Wealth, Virtue, and Moral Luck
By
9.26.24 |
Symposium Introduction
The rise of economic inequality punctuates national discourse and a reliable concern throughout national election cycles. Over the past few decades, mentions of “the one percent” have come to signify that rarified class of people who—through inheritance or business savvy or greed and exploitation or any combination therein—have accumulated wealth beyond most people’s wildest dreams, far more than any one person or family could expect to spend in their lifetime. With this kind of wealth comes power; with resources that far outstrip most of the world’s nation-states, these individuals and families influence everything from national politics to academic programs on college campuses. Some in the one percent finance charitable works and aid organizations with a global reach, while a portion of this cohort choose to invest billions in the new space race. There are conferences, meetings, and retreats where high net worth is the price for admission and decisions with far-reaching geopolitical implications are made behind these closed doors.
While many of us lament the extreme and conspicuous consumption of the one percent and the legal and tax loopholes that enabled the accumulation of such wealth, we may be tempted to overlook that we, too, often have more than we need. The surplus that many in the middle class have, and what we choose to do with it, raises important questions for economic agency and virtue. Kate Ward’s Wealth, Virtue, and Moral Luck: Christian Ethics in an Age of Inequality offers an invitation to consider the implications of this excess. Ward argues that a moral critique of inequality is incomplete without interrogating the ways that the scope of inequality shapes moral development and facilitates the adoption of economic virtues or creates impediments in doing so. She offers an account of how wealth and poverty function within a Christian account of moral luck, that is, how life circumstances provide frames of reference and social relationships that impact how one conceives of the moral project. Through the lenses of the economic hyperagency available to the wealthy and the scarcity some experiencing poverty face, Ward considers how each condition can impede or assist in the development of the cardinal and economic virtues.
Our symposium respondents raise rich considerations for further discussion. Kate Jackson-Meyer meditates on the preponderance of media highlighting the lives of the uberrich, affirming Ward’s low threshold for considering “wealth” in order to provoke discomfort and introspection among her likely readers (namely, educated academics and theologians and our students). Jackson-Meyer offers further complexity to Ward’s project by inquiring about the relationship between inequality, the development of virtue, and human flourishing. In addition to inequality, she identifies additional measures that contribute to one’s sense of wellbeing and flourishing, suggesting that policies intended to counteract the impacts of inequality ought to include metrics beyond economic circumstances.
Vincent Lloyd provocatively challenges Ward’s thesis, suggesting that perhaps it is not one’s economic status but instead one’s learned relationship with money that impacts the development of economic virtues. If one’s life centers around money, whether wealthy or in poverty, that life will have a different emphasis than if one treats money with indifference. Further, Lloyd interrogates the limits of virtue ethics, as it is presently conceived, to confront systemic domination and potentially promote social transformation by cultivating “virtues of struggle.”
Through the lens of rural contextual theology, Ben Durheim considers the application of moral luck in rural communities. Durheim builds upon Ward’s definition of poverty to include the impoverishment of essential services—in particular, sufficient healthcare and social services—that rural communities often face. At the same time, Durheim identifies that many rural communities, even those that lack material resources, still consider themselves to be bastions of moral community capable of rigorous moral formation.
Karen Guth attends to the transgenerational, structural impact of economic inequality in relation to her own work addressing the tainted legacies of slavery, racism, and sexual violence. She suggests that work on inequality would benefit from greater engagement with trauma studies and the intersectionality of socio-economic class, race, and gender as each inform conditions which impact virtue development. Like Lloyd, Guth raises the potential pitfall of virtue ethics’ overemphasis on the development of personal virtue without greater attention to the virtues developed amidst liberatory struggle, as so many liberation and womanist theologies indicate.
MT Dávila reflects on the neoclassical economic perspective of a market that is morally neutral, especially as Ward elucidates the ways wealth and poverty impact an agent’s ability to develop the moral life. She highlights religious, social, and cultural messages that entrench the moral imagination and create scotosis that prevents agents from perceiving the harms perpetuated by the systems of inequality in which we participate. Dávila powerfully illustrates existing self-reinforcing systems that compound inequality and further impair understanding the context of the socio-economic other with empathy and through solidarity.
10.3.24 |
Response
Virtues Great and Grand
One of the most important but least appreciated essays on the virtues was penned in 1960 by the Italian writer Natalia Ginzburg. Born of a Jew and a Catholic, raised an atheist, Ginzburg’s sensitivity to the subtleties of moral life is nearly unmatched—as is the elegance of her prose. Ginzburg begins her essay “The Little Virtues” by asserting that often we approach moral education with a focus on inculcating prudence in the narrow sense: thrift, caution, tact, and shrewdness. She charges that, instead, we ought to be focused on the “great virtues,” those that make for an exceptional life rather than a competent life, virtues like courage, generosity, frankness, and neighbor-love. The little virtues aim at coping with the risks of the world; the great virtues point beyond the world.
At the heart of Ginzburg’s essay is an account of what virtue looks like with respect to money. She reflects on the child who spends months saving up for an expensive item he covets. When he starts saving, money is just like any other object he favors, like rabbits or flowers. But as he saves, money takes on increasing significance. Finally, when he has enough money to buy the item he wants, he is inevitably disappointed – and lonely, without the money he grew to cherish for the potential happiness it represented. Compared to the potential of the money, the actual object it purchased seems quite dull. The child begins to prefer money over things.
Instead of encouraging a child to save up for a coveted object, Ginzburg suggests that “we should give him money to spend when there is money—because then he will learn to part with it without worrying about it or regretting it.”1 If tomorrow the child is poor, it will not be such a hardship, for he has not learned to worship money but rather he knows “how quickly it runs through our hands.”2 In sum, Ginzburg’s prescription is this: “The money we give our children should be given for no reason; it should be given indifferently so that they will learn to receive it indifferently; but it should be given not so that they learn to love it, but so that they learn not to love it, so that they realize its true nature and its inability to satisfy our truest desires, which are those of the spirit.”3
I take Kate Ward to be aspiring to an account of the virtues that is related to that put forward by Ginzburg. For Ward, having insufficient money to meet our basic needs leads to vice and having more money than required to meet our basic needs also leads to vice. Having just the right amount of money, somewhere around lower-middle-class status in the US, is the ideal context for the cultivation of the virtues. Ward suggests that everyone, and especially Christians, ought to be concerned with growing income inequality because it has detrimental effects on the moral health of the nation: inequality means more poor people and more rich people, so there are more vicious people. Drawing on social science research as well as the Christian tradition (in its liberal, North American, Catholic flavor, which now incorporates insights from liberation theologies), Ward makes the case that income inequality out to be addressed as an ethical issue, not just a political issue.
While Ward offers many examples of causal links between vice on one hand, and poverty and wealth, on the other, it strikes me that her project might be productively redescribed in Ginzburg’s terms. If the right relation to money is indifference and the wrong relation to money is to mystify it, to give it god-like power, poverty and wealth tend to promote the latter. Having about as much as one requires to meet one’s basic needs is the precondition for indifference to money. While sometimes one will be short and sometimes there will be extra, when the amount of money approximates needs it is possible, with effort and grace, to become the sort of person who does not fixate on money, as is the habit, in different ways, of both the poor and the rich. And indifference to money, Ginzburg observes, is the prerequisite to genuine generosity, allowing us to be attentive to and responsive to the needs and desires of those around us.
This strikes me as correct, and I appreciate Ward leading us toward an implication of this point for those in the academy: while there is a great deal of conversation about adjunct labor being under-compensated, there is not enough conversation about tenured faculty labor being over-compensated. If we want our educational institutions to cultivate the virtues but faculty are either too poor or too wealthy to develop the virtues themselves, the enterprise is bound to fail. We might say the same of religious communities in which the culture is set by the rich or upper-middle class: these will struggle mightily to become virtuous communities.
When I taught Ward’s book last year to a group of theology masters students, mainly with pastoral interests, the students treated her thesis as essentially uncontroversial. Wealth and income inequality are problems—to such an extent that they could fittingly be labeled moral crises. Students were appreciative of how Ward filled out the meaning of “moral” in this context. But about a third of the students were dissatisfied. They wanted to hear more about the need to transform our current economic system, and they worried that Ward’s focus on the virtues distracts from what they take to be the root causes of inequality.
This concern points to a general problem that I worry does not receive sufficient attention in our conversations about ethics, and particularly Christian ethics. How do we navigate the difference between the register of ethical analysis and that of political analysis? It is too simplistic to see these two registers as disjunct. There are cases where the politics of a context means that ethical analysis, while possible, is not apt. It might be possible to examine how memorializing war heroes promotes the virtues in the case of both heroes from the Confederacy and the Union, and to do that in a highly sophisticated way, using cutting-edge tools of ethical analysis. But such an enterprise is not apt because of the political context. That political context means that what appears to be virtue (in this example, developed by the Confederate monuments) is actually the simulacrum of virtue: particularly pernicious vice. It is only by shifting to the political frame that the true nature of supposed virtue becomes visible. The analogous worry, in the economic case addressed by Ward, is that the apparent virtues of the lower-middle class are simulacral given the political context (say, capitalism).
Put another way, it strikes me as more plausible that Ward’s analysis is correct when it is put in the following terms: a near-match between capacities and needs is the prerequisite to cultivating virtue. But adding money into this proposition, as shorthand for capacities, muddles matters. In the Communist Eastern bloc, in medieval Europe, or in pre-colonial North America, for example, it is plausible that for many people there was a near-match between capacities and needs—for many more people than holds today in the US and around the world. In such contexts, at least as they are romanticized, capacities are more relational than monetary: when someone has a need, that person can draw on a web of relationships to meet that need (rather than on an income stream). Calculating the per capita gross domestic product in such contexts obscures the relevant features of the near-match between capacities and needs—and also obscures political structures, forms of domination, that can block that near-match.
I think that the context of virtue that Ward identifies, what Ginzburg might call the necessary context for the cultivation of the great virtues, is aspirational, maybe eschatological
After systems of domination are overthrown, we will live in a way that our capacities nearly match our needs. Marx talks about this in terms of the end of alienation and the realization of species-being. Christians call it the land of milk and honey. And it strikes me as a grave confusion to talk about virtue as it manifests at the end of time in the same way we talk about virtue as it manifests in time, during the world.
Let’s identify a third species of virtue, neither small nor great. Let’s call these virtues grand. Small virtues tie us to the world. Great virtues are exercised after the world; when they are exercised in the world, they offer a foretaste of the eschaton. Grand virtues are those which we can only cultivate as we work together toward transforming the world. As Marx says somewhere, through struggle we become fit to govern ourselves. In a theological idiom, through struggle against domination, against false gods, we orient ourselves toward the one true God. Through struggle against domination—against racial domination, against patriarchy, against colonialism, and against capitalism—we discern the machinations of the powerful, we learn how to tap into the capacities of our community to respond to mastery, and we become attuned to the meanings of justice, care, prudence, solidarity, and fidelity when those virtues are stripped of the distortions imposed upon them by ideology, by the interests of the wealthy, powerful, and white. The grand virtues whither in those who accede to domination, from both sides of the relationship of domination. But no one fully accedes. Just as it is our nature to dominate, it is our nature to struggle against domination. When those struggles are amplified and when we join together in such struggle, in collective movements against domination, the grand virtues develop.
One worry I have about Ward’s argument is that it is precisely in the petite bourgeoisie, in the class where capacities and needs are most closely aligned, that struggle against domination is most often muted. Among the poor, with little to lose, it is natural to struggle against the systems that impoverish them—they are hindered only by bandwidth deficits (and by ideology, though ideology filters down to the poor only imperfectly, given the friction created by unmet needs). While the wealthy are obviously invested in preserving their wealth, excessive capacity to meet needs also opens space for a few of the wealthy to become artists and intellectuals, and for a few of these to align their interests with those of the poor, that is, to struggle. It is just the lower-middle class who can cultivate an indifference to money, and so an allergy to struggle. In sum, where the great virtues can be cultivated, the grand virtues are inhibited; where the grand virtues can be cultivated, the great are inhibited.
But this may not be the case anymore. Today, it is not clear that even the great virtues can be cultivated in the lower-middle class. Classically, the lower-middle class referred to small shopkeepers and family farmers. (For a couple decades after the Second World War, American factory workers imagined themselves to have ascended from the proletariat to the petite bourgeoisie, but as Gabriel Winant has recently, brilliantly shown, this was always illusory.)4 Today, the occupations of the lower-middle class, the seat of virtue according to Ward, increasingly involve small-scale management; they are the bureaucrats of the public and, especially, private sector. Middle managers, marketing specialists, project supervisors, and a whole lot of people in financial services and insurance back offices. They occupy what David Graeber analyzes as “bullshit jobs,” jobs that fulfill no social needs or are detrimental to society, jobs whose uselessness is perfectly evident to their holders.5 For those who work in “bullshit jobs,” their income may nearly meet their basic needs, but the jobs themselves are soul-draining and create deep moral damage, the result of realizing you are spending eight hours a day doing, essentially, nothing. This moral damage imposes a bandwidth tax that may have effects as significant as that imposed by poverty. In short, it is not clear that there are a substantial number of jobs left in the US and Europe that would create the conditions for the cultivation of the great virtues. On the contrary, as the wave of protest movements from Occupy Wall Street to Black Lives Matter demonstrates, we are seeing increasing opportunities across the classes to cultivate the virtues of struggle.
Finally, reading Ward’s book makes me wonder whether there is a sort of second-order virtue that has to do with appreciating moral luck, with attending to the ways fate puts us in situations that ease or hinder the cultivation of the virtues. Even after we have ended income inequality, fate will still play a role in determining how rocky the road is to flourishing, and this is something we ought to be ever-mindful of in ourselves and in the lives of those around us. Ward’s book helps to build our capacity for attentiveness in this regard. And it helps us notice how strong the ideology is that ties goodness to monetary success, poverty to failure.
Natalia Ginzburg, once again, has advice on how to cultivate this sensibility. Counter-intuitively, she argues that those charged with moral formation need to stop rewarding success and punishing failure:
Life rarely has its rewards and punishments; usually sacrifices have no reward, and often evil deeds go unpunished, at times they are even richly rewarded with success and money. Therefore it is best that our children should know from infancy that good is not rewarded and that evil goes unpunished; yet they must love good and hate evil, and it is not possible to give any logical explanation for this.6
In a sense, we are back to the primal point that Nietzsche famously makes and Elettra Stimilli has recently elaborated, about the connection between debt and guilt, between money and morality. The problem may not only be income inequality; deeper down, it may be about income itself, about the tendency of money to solidify and mystify a system of rewards and punishments that obscures the paradox at the heart of faith.
Natalia Ginzburg, “The Little Virtues,” in The Little Virtues, trans. Dick Davis (New York: Arcade, 1985), 104.↩
Ginzburg, “The Little Virtues,” 104.↩
Ginzburg, “The Little Virtues,” 105.↩
Gabriel Winant, The Next Shift: The Fall of Industry and the Rise of Health Care in Rust Belt America (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2021).↩
David Graeber, Bullshit Jobs: A Theory (New York: Simon & Schuster, 2018).↩
Ginzburg, “The Little Virtues,” 105–6.↩
Kate Jackson-Meyer
Response
Wealth, Misery, Happiness, and Flourishing Inequality
There is a growing genre of television dramas focused on the lives of the uberwealthy that has received significant public attention. Shows like Succession, Billions, and White Lotus, to name few, seem to have captured the imagination of many by revealing the extravagances of extreme wealth and the misery it creates. For instance, HBO’s four-season drama, Succession, chronicles the Roys, a media tycoon family, apparently loosely based on the Murdochs, as the siblings—Kendall (Jeremy Strong), Shiv (Sarah Snook), Roman (Kieran Culkin), and sometimes Connor (Alan Ruck)—incompetently and furiously jockey and betray each other, and anyone else in their way, in an effort to take over the family business from their father, Logan Roy (Brian Cox).1 They fight with an astonishing level of deprivation given that the stakes of failing seem so low—the winner inherits the family business and all its billions and the losers inherit billions of dollars without the headache of running a family business.
Part of the appeal of the show seems to be the assurance that many aspects of uberwealth are absurd. For instance, the show spawned commentary describing the “Succession era” phenomenon of “stealth wealth” or “silent luxury.”2 That is, luxury clothing that signifies its expense by being discreet, plain, and without branding. This was epitomized in the significant attention that Kendall Roy’s plain black $625 cashmere baseball cap received.3 I might be missing something here, but the joke seems to be on the uberwealthy, for there is no possible way a $625 cashmere baseball cap is near twenty times better than my (arguably overpriced) $30 Boston College wool baseball cap.
But most of the appeal of the show, I suspect, is a kind of schadenfreude we viewers take in watching the myriad ways that money leads to misery. For why else revel in the downfall of the Roy family except to be assured that life is worse with private jets and yachts? Although the show is wildly crass and often audacious, the characters are developed with enough nuance that is easy to imagine how the family dynamics could have gone a different way had the Roys not been cursed with all that money.
The characters treat each other in awful ways that easily map onto behaviors that Kate Ward warns about in her book, Wealth, Virtue, and Moral Luck.4 There is the unforgettable balcony argument scene in season 4 where the harsh exchanges between Shiv and her husband reveal that fidelity was always impossible given that money and power are the primary objectives for both of them.5 And the brothers, Kendall and Roman, display a complete lack of fortitude when they pressure their network to falsely call a presidential election in favor of the candidate who they believe will serve their interests at the expense of society.6 In numerous ways, the Roys typify Ward’s warnings about how money “as an end itself” and hyperagency can malform the wealthy (133–70). As a result, the Roys are anything but happy.
But Ward’s well-researched and insightful book uses the lens of wealth to make much more trenchant and challenging societal critiques than what is possible by simply criticizing the uberwealthy. Ward affirms the dignity of the poor and challenges a large swath of readers to recognize their own wealth and the negative moral effects it has on themselves and society. It may be entertaining and satisfying to watch the Roys crumble under the weight of their wealth, for as the blithely cynical German phrase goes, revealing a likely widespread moral failing, “Schadenfreude is the best type of freude.” But instead of falling into that mode, Ward does the hard work of challenging many readers of her book to introspect on how our relationships with money might be harming ourselves and those around us. It is laudatory and brave to raise these points and I admire Ward’s prophetic voice in this regard.
A central insight of Ward’s book is that in a capitalistic society one’s wealth (or lack thereof) determines one’s position to a range of choices/access to power, goods, activities, and opportunities. And that relationship to goods, services, opportunities, etc., is likely to encourage or thwart virtue in particular ways that may or may not be obvious. For Ward, this orientation to the world predicated on the moral luck of one’s economic situation has serious moral implications that have generally been overlooked.
To make her point, Ward works with two primary categories that are intentionally broad, wealth and poverty:
She defends these definitions for numerous reasons (118–32), and if her definition of wealth makes many academics uncomfortable, that is by design. She quips, “Perhaps attempts to define wealth feel especially fraught as specialists confront the risk of self-implication” (124). And she specifically wants readers of her book to consider that they might be wealthy, even if they are not in the 1 percent, and that this matters for virtue:
She joins David Cloutier and Sondra Ely Wheeler in criticizing Christian theology for permitting a “middle class exemption” that allows many of us to ignore the tradition’s admonitions against wealth (127). Ward boldly states:
Following this, Ward offers a brilliant description of the hyperagency of the wealthy that presents a challenge to middle-class and upper-class readers of the book by applying it more broadly than her source materials does. Ward writes that Paul Shervish defines hyperagency as such:
Wards explains that Shervish applies this to people with millions of dollars, but she thinks it applies to all people who satisfy her definition of wealth, that is to everyone with more than they need (134).
In this way, Ward presents a profound challenge to middle-class and upper-class readers, myself included, who might easily enjoy a critique of the Roys but who might let themselves off the hook when thinking about the ill effects of wealth. Ward’s sympathetic but unrelenting insistence that anyone who has more than they need is vulnerable to the vicissitudes of wealth and its relationship to the virtues of prudence, justice, solidarity, fidelity, humility, self-care, temperance, and fortitude (140–64) made reading her book not only academically edifying, but also personally challenging.
Furthermore, the urgency of Ward’s analysis is made especially clear in her attention to the ways that the demands of poverty can impinge on agency, forcing moral agents to choose between important obligations, such as caring for one’s own family and caring for others (175, 183), and result in “burdened virtues” (a concept from Lisa Tessman that Ward powerfully expands on, 171–208). Ward is clear that this is not victim-blaming (171–76); rather she calls our attention to the ways that economic imbalances put people in morally precarious situations that we can no longer ignore.
While I appreciate the demanding ethic Ward proposes built around her broad definitions of wealth and poverty, I do wonder whether utilizing only two categories is, ultimately, limiting. There are different levels of poverty and wealth and this seems to greatly affect what kind of moral luck (99–112) people are dealt. There seems to be a meaningful difference between the hyperagency that one is able to wield from having a surplus that allows one to spend on the occasional latte and fresh berries (which Ward is quite critical of, 136–37, 161) versus a Costco membership and Costco-sized boxes of berries versus surplus enough to save for retirement and sending children to college versus the Roy-level of surplus that allows one to buy political campaigns.
But while we can debate the definitions of wealth and poverty and a taxonomy of the possible subsections, this does not take away a central point of Ward’s work that also makes Succession so compelling—our interest in whether it is true that money doesn’t buy happiness, even though it is clear that a certain threshold of money is required to obtain the goods necessary for flourishing in this life in our capitalistic society. And Ward raises the stakes of this truism showing how money also does not buy virtue. Ward uses the contexts of wealth, poverty, and inequality to reveal challenges in the moral life because her ultimate concerns are individual and communal flourishing, what she describes as “human excellence” (47). Her references to inequality are generally related to economic matters, while at the same time calling us to view the human person and society in much more than economic terms, such as when she persuasively argues for a broader view of societal prosperity than GDP (18–19), and how she persuasively elucidates the many ills that income inequality causes (15–20). By bringing moral formation into the purview of analysis of inequality, Ward invites us to broaden the ways we understand inequality and prosperity.
Following this, I would like to consider the value of theology taking seriously individual and communal measures of well-being with special attention to the problem of “well-being inequality” and the prospects for this kind of data to guide public policy.7 There is a vast and growing literature in psychology, public health, and beyond on how to evaluate individuals, communities, and societies in reference to what is often called “well-being,” “life satisfaction,” “happiness,” or “flourishing,” all of which are meant to point to objective or subjective holistic assessments of life.8 Such measures provide a broad picture of people’s lives, and when considered at the level of communities and societies, can guide public health policies to work toward supporting the flourishing of individuals and society.9
There are numerous ways to measure well-being in the social science literature and a discussion of these is beyond the scope of what can be addressed here. To name one useful measure, the Flourishing Measure was developed at the Human Flourishing Program at Harvard where I am a post-doc. The Flourishing Measures is a twelve-question survey asking respondents to report on the following six domains of their lives: (1) happiness and life satisfaction; (2) mental and physical health; (3) meaning and purpose; (4) character and virtue; (5) close social relationships; and (6) financial and material stability.10 Using these areas to assess the flourishing of individuals and society offers a holistic and robust assessment that address various areas that are of concern to Ward and others.
Importantly, this kind of data paints a complex picture that, commiserate with Ward’s concerns, indicates that promoting well-being requires supporting numerous aspects of peoples’ lives. For instance, from this data it becomes clear that social connectedness is critical to well-being. Canadian economist, John Helliwell, explains the findings from the World Happiness Reports, based on Cantril’s ladder life satisfaction question:
This also highlights the need to expand how we assess inequality within a society. Helliwell explains the importance of emerging work on well-being inequality or “happiness inequality”:
Thus, attention should be given to how well-being or flourishing may be experienced unequally within societies and across nations, and public policies should work towards rectifying this. Studies have started to look at the problem of “flourishing inequality,” but more work must be done.13 For instance, one global well-being study shows that life satisfaction is higher in wealthier nations, while nations with less wealth score higher on meaning and purpose.14 So then, there are lessons about how to cultivate meaning and purpose that less wealthy nations can offer and that should be investigated further. The Global Flourishing Study, a five-year longitudinal study using the Flourishing Measure, will look into flourishing inequality in more depth.15
Policy aimed at addressing flourishing inequality is a hopeful way forward because it would be holistic in nature and would address not only economic and health factors, which absolutely must be addressed, but do so in a way that supports the whole person and communities. Such policies would likely complement many of Ward’s policy suggestions (216–17). Work in this vein could highlight the strengths of marginalized communities that could be instructive for promoting flourishing cohering with many of Ward’s reflection, such as how those in poverty may embody the virtue of solidarity (184–87). Importantly, policies that come out of this data can be led by the voices of the poor and vulnerable, as Ward suggests solutions should be (220). This is because many of these measures, such as the Flourishing Measure, are based on self-reports. And such data-led policies could both support the flourishing of marginalized communities and learn from their strengths. Policies that come out of flourishing inequality research are also likely to be better equipped to address the harms of wealth given that prosperity is assessed much more broadly than by economics alone. For as Helliwell explains, using well-being inequality as a guide “in turn suggests, but does not necessarily require, a policy framework that explicitly targets those most in misery.”16
I don’t know what the Roys would score on the Flourishing Measure, but I do like the idea that this kind of data zooms out to offer a robust view of prosperity where money is not an end in itself and where the struggles and strengths of the poor and marginalized can drive social policy in innovative and profound ways. And I am grateful for Ward’s prophetic voice challenging us to reexamine the moral implications of wealth and inequality, thus prompting personal and social change.
Natalie Jarvey, “‘Succession’: The Real People Who Inspired the HBO Hit,” Vanity Fair, March 23, 2023, https://www.vanityfair.com/hollywood/2023/03/succession-real-life-inspiration-rupert-murdoch.↩
Rachel Shin, “In the ‘Succession’ Era, Wardrobes of the Wealthy Are Subtler than Ever. The Rich Identify Each Other with Luxury That Only a Highly Trained Eye Can Detect,” Fortune, July 24, 2023, https://fortune.com/2023/07/24/stealth-wealth-clothing-succession/.↩
Amanda Mull, “There’s No Secret to How Wealthy People Dress,” The Atlantic, May 15, 2023, https://www.theatlantic.com/technology/archive/2023/05/stealth-wealth-fashion-trend-succession-tiktok/674065/.↩
Kate Ward, Wealth, Virtue, and Moral Luck: Christian Ethics in an Age of Inequality, Moral Traditions series, (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2021).↩
Xuanlin Tham, “Shiv and Tom’s Balcony Fight in Succession Is a Monumental Game-Changer,” British GQ, May 9, 2023, https://www.gq-magazine.co.uk/article/succession-season-4-episode-7-tom-shiv-fight.↩
Linda Holmes, “‘Succession’ Season 4, Episode 8: ‘America Decides,’” NPR, May 14, 2023, https://www.npr.org/2023/05/14/1175751402/succession-season-4-episode-8-america-decides.↩
John F. Helliwell, “Measuring and Using Happiness to Support Public Policies,” in Measuring Well-Being: Interdisciplinary Perspectives from the Social Sciences and the Humanities, ed. Matthew T. Lee, Laura D. Kubzansky, and Tyler J. VanderWeele (New York: Oxford University Press, 2021), 41.↩
Matthew T. Lee et al., Measuring Well-Being: Interdisciplinary Perspectives from the Social Sciences and the Humanities (New York: Oxford University Press, 2021).↩
Helliwell, “Measuring and Using Happiness to Support Public Policies,” 32.↩
Tyler J. VanderWeele, “On the Promotion of Human Flourishing,” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 114, no. 31 (August 2017): 8148–56, https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1702996114.↩
Helliwell, “Measuring and Using Happiness to Support Public Policies,” 39.↩
Helliwell, “Measuring and Using Happiness to Support Public Policies,” 41.↩
Sarah S. Willen, “Flourishing and Health in Critical Perspective: An Invitation to Interdisciplinary Dialogue,” SSM – Mental Health 2 (December 1, 2022): 100045, https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ssmmh.2021.100045.↩
Shigehiro Oishi and Ed Diener, “Residents of Poor Nations Have a Greater Sense of Meaning in Life than Residents of Wealthy Nations,” Psychological Science 25, no. 2 (February 2014): Abstract, https://doi.org/10.1177/0956797613507286.↩
“Baylor and Harvard Researchers Partner in Long-Term, Global Study of Human Flourishing,” October 29, 2021, https://hfh.fas.harvard.edu/news/baylor-and-harvard-researchers-partner-long-term-global-study-human-flourishing.↩
Helliwell, “Measuring and Using Happiness to Support Public Policies,” 41.↩
9.26.24 | Kate Ward
Reply
Response to Jackson-Meyer
It is an honor to have Wealth, Virtue, and Moral Luck featured as the topic of a Syndicate symposium. I’m deeply grateful to Sean Larsen, Cody Sandschafer and the Syndicate editorial board, to Sara Bernard-Hoverstad for her able shepherding of our conversation, and to the respondents for their generous and thoughtful contributions.
As an avid consumer of stories about the foolish or unhappy rich—from Jane Austen to Kevin Kwan to The White Lotus—I was delighted by Kate Jackson-Meyer’s turn to Succession to explore themes from my book. In her hands, these stories reveal a perennial tension: “our interest in whether it is true that money doesn’t buy happiness, even though it is clear that a certain threshold of money is required to obtain the goods necessary for flourishing in this life in our capitalistic society.” The interplay between money’s necessity for flourishing and its insufficiency to guarantee it forms the heart of her symposium contribution.
Jackson-Meyer’s journey to the heart of the matter made me think of how consistently Christian stories confront us with our human tendency to try, and fail, to summon happiness through material means. Fruit from the forbidden tree (Genesis 3); a tower to make a name for ourselves (Gen 11:1–9); a seat at the Teacher’s side (Mark 10:35–45); water to save us the endless trips to the well (John 4:4–42). These stories stick with us because we know better than the foolish protagonists: knowledge, fame, glory, satiety don’t come so easily. And yet, as Jackson-Meyer suggests, perhaps the persistence of wealthy morality tales like Succession means we have to keep testing our knowledge of this fact, like pressing a bruise: Are we sure the material thing doesn’t bring the immaterial good? Are we sure, now?
This loosely held certainty sits in tension—as Jackson-Meyer rightly points out—with the bedrock concern of Christian ethics with human flourishing. Indeed, up to a certain level, income directly translates into human flourishing. This is true not just for material measures of well-being such as food security and safe housing, but for less tangible goods like friendship. As I point out in the book, sociologists know that poorer people tend to have fewer friends, and spend less time with their friends, than those with more income (192). Higher-income people are more likely to have not only stable housing but also stable marriages. Jackson-Meyer’s evocation of holistic flourishing measures, about which I’ll say more later on, reminds us that material comfort can be necessary, but not sufficient, for holistic well-being, and this because it undergirds the achievement of those intangible goods that make up relational flourishing.
I agree with Jackson-Meyer that “there are different levels of poverty and wealth and this seems to greatly affect what kind of moral luck people are dealt.” My provocative choice to make the categories of poverty and wealth mutually exclusive and exhaustive of the range of economic positionality does, therefore, gloss over the real differences in experience Jackson-Meyer points out—for example, between the wealthy with Costco memberships and retirement accounts and those whose wealth affords influence over elections. Jackson-Meyer penetratingly suggests that gawking at the excesses of the fictional 1 percent is a convenient way for the middle-class “wealthy,” as I define them, to avoid interrogating our own political and moral situation with regard to economic life. Within Christian ethics, the unique moral and political position of the wealthiest 1 percent, 5 percent or whoever can afford election influence these days has already been named and critiqued when I sat down to write, for example, by Joerg Rieger and Rosemary Henkel-Rieger in Deep Solidarity and other works inspired by the Occupy Wall Street movement. My goal with the book, different from those who focus on the 1 percent, was to illuminate some of the ways the political and moral pitfalls of having more than we need actually do align with the political and moral pitfalls of 1 percent status.
I am glad Jackson-Meyer picked up on the example of buying berries as an example of the hyperagency of having more than we need, which remains for me one of the most potent examples of this in the book. My intent is not to “criticize” the ordinary luxury of buying berries (although I agree with David Cloutier’s critical evaluation of middle-class discretionary spending in The Vice of Luxury, and his call to spend less on ourselves, more on the needy and to spend what we do spend more thoughtfully.) When we take in portrayals of the very wealthy, like Succession, we ask ourselves what it must be like to spend so blithely on cashmere baseball caps, political influence and other expenses that are out of reach for most who have more than we need, and thus universally agreed to be luxuries. From a virtue perspective, Stephanie Land’s account of being unable to buy her daughter berries as a working-poor single mom challenges me to ask myself what it’s like for me to be able to buy those berries without a thought—so frequently that some go bad in our fridge—in a time, place, neighborhood where I know other parents cannot do the same. What does this taken-for-granted exercise of agency—indeed, of the hyperagency to waste a farmworker’s labor—do to my hopes for virtue? What responsibility does it place on me as a Christian hoping to play a part in building the reign of God?
This leads me to Jackson-Meyer’s welcome call for more theological attention to holistic measurements of wellbeing across populations and ensuing attention to “flourishing inequality,” that is, inequality in flourishing broadly defined. Certainly, the widespread intuition that extreme economic inequality is morally wrong is because of an equally correct intuition that economic inequality translates into inequality of flourishing. The more holistic Flourishing Measure challenges our economistic tendency to assume that economic growth or redistribution automatically translates into increased or more equal measures of flourishing. It points to additional “solutions, if we dare use that term” (to borrow an indispensable phrase from MT Dávila’s forthcoming symposium essay), such as promoting trust in business and government as a way to increase flourishing, whether or not increased or redistributed income is possible.
The Flourishing Measure and the World Happiness Reports reveal that human well-being is multifaceted, reliant on spiritual as well as material factors, and cannot be reduced to the material even as material resources play a large role in it, insights entirely consistent with Christian theological anthropology. Still, I think there will always be a place in theo-ethical inquiry for attention to economic inequality, more narrowly considered. This is because the Christian tradition consistently calls for material redistribution, on personal and social scales, when inequality coexists with need. Material redistribution may not be sufficient to guarantee greater equality of flourishing, but the significance of GDP per capita in World Happiness measures reminds us that it is a necessary component toward this goal. Moreover, the Christian tradition suggests that the holistic well-being of those who redistribute, as well as those who receive restitution, is at stake when we redistribute material goods in contexts of coexisting inequality and need.
The insight Jackson-Meyer cites, that “if average life evaluations are an appropriate measure of community welfare, then the effect of happiness inequality on life evaluations provides an empirical measure of a society’s aversion to inequality” is a hopeful note, a suggestion that it might be possible to quantitatively demonstrate the conviction of Christian anthropology that our well-being is bound up with, indeed might demonstrably rise and fall with, the well-being of others. The efforts of Jackson-Meyer and her colleagues are indispensable for communicating this insight of humanistic and spiritual traditions in a language and with an institutional authority even the vicious, fictional tycoons of Succession might find themselves moved to take seriously.
Thank you, Kate.