea—and I think the conversation between “science and religion” might do well to take a break from its back-and-forth over the God of classical theism and focus on these other figures, instead. Why? Well, to change the channel and watch something else for a while. But also to get a sense of whether “science” is justified when it asks why the universe is this way and not another, and what exactly science becomes when it does.


    1. Neil Manson reports on this position in his introduction to God and Design: The Teleological Argument and Modern Science, ed. Neil A. Manson (New York: Routledge, 2003), 18.

    2. See Worlds, 202, 220–25.

    3. See Worlds, 216.

    4. Augustine, Confessions, 1.1.1.

Shares
Verified by ExactMetrics