Theology in the Flesh
By
10.2.17 |
Symposium Introduction
At the beginning of his defining book, Totality and Infinity, Emmanuel Levinas offers the following provocative synopsis of what he takes to be the history of metaphysics, which serves as the backdrop of his own account of the absolute alterity found in the ethical relation:
“The true life is absent.” But we are in the world. Metaphysics arises and is maintained in this alibi. It is turned toward the “elsewhere” and the “otherwise” and the “other.” For in the most general form it has assumed in the history of thought it appears as a movement going forth from a world that is familiar to us, whatever be the yet unknown lands that bound it or that it hides from view, from an “at home” which we inhabit, toward an alien outside-of-oneself, toward a yonder. (Levinas 1969, p. 33)
For Levinas, the metaphysical “alibi” is such that we are stable in ourselves and, thus, able to move beyond ourselves toward this objective order that lies beyond the illusory world of embodied sense and meaning. Epistemology as a search for that which is transcendentally stable forms much of the general metaphysical account of numerous philosophers from Plato to Hegel, and beyond. Famously, or perhaps infamously depending on who you ask, the postmodern turn in philosophy (in both the continental and also the analytic traditions), amounts to a humbling of such epistemic pretense regarding the narrative of metaphysical stability. The “alibi,” as it were, has begun to wear thin and questions have rightly been raised about whether or not it remains plausible. The consequences of such questions on human inquiry are significant indeed.
In the wake of this general postmodern awareness, the issue that now presses upon us is not how to get beyond ourselves to some sort of stable objective reality, but how best to understand who it is that we are as confronted by the epistemic realities that attend embodied, contextual existence. In this way, postmodernism does not preclude metaphysical realism, but simply the idea that we could somehow have access to that reality outside of where it is that we currently find ourselves. We are in the world. Whatever true life there is, if it is to be known by us, must be available to us as the beings we are, not the beings we would like to be if we somehow could escape the limitations of physicality and finitude. Indeed, it is precisely because of such limitations that the task of inquiry presents itself to us as a task in which to engage ever more deeply, rather than as a goal to be finally achieved. The end of inquiry, if there is such a thing, is not fixed and waiting for us, but stands as the vanishing point of the human condition itself. When inquiry stops, so does our finitude. Since it doesn’t seem like we are going to become infinite anytime soon, inquiry continues . . . but now humbly aware of itself as a contingent human practice. Thinking is no longer best conceived as a divine activity in which humans are able to participate insofar as they overcome their current situation and obtain direct access to that “elsewhere” and that “yonder” of which Levinas speaks, and toward which traditional metaphysical inquiry has striven.
What is especially striking about this postmodern realization is that it is not at all distinctively postmodern. Instead, it is quite ubiquitously, and extremely mundanely, human . . . all too human. We are bodies in motion. Inquiry amounts to bodies asking questions. Accordingly, regardless of our discipline, our training, or our discursive goals, we should all be attentive to the ways in which our bodies form the ground from which any such inquiry could spring forth and become categorized as philosophy, or theology, or psychology, or sociology, or whatever. Advances in cognitive science, and especially cognitive linguistics, have helped to refocus our attention away from the Truth (always with a capital-T) “out there” to the inescapable truth (whether with a capital or not) that language is always a product of one’s embodied (prelinguistic) experiences. Language may or may not be the house of being, but embodiment is the soil upon which any such house would be able to be built.
As obvious as it might seem to say that we only speak and think as we do because of the vocal chords and brains that we have, this realization is often ignored or even outright rejected due to two general worries. On the one hand, this account of embodiment and its impact on language and concepts might be viewed as metaphysically restrictive. On the other hand, this account can also be read as epistemically (and ethically) reductive. In the first case, one might point to thinkers such as Jacques Derrida, who is sometimes read as suggesting that since we can’t escape our perspectives that there really is nothing other than these perspectives—there is no state of affairs by which one perspective could be deemed better than any other. In the second case, one might offer any number of reductive physicalist accounts of knowledge and moral theory. When confronted with the options of problematic metaphysical anti-realism or problematic scientistic reductionism, perhaps it is better to abandon the assumptions that led to such options.
However, many scholars have rightly demonstrated that the implications of cognitive linguistics and postmodern epistemology avoid both of these worries. In fact, no metaphysical implications follow at all from a postmodern awareness of embodied human inquiry and the impact of lived experience on our speech and thought. All that follows is an increased humility regarding the pretentions to being able to get beyond ourselves to check what it is that we claim to know. Whether or not Derrida engages in a non sequitur, we shouldn’t do so. Just because we can’t know Truth other than as engaged and interpreted as truth available to bodies like us doesn’t mean that there is no Truth, but simply that we can’t stop being who we are in order to know it. As Kierkegaard’s Johannes Climacus rightly warns, to try to know objective Truth in this way would be so inhuman that it is not clear that any existing individual could recommend it. We are stuck with ourselves, but that doesn’t mean that we are all that there is (see Kierkegaard 1992).
Similarly, reductive physicalism might indeed be true, but it is not at all required by the conclusions drawn by cognitive linguistics. That our speech and thought is shaped (necessarily and inescapably) by embodied experience doesn’t mean that we are merely, or only, or reducible to vocal chords and brains. It simply means that even if we are ultimately souls, or minds, we are now unable to understand anything outside of the embodied lived experience that forms our framework for meaning. So, just because we can’t make sense of disembodied ethical decision, for example, doesn’t mean that there are not moral facts. Just because we can’t know reality as God does, say, doesn’t mean that there is not divine knowledge of reality. It simply means that moral facts and divine knowledge would only be knowable by us if they are knowable by the sorts of beings that we are. This should seem trivial because it is. Again, the upshot of postmodernism is not something new and radical about how to conceive of ourselves, but something deeply universal to the human condition that has simply been forgotten at various points in our history—viz., being concerned about giving an alibi can often prevent us from being concerned about speaking truly. Cognitive linguistics, even if a recently emerging field, is not itself suggesting something that we didn’t know previously, but simply helping us understand how it is that we know anything at all.
One of the truly slow adopters of these realizations about embodiment and its impact on inquiry and discourse is Christian theology, and especially Evangelical Christian theology. Perhaps this hesitancy is due to the reasons mentioned above. Indeed, surely metaphysical anti-realism and reductive physicalism would pose serious problems for the worldviews of many within Christian faith communities. Unfortunately, though, adopting such problematic interpretations leads to a genuinely missed opportunity for theological discourse to be maximally relevant to the human condition—the condition to which faith is, itself, supposed to speak most directly. In his new book, Theology in the Flesh: How Embodiment and Culture Shape the Way We Think about Truth, Morality, and God, John Sanders sets out to correct these misconceptions and demonstrate with clarity and precision the resources offered by cognitive linguistics for both Christian theology and Christian life. This book is comprehensive in its scholarship and probing in its challenge to the complacency that so often characterizes Christian thinking.
The participants in this symposium are Bonnie Howe, James Van Slyke, Sharon L. Baker Putt, and Scot McKnight. They all offer careful engagements with Sanders’s thought but all apply it to different areas of intellectual and religious concern. First, Howe focuses on the way that cognitive linguistics impacts moral interpretation. Then, Van Slyke turns to questions of political existence and the dominant metaphors used to situate individuals into social groups. Next, Baker Putt moves into a more directly theological vein and considers traditional models of the atonement in order to explore new resources offered by cognitive linguistics for avoiding the moral problems associated with the satisfaction and penal substitution theories. Finally, Scot McKnight considers theological epistemology and the possible ways that cognitive linguistics can invite a better awareness of how specific theological claims might be read by different individuals and groups because of different social histories.
Ultimately, in these essays, and in Sanders’s replies to each of them, what we find is a robust demonstration of how humility and hospitality need not lead to a watered-down homiletics. Standing confidently within one’s religious tradition, and engaging confessionally in the theological reflection occurring within that tradition, should not be threatened by an awareness of one’s own embodied finitude. Indeed, in light of the Christian notion of kenosis, it seems much more likely that we are better able to understand the account of God revealed in Christian scriptures when we no longer attempt to overcome our embodiment, but instead stand, in our full fleshy reality, in a personal relation to a God who took on flesh in order to be related to us. Although Levinas provides a profound account of how ethics requires a relation to the absolutely other, Christianity, at least according to the model of it presented by the authors in this symposium, shows how the absolutely other is not lost in mystical distance, but perhaps found most radically, most intimately, most humanly, when we realize that all knowledge of God is embodied knowing.
References
Kierkegaard, Søren. 1992. Concluding Unscientific Postscript to Philosophical Fragments Vol. I. Ed. and trans. Howard V. Hong and Edna H. Hong. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Levinas, Emmanuel. 1969. Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority. Trans. Alphonso Lingis. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.
10.9.17 |
Response
Engaging John Sanders
John Sanders offers an excellent introduction to embodiment and theology in Theology in the Flesh: How Embodiment and Culture Shape the Way We Think about Truth, Morality, and God. Sanders provides a helpful and comprehensive overview of current views in embodied cognition, a model of human cognitive activity that prioritizes systems of the entire body and motor action in the world. Embodied cognition does not view thoughts as abstracted from the world or “inside” the head; rather thought is composed of metaphors and schemas based on motor actions performed in the world, neural network systems of the brain, and the physiological systems of the body.
When we describe a concept such as a romantic love, we use various metaphors based on our embodiment to describe the experience. So persons “fall in” love when a relationship begins, and experience “bumps in the road” when relationship difficulties arise, which may lead them to “go their separate ways” when the relationship ends. Thus, we use a motor experience like taking a walk or a hike to describe a more ambiguous concept like romantic love. Since all persons are bodies, embodied experience provides a shared foundational frame for understanding a variety of conceptual forms that may be difficult to describe. Most humans go through similar experiences in their early motor development, thus it stands to reason that many cultural forms would emerge based on these shared experiences.
The use of embodied cognition to help understand various theological concepts is in some ways a natural extension of the move to a physicalist understanding of the person in theology. In the Christian tradition, dualism was often the assumed ontological view of humanity where persons were composed of an immaterial soul and a physical body. From a Neoplatonic perspective, which heavily influenced the writings of Augustine and many foundational theological treatises in the Western tradition, the soul was that which was closest to God and most clearly the part of humanity that was made in his image (Cary 2000). Many theologians and Christian philosophers have embraced various forms of physicalism or emergent monism as an ontological view of the person who is not composed of a disembodied mind or soul plus a body (Clayton 2004; Green 2008). Murphy’s nonreductive physicalism attempts to integrate insights from the cognitive neurosciences and contemporary philosophy of mind to view the person as physical without the reduction of the person to some form of biological determinism or materialism (Murphy 2006). Although debates will continue on the type of physicalism that is most resonant with theological categories, the turn to physicalist views of the person makes embodied cognition an important avenue for understanding theological discourse because if our bodies are the primary ontological substance that constitutes the person then understanding the role of the body in the construction of a religious tradition will be essential.
Sanders uses embodied cognition as a framework for understanding many different aspects of the Western Religious tradition including our understanding of truth, the foundations of morality based in embodiment, various Christian doctrines, and conceptions of God. Each of these topics is interesting in its own right, but I’ll limit myself to the topic of morality because much of my own research has focused on that topic. Sanders’s work using embodied cognition to understand theological and political categories presents an opportunity for a fruitful dialogue on contemporary American politics. Embodied cognition (and the related discipline of evolutionary psychology) provides a framework for a better understanding of the polarization in contemporary American politics in that persons are using different types of embodied metaphors and adaptive cognition to process religious and political information. These sciences can be used to understand how these stark differences emerged and provide a shared psychological language that both conservatives and liberals could use to comprehend political and religious differences and better understand the perspective of the other side.
A strong argument can be made for the usage of different unconscious embodied cognitive systems in moral judgment. One of the strongest of these systems is disgust, which is an evolved system that helped to protect our evolutionary ancestors from parasites, disease, and infection. Any time you’ve left milk in the refrigerator for too long and were unwise and performed a smell test on it, olfactory cues activated the disgust system, which immediately identified the sour milk and instantaneously gave you the motivation to throw it out quickly. The disgust system works well not because it uses reflective reason but because it works at the unconscious level to provide a strong motivational cue to get rid of the disgusting substance quickly. It is also biased toward over-detecting false positives since it is ultimately in our best interest to get rid of a potentially infected substance rather than to take the chance that it may be unsafe. Thus, once a person is in a state of disgust it is often difficult to untether the unconscious judgment from our current processing situation.
Several studies have demonstrated the role of disgust in moral judgments. When sitting at a disgusting desk (sticky, with gum attached to it, dirty) or when smelling something foul (fart spray), persons are more likely to make negative moral judgments regarding someone’s behavior and when arbitrary words are hypnotically paired with the disgust response, persons are more severe in their moral judgments (Schnall, Haidt, Clore & Jordan 2008; Wheatley & Haidt 2005). Inducing disgust through olfactory cues increases negative views of gay men (Inbar, Pizarro & Bloom 2011). Based on this and other social psychological research, Haidt developed the social intuitionist model (SIM) of moral judgment (Haidt 2001). This model argues that moral judgments are primarily intuitive in that evolutionary adaptive programs, such as disgust, play the dominate role in moral judgment and reason is an ad hoc justification for our intuitions. Based on empirical evidence from multiple sources, five primary moral foundations were identified with links to our evolutionary heritage: care/harm, fairness/cheating, loyalty/betrayal, authority/subversion, and sanctity/degradation (Graham et al. 2013).
Haidt demonstrates the embodied nature of morality and the important role that evolved moral intuitions play in moral judgment. For some, there may be a concern for a type of biological determinism, where evolution or moral intuitions determine moral judgment, but I think this would be a mischaracterization. Although intuitions form the basis of moral judgment, the types of morality paired with specific intuitions will vary based on cultural factors and experience. For example, in American politics, conservatives and liberals emphasize different types of moral foundations with liberals emphasizing care/harm and fairness/cheating while conservatives emphasize loyalty/betrayal, authority/subversion, sanctity/degradation (Haidt & Graham 2007). Thus part of the reason why American politics has become so divided is because they are emphasizing different moral foundations activating different contrasting intuitions, which contributes to the inability for liberals and conservatives to understand the perspective of the other.
When a particular political view (typically from the opposite spectrum of one’s personal political views) is paired with a powerful embodied response such as disgust, it becomes very difficult to have a fruitful exchange on political differences. Since evolution designed disgust to be non-reflective, automatic and quick to respond, this embodied motivation will often override any attempt at reason, even in the most open-minded of persons. Sanders highlights a similar and important pattern of parental metaphors that are used as intuitions to help conceptualize God (Froese & Bader 2015; Lakoff 2002). These metaphors work in concert with moral foundations to provide an unconscious framework for the fusing of American politics with a particular religious narrative. This is one of the real opportunities for embodied cognition, it provides part of the explanation for the deep cultural divides in America and could be used as a shared scientific language for unpacking the roots of disunity.
Many liberals continue to be baffled at how Donald Trump won the election. Most polls had Hillary Clinton winning and with the video footage surfacing of Trump bragging about his sexual exploits it seemed like his campaign was in a downward spiral. However, Trump did win the election and embodiment, in terms of our evolutionary heritage, may be able to help explain why a man that most democrats and liberals would most likely characterize as repulsive, unintelligent, and barbaric is now president. The primary voter for Trump was male and in fact if just men had voted Trump would have won in a landslide (Silver 2016). One poll identified that the best predictor of support for Trump was not race, income, or education, but propensity toward authoritarianism (MacWilliams 2016). Authoritarianism is a preference for and willingness to defer to perceived dominance in others, usually males (Rueden 2016). This is also supported by the conservative association with the moral foundation of authority/subversion and an authoritative God. Humans show a tendency to prefer leaders who are taller and exhibit more masculine features, which is associated with higher levels of testosterone and aggression in men (Little, Burriss, Jones & Roberts 2007; Re, DeBruine, Jones & Perrett 2013). These qualities are most often desired during threatening situations or fearful contexts. Trump’s acceptance speech illustrated the type of fearful and threatening perceptions often associated with his campaign.
Another factor that contributed to his win is also related to embodiment, viz. human sexuality. Recent research has linked different aspects of religiosity to evolved mating strategies and there may be reason to suspect that similar evolutionary adaptations may have influenced views of Trump (Slone & Van Slyke 2015; Van Slyke 2016). The different forms of authoritarianism associated with Trump could be related to the types of male display behaviors used to attract a mate. Although males made up the largest voting block for Trump, a significant percentage of women voted for Trump as well (41%), which is fairly similar to the percentage of women who voted for Romney in 2012 (44%) (Clement & Alcantara 2016). Part of the preference (or tolerance) for Trump may be related to female mate preferences. Women show preferences for more masculine faces and lower-pitched masculine voices especially during peak levels of fertility during their menstrual cycle (Puts 2005). Females also show preferences for self-assurance, social dominance, self-confidence, and competitiveness during peak levels of fertility (Gangestad, Simpson, Cousins, Garver-Apgar & Christensen 2004).
During ovulation, females report higher levels of marital satisfaction with male partners who are relatively more masculine (Meltzer 2017). Despite the fact that egalitarian marriages are preferred by a significant number of men and women, couples with more traditional gender roles tend to have higher levels of sexual frequency in contrast to more egalitarian gender roles (Kornrich, Brines & Leupp 2013). This research does not indicate that mate preferences determine female voting choices, but demonstrates possible influences on voting behaviors that would apply to males and females. For example, during the 2012 election, it was found that during ovulation single females were less religious, more liberal, and more likely to vote for Barack Obama, while women in committed relationships were more religious, more conservative, and were more likely to vote for Mitt Romney (Durante, Rae & Griskevicius 2013). This is an interesting finding because it suggests that ovulation will affect women’s preferences differently based on their marital status and current reproductive goals. This type of research in evolutionary psychology may provide some new avenues for understanding a wide range of behaviors in both politics and religion.
Sanders’s work presents a helpful new paradigm for understanding theology from an embodied cognition perspective. Understanding the embodied intuitive moral foundations may shed light on unconscious processing that effects how moral and religious concepts are formed and transmitted. Mating preferences and display behaviors may help to shed light on preferences in political candidates and leaders from a variety of religious domains. By looking at the psychological science behind these views, it may provide a common language to help understand differences in political persuasion and how persons can form perspectives that seem so alien to our own understanding of the world.
References
Cary, P. (2000). Augustine’s invention of the inner self: The legacy of a Christian platonist. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Clayton, P. (2004). Mind and emergence: From quantum to consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Clement, S., & Alcantara, C. (2016). “2016 Election Exit polls.” The Washington Post. Retrieved from https://syndicate.network.washingtonpost.com/graphics/politics/2016-election/exit-polls/
Durante, K. M., Rae, A., & Griskevicius, V. (2013). “The fluctuating female vote: Politics, religion, and the ovulatory cycle.” Psychological Science, 24(6), 1007–1016. http://doi.org/10.1177/0956797612466416
Froese, P., & Bader, C. (2015). America’s four gods: What we say about God and what that says about us. New York: Oxford University Press.
Gangestad, S. W., Simpson, J. A., Cousins, A. J., Garver-Apgar, C. E., & Christensen, P. N. (2004). “Women’s preferences for male behavioral displays change across the menstrual cycle.” Psychological Science, 15(3), 203–207. http://doi.org/10.1111/j.0956-7976.2004.01503010.x
Graham, J., Haidt, J., Koleva, S., Motyl, M., Iyer, R., Wojcik, S. P., & Ditto, P. H. (2013). “Moral foundations theory: The pragmatic validity of moral pluralism.” Advances in Experimental and Social Psychology, 47, 55–130.
Green, J. (2008). Body, soul, and human life: The nature of humanity in the Bible. Studies in Theological Interpretation. Grand Rapids: Baker Academic.
Haidt, J. (2001). “The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment.” Psychological Review, 108, 814–834.
Haidt, J., & Graham, J. (2007). “When Morality Opposes Justice: Conservatives Have Moral Intuitions that Liberals may not Recognize.” Social Justice Research, 20(1), 98–116. http://doi.org/10.1007/s11211-007-0034-z
Inbar, Y., Pizarro, D. A., & Bloom, P. (2011). “Disgusting Smells Cause Decreased Liking of Gay Men.” Emotion, 12, 23–27. http://doi.org/10.1037/a0023984.supp
Kornrich, S., Brines, J., & Leupp, K. (2013). “Egalitarianism, housework, and sexual frequency in marriage.” American Sociological Review, 78(1), 26–50. http://doi.org/10.1177/0003122412472340.
Lakoff, G. (2002). Moral politics: How liberals and conservatives think. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Little, A. C., Burriss, R. P., Jones, B. C., & Roberts, S. C. (2007). “Facial appearance affects voting decisions.” Evolution and Human Behavior, 28(1), 18–27.
MacWilliams, M. (2016). “The one weird trait that predicts whether you’re a Trump supporter: And its not gender, age, income, race, or religion.” Politico. Retrieved from http://home/163979.cloudwaysapps.com/esbfrbwtsm/public_html.politico.com/magazine/story/2016/01/donald-trump-2016-authoritarian-213533
Meltzer, A. L. (2017). “Wives with masculine husbands report increased marital satisfaction near peak fertility.” Evolutionary Behavioral Sciences, 11(2), 161–172. http://doi.org/10.1037/ebs0000083
Murphy, N. (2006). Bodies and souls or spirited bodies? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Puts, D. A. (2005). “Mating context and menstrual phase affect women’s preferences for male voice pitch.” Evolution and Human Behavior, 26(5), 388–397. http://doi.org/10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2005.03.001
Re, D. E., DeBruine, L. M., Jones, B. C., & Perrett, D. I. (2013). “Facial cues to perceived height influence leadership choices in simulated war and peace contexts.” Evolutionary Psychology, 11(1), 89–103.
Rueden, von, C. (2016). The conversation about Trump should consider the evolution of men’s political psychology. Retrieved May 15, 2017, from evolution-institute.org
Schnall, S., Haidt, J., Clore, G. L., & Jordan, A. H. (2008). “Disgust as embodied moral judgment.” Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 34(8), 1096–1109. http://doi.org/10.1177/0146167208317771
Silver, N. (2016). “Election update: Women are defeating Donald Trump.” FiveThirtyEight.com. Retrieved from http://fivethirtyeight.com/features/election-update-women-are-defeating-donald-trump/
Slone, D. J., & Van Slyke, J. A. (2015). The attraction of religion: A new evolutionary psychology of religion. New York: Bloomsbury Academic.
Van Slyke, J. A. (2016). “Can sexual selection theory explain the evolution of individual and group-level religious beliefs and behaviors?” Religion, Brain & Behavior, 1–7. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/2153599X.2016.1249922
Wheatley, T., & Haidt, J. (2005). “Hypnotic disgust makes moral judgments more severe.” Psychological Science, 16, 780–784.
10.23.17 |
Response
Anthropogenic Theology
I didn’t know what to expect when I was asked to participate in this forum about John Sanders’s Theology in the Flesh (Sanders 2016), but I knew I needed to become more aware of cognitive linguistics, I wanted to read more from Sanders because I have found him in the past to be courageous and informed, and so I was unprepared for the delight the book brought. Theology in the Flesh is both an introduction to cognitive linguistics—and so far as I know a very good introduction—and an exploration of its significance for a variety of theological topics, not the least of which explored are God, atonement and scriptural interpretation. Sanders has a foot in two streams: in the stream of academic cognitive linguistics and mostly evangelical theological interests. The frisson is palpable at times and more than fun.
Cognitive Linguistics
I begin by bringing to the surface some of Sanders’s understanding of cognitive linguistics. What Sanders and others think is that “cognitive linguistics is a game changer for the way religious believers construct theological meaning” (Sanders 2016, p. 4). But what is it? “Understanding language entails comprehension of how both writer and reader are thinking, and the thoughts of both are shaped by human embodiment and cultural communities because human thinking is deeply dependent upon both the particular types of bodies humans have and the specific cultural communities we inhabit” (4–5). Again, “Humans are embodied beings and the particular kind of body we have, with our specific sensory and motor systems, constrains our cognitive abilities” (6). But all this leads to a full display of the heart of Sanders’s proposals, and at the heart are these five claims: “Human cognition is dependent upon embodied human experience. All human understanding is perspectival. Meaning is encyclopedic. Linguistic meaning is grounded in usage and experience. Linguistic meaning is flexible and dynamic” (19–20). In one crisp sentence we get this: “Human knowing is situated embodied knowing” (23). The implication is potent: “Thus, all human embodied knowing is and can be no other than ‘anthropogenic’” (23). That conclusion and term “anthropogenic” may not be a game changer but it is a necessity, both to admit and to bring into play at all times.
Words on a page, that is words when I read Paul’s letter to Philemon or Jesus’ words in the Sermon on the Mount, are not isolable from their authors or the person whom an author (in the case of Jesus) may be more or less quoting. What are words on a page? As mind-to-mind, or better yet person-to-person, communication units words “serve as points of access or prompts to incredible stores of knowledge. Words do not come with fully stipulated prepackaged meanings” (25). This is vital to understanding what the Bible is. It cannot be said often enough. Language, words, texts, and the like are communications between minds, not simply a text with a mind/reader. Thus, “language is fundamentally about meaning between persons” (188). It makes a big difference when the Bible is seen as one author—a human-divine author mind you—communicating with a reader in a community or even a reader alone, than if it is taken as a TEXT communicating with a READER.
Objective Truth
John Sanders makes—and I don’t know the subject well enough to know if it is distinct to him—a contribution (at least to me) when he turns to objective truth—especially what happens to objective truth when it moves into the realm of cognitive linguistics. There are, as is well known, three major theories of truth: truth as correspondence (to reality), coherence (with reality) and truth as pragmatics. Sanders is persuaded that cognitive linguistics makes a singular contribution to whether or not we can know truth objectively, and he here shifts out of the realism vs. non-realism gambit. Sanders accepts “objective truth,” but explains how cognitive linguistics alters the way that both terms are determined, since they are often overdetermined (by well-meaning fundamentalists, some of whom won’t listen) or underdetermined (by well-meaning postmoderns, some of whom are cynical). He says, “Given our embodied cognitive abilities, humans are predisposed to experience entities in some specific ways rather than others” (88). That is, “The sky is blue for us, given our species-specific perceptual capacities” (89). Some will raise the red flag or warn of the slippery slope, but Sanders will have none of that: “this does not mean that all human concepts are arbitrary social constructions” (89). We are embodied knowers and bodies impact our knowing. That means, truth, “like meaning, is related to understanding and human understanding is embodied. In other words, truth, for humans, depends upon the way we understand our world through our embodied experiences, which includes both our sensorimotor capacities as well as culture” (95). Again, “Cognitive linguists believe there is truth as correspondence to reality, but it is truth according to our embodied sensory and cognitive capacities. It is a species-specific understanding of reality” (97). Here he says it in the best way possible: “Humans have objective truth, for some things, so long as by ‘objective’, we mean the way things appear in relation to our normally operating species-specific cognitive abilities” (97). Can I know you, can I know someone you tell me about, can I know a person described in a book, can I know Jesus—and know these persons objectively? Yes, so far as I am an embodied knower know other embodied persons. He offers a form of chastened, critical but hopeful realism.
In a recent discussion in theological circles the apocalyptic Paul folks have made larger claims for how we know—only through apocalypse—and in making such claims they have argued that something like N. T. Wright’s method of knowing through history cannot render results that are right for knowledge of God. That is, one cannot study history and conclude something about God. One can only experience the revelation of God to know God, and once one knows that revelation one can know everything else. One wonders from reading Theology in the Flesh if apocalyptic epistemology has not denied the reality of embodied knowing (see Adams 2015). As Sanders puts it, “Thus, objective truth always refers to the way humans understand a situation” (97). Here one transcends in some ways critical realism but knows the limits of human knowing because of embodiment.
To be sure, we are not God and God does not know as we know. “Hence, God’s way of understanding is non-anthropogenic” (98). The issue is not what God knows or how God knows—who can know that but God? But in our Christian faith we make claims that God has spoken to us—in word and in flesh and in Spirit and that God continues to speak to us. How then does God do this? Cognitive linguistics advances the discussion; in the words of Sanders, “But if God is to communicate with us, what is God to do? God will have to communicate by thinking like a human and utilize particular cultural forms of meaning” (98). Which diminishes the confidence of the apocalyptic knower and keeps the historian humble. Which is to say, Sanders very often keeps us aware that embodied situated knowing has its limits, some of them severe: “The emphasis in cognitive linguistics on embodiment and culture leads to the conclusion that the quest for timeless and culture-free truth is a dead end for humans” (7–8).
One of the more fascinating discussions in this book, and one senses Sanders could easily have made this three volumes, is about “categories.” I often hear people wistfully wish for a non-categorized world: no evangelical vs. liberal/progressive, no Calvinist vs. Arminian, no male vs. female, and no African American vs. White American. Ah, Sanders observes, that world does not exist for embodied situated knowers. As he explains, “Humans need order to live meaningfully, and placing objects and experiences into categories is one important way of achieving this goal” (27). To be sure, categories have been abused, especially in the Western tradition: “Since the time of Socrates, Western thought has generally thought of categories as containers with clearly shaped boundaries, so we know what is inside and what is outside” (27). Most importantly, as one can hear on any blog or any discussion of who is and who is not an evangelical, “membership in a category is all-or-nothing . . . degrees of membership are not allowed . . .” (28).
But cognitive linguistics throws dust into the eyes of such neatness even if watchdogs will not listen. Most importantly, when it comes to categories there is a further specification that leads both to a reshaped way of thinking about ideas and morals: “humans normally categorize by means of a ‘prototype,’ a mental concept of exemplars that best represent instances of a category rather than by means of the necessary conditions of the classical theory” (30–31). In my field of New Testament studies, when we talk about various approaches to Jesus or to Paul we think of major proponents and let them speak for a class of other scholars: Dom Crossan on Jesus, Beverly Gaventa on the apocalyptic Paul, Jimmy Dunn on the new perspective, and Stephen Westerholm on the old or Reformation perspective. In a recent attempt to map such trends in Paul, I asked a few authors I know if the synthesis described them and they said “no.” If one wants to describe the new perspective then, describe solo scholars, use the prototype alone: E. P. Sanders, J. D. G. Dunn or N. T. Wright, but don’t try to combine them into a synthesis. Why? Because we think in terms of prototypical categories. Sanders, John that is, observes, “Of importance to education is that people learn a category more easily and accurately if they are initially exposed to only the most representative exemplars of the category” (32). Of course, one scholar is not the whole and so cognitive linguists think in terms of radiation: “The term ‘radial’ is commonly used by cognitive linguists to denote the idea that category membership radiates outward from the center or prototypical members” (32).
But this leads to categories, which leads to prototypes, which leads to moral exemplars, which leads to the stubborn exaltation of such exemplars in The Gospel Coalition, Missio Alliance or charismatics. That is, the exemplars for TGC are John Piper, Tim Keller, and D. A. Carson. They can do no wrong among their crowds for that would destroy them as exemplars. Among Missio Alliance, I think of my colleague David Fitch, and when it comes to charismatics their heroes seem to be Gordon Fee and Craig Keener. In quoting a study, Sanders says, “The authors argue that moral exemplars carry special salience as the center of a category and because communities encourage members to imitate the exemplars. Communities identify genuine human flourishing by highlighting paragons who show how to live morally and virtuously in the decisions they make and the ways they relate to others” (159). Cognitive linguists, so I am arguing, provide for us an explanation for why it is that some people are exalted to such a level and why anyone who does not fit the paragon exemplar status is either silenced or somehow demonized and scapegoated.
Theology in the Flesh, however, is a book mostly about how cognitive linguists give us a refined angle on metaphors. When I wrote A Community Called Atonement (McKnight 2007), I explored the various metaphors about the atonement. One of my reviewers was stuck on the idea that there has to be a “central” metaphor. In the book I used the image of a golf bag into which we place golf clubs, with the clubs being the various atonement metaphors and the bag being a big enough category to contain all the metaphors. I settled on “incorporation through identification,” but I will let John Sanders turn it into a Lakoffian uppercase metaphor. My reviewer was settled in his mind on a prototypical metaphor that gave perspective to all the others. So he said that in playing golf eventually everyone uses the putter for every hole. To which I said “sometimes one knocks the ball in the hole before getting to the green where one uses the putter.” Not surprisingly, this didn’t get us anywhere. He was stuck, as I see it now, on the powerful usefulness of a prototypical metaphor, while I was working toward the abstraction of a more comprehensive set of terms.
What I most like about Sanders’s discussion of metaphor is that it is a cognitive tool and not simply an illustration or “just” a metaphor. Thus, “a conceptual metaphor is when we understand or experience one thing in terms of another—concept A is understood in terms of concept B” (49). We think about fundamental religious realities with metaphors and the metaphor is a window (speaking of which) onto the “target domain” (say, God) but the metaphor sheds light on God because through its words it prompts our thoughts about God. Hence, in the Bible there are two dominant domains about God—Father and King—but “since different sources highlight different features in the target domain, it is not surprising, for instance, that biblical writers employ so many different metaphors for God. No single metaphor captures all of ways humans understand God” (59). Thus, there is no single metaphor for God; when one succumbs to such a singular method of knowing, God is diminished because our knowing is diminished.
All of this, I think, leads Sanders into his most important discussion about how we treat the Bible. If it is a TEXT and we are READERS, then we miss out on what the cognitive linguists teachs us: texts are not just words on a page. They are words from one mind to another, or from one person to another. Hence, “this means that the notion that all the meaning resides in the text is false” (40). Instead, “grammar and words prompt for the construction of meaning, but meaning is not simply the sum of the parts of speech” (118). A text is an iceberg and below the surface there is far more than is above the surface, and cognitive linguists not only teach us this but tell us that ultimately what lies below the surface and above the surface is a human being seeking to communicate. He’s right in this, too: “This understanding of the nature of meaning contrasts strongly to a prominent approach in American evangelical theology, which circumscribes meaning to texts rather than minds, embraces an autonomous rather than encyclopedic view, and tends to discount the role of cultural framing” (118). He mentions a former teacher of mine, David Wells, as well as two of my former colleagues, Walter Kaiser and Wayne Grudem. All could benefit from John Sanders, even if they regard him, and he them, as not so prototypical!
Sanders knows the limits of metaphors, but I want to draw our attention to one I don’t think he brings into the discussion and which would turn this discussion in some other directions—namely, slavery. We are all aware that slavery has a history, that New World slavery is not the same as Roman empire slavery, though it is not as different as some would like to believe. We are aware, and more need to be more forthcoming about this if they want to see the Bible for what it is as embodied situated knowing, that the Bible does not go as far as we would like on abolition. That is not the problem I want to focus on here. The problem is the use of slavery as a metaphor. I shall try out a Lakoffianism: THE CHRISTIAN LIFE IS SLAVERY. What does it mean to us today to use the metaphor of slavery for the Christian life? Consider these passages:
- Gal 1:10: Am I now trying to win the approval of human beings, or of God? Or am I trying to please people? If I were still trying to please people, I would not be a servant of Christ.
- 1 Cor 9:19: Though I am free and belong to no one, I have made myself a slave to everyone, to win as many as possible.
- 2 Cor 4:5: For what we preach is not ourselves, but Jesus Christ as Lord, and ourselves as your servants for Jesus’ sake.
- Rom 6:16–17: Don’t you know that when you offer yourselves to someone as obedient slaves, you are slaves of the one you obey—whether you are slaves to sin, which leads to death, or to obedience, which leads to righteousness? But thanks be to God that, though you used to be slaves to sin, you have come to obey from your heart the pattern of teaching that has now claimed your allegiance.
- Rom 6:19–20: I am using an example from everyday life because of your human limitations. Just as you used to offer yourselves as slaves to impurity and to ever-increasing wickedness, so now offer yourselves as slaves to righteousness leading to holiness. When you were slaves to sin, you were free from the control of righteousness.
- Rom 12:11: Never be lacking in zeal, but keep your spiritual fervor, serving the Lord.
- Rom 14:18: because anyone who serves Christ in this way is pleasing to God and receives human approval.
We can unpack this as follows: to call ourselves slaves/servants of Christ is to affirm the Lordship of Christ, our surrender to him as Lord, his redemption of us, and our summons to serve Christ in life. We could say it expresses the glory of being in relation to the Lord Jesus. In the Bible to be called a “servant of God” is a complement.
For the African American in the United States today, who knows New World slavery, who knows the aftermath of the Civil War, who knows Jim Crow laws, and who knows the insoluble and intractable implications of racism and slavery in the United States that manifest themselves every day on every street of our major cities and elsewhere, what does it mean to say that being a “slave” of Christ is a complement? Better yet, can it even be understood as such a complement? No, it can’t be apart from the training of the mind not to do what embodied situated knowing is all about. Metaphors can become obsolete but when they are in the Bible the African American reader becomes truculent with the Bible itself. Rightly so.
Embodied situated knowing is a reality, and so is the legacy of some metaphors. Every reading of such metaphors for the African American and I hope increasingly for white Americans ought to be a history lesson in the power of words and their legacy. Redemption comes but it may mean talking back. All theology is anthropogenic and it would be much better if the anthropos—the human—had a nobler history. Perhaps what Theology in the Flesh will do for many of us will be to remind us of the potency of metaphors and the need for the redemption of some of them.
References
Adams, Samuel V. 2015. The Reality of God and Historical Method: Apocalyptic Theology in Conversation with N. T. Wright. Downers Grove: IVP Academic.
McKnight, Scot. 2007. A Community Called Atonement. Nashville, TN: Abingdon Press.
Sanders, John. 2016. Theology in the Flesh: How Embodiment and Culture Shape the Way We Think about Truth, Morality, and God. Minneapolis, MN: Fortress Press.
Bonnie Howe
Response
Minds Reading
Reflections on John Sanders’s Theology in the Flesh
When we open our Bibles and begin to read, our minds are engaged. Yes, and our hearts can be moved. But human minds are not disconnected from human hearts or from our whole selves. In cognitive linguistics, we speak of embodied human minds and of thought and language as grounded in everyday, experienced reality. Potentially—hopefully—our whole selves are engaged, especially when we read the Bible in our faith communities. We want our actions as individuals and as church communities to flow from our Bible reading. We do live in interesting and challenging times, and I’m eager for us to have this conversation around John Sanders’s Theology in the Flesh because I think he is offering us a treasure trove of questions, insights, models and methods for doing faithful and biblically grounded theology.
Theology in the Flesh does open up a huge set of issues and questions. Here I want to focus on the implications of cognitive linguistics for Bible reading, biblical interpretation, and ethics. Sometimes my church friends and extended family members tell me that Bible reading is not rocket science. “I just read the Bible and do what it says.” So, I get it: it’s not linguistic science, either. But some of us are interested in understanding in more detail how reading and interpretation happen. It’s not as simple as it seems, and I think in this case it’s not necessarily that the devil is in the details. Doing cognitive linguistic analyses of Scripture has opened up its richness for me, rather than closing it down.
Way back in 1980, George Lakoff and Mark Johnson said, “The meaning is not right there in the sentence—it matters a lot who is saying or listening to the sentence and what his social and political attitudes are” (Lakoff and Johnson 1980, p. 12). Words—as with all of our perceptions—are interpreted, and that interpretation is mediated through our everyday experience, including whatever connections and memories any text evokes for us. Without that embodied experience, the text evokes nothing. That’s part of what we mean by “embodiment” and embodied cognition. I think that is also what John Sanders means by theology “in the flesh.” He’s echoing (with permission) Lakoff and Johnson’s Philosophy in the Flesh (1999), and I find Sanders’s appropriation of the idea deeply coherent with incarnational Christianity.
Here is one touchstone concept from cognitive linguistics: Reading is a humanly invented activity, for many people a daily activity, one that involves our minds. Human beings—across cultures—love language, tell stories, and write books. Reading is both wonderful and ordinary, in the sense of everyday.
On one level I’m simply observing that reading the Bible, which I do believe is the Word of God, also works this way. Yes, the Bible is revelatory in ways that even other ancient texts are not. But, in God’s wisdom and self-giving love, God has taken the risk (a key concept for Sanders) of using human language and literary conventions to communicate that wisdom and love. John Sanders says it this way at the beginning of chapter 6, “Reading the Bible.”
That last phrase is loaded! What does it mean to pay “attention to the conceptual structures prompted by the texts”? I’ve spent over twenty-five years trying to understand what that means and how to do it, and I am still learning.
My introduction to the field was via Lakoff and Johnson’s Metaphors We Live By. I found it in a Berkeley bookstore, read it—and it blew my mind. I was hooked when they said this on page 1:
Metaphorical thought. Conceptual system. We use it to comprehend everyday reality. It affects both thoughts and actions. Another piece of the argument in that book also got my attention: “The most fundamental values in a culture will be coherent with the metaphorical structure of the most fundamental concepts in the culture.” That’s the first sentence of chapter 5, in Metaphors We Live By. I was studying biblical ethics, and I realized that if Lakoff and Johnson are right, then we ought to pay attention to the metaphorical structures in the texts, in Scripture. That’s how I personally got hooked on cognitive linguistics. First it was about metaphor, thought, and values and ethics.
I soon realized that although we do live by metaphors, it’s not just about metaphors. A great strength of Sanders’s book is that he shows us an array of cognitive linguistics interests, tools, and models. If you haven’t read more than Metaphors We Live By, you haven’t given this set of approaches enough attention. The field has grown; the models have been refined and have proliferated. Cognitive linguistics is offering us much more than it could in the ’80s and even the ’90s.
For most people in the modern world, reading in our natural language is a daily activity. But though reading is everyday, if we ask how it works, the answers get complicated quickly. The wonder is that we make sense at all of squiggles on a page or screen, and that we ever come to shared interpretations. We read a text, and we make sense of it. That is wonderful! It ought to evoke awe, as we ponder how that happens. Literary scholar and cognitive scientist Mark Turner makes this observation:
Cognitive linguists and literary scholars like Mark Turner have worked for several decades now to understand how language and thought are linked, to discern the patterns and processes involved in reading and interpretation of texts. In The Way We Think, Mark Turner and Gilles Fauconnier ask this question: “When we see words on a page, do those words stand directly for external realities?” (Fauconnier and Turner 2002, p. 146). Their answer is “No, but . . .” No, words do not directly stand for anything. Words are key to the making of meaning and to human communication because they are prompts, triggers that activate the human imagination. Words activate perception, which then is available for interpretation. In cognitive linguistics circles we say, “The meaning is not in the word.” We mean that words are not little meaning capsules that carry x content no matter the context in which they are uttered or written or read.
What in the human brain and embodied mind (two different entities) allows reading and interpretation to work? It is complicated. One thing we know for sure: Reading is not automatic. Readers participate in making meaning out of textual cues. One set of implications for those of us trying to make sense of ancient texts is that we are doing cross-cultural work. Listen to Ben Bergen, who directs the Language and Cognition Lab at the University of California, San Diego:
This has huge implications for biblical interpretation. It should encourage us to do thorough social-cultural and historical background work along with our basic Bible reading. When we construct mental experiences as we read, as we engage the stories of Scripture, our minds are working hard to make meaning, and the way we construe scenes matters.
The Morals of the Stories
Because so much of Scripture is narrative material and because we are a Story-formed people, we’d be wise to pay attention to what researchers are finding out about how we process not just single words or phrases, but stories and narratives. For example, in a study done at Washington University in St. Louis, published in 2009 in Psychological Science, fMRI scans tracked brain activity as people read short stories and processed individual words (Speer et al. 2009). They found that readers simulate each new situation encountered in a narrative. We don’t just decode words, we are running simulations. On this topic, John Sanders quotes Warren Brown and Brad Strawn, who wrote a book called The Physical Nature of Christian Life: Neuroscience, Psychology, and the Church:
Brown and Strawn’s insight is significant for many reasons, but what I’d like to point out is that scriptural morality and ethics is a morality of the stories, and not just a principle-based one, not reducible to rules or propositions or even lists of values.
To get at the nitty-gritty of how that works, we do need to pay attention to the features of the narrative, to how the stories are told (and received). Lakoff and Johnson were right: We do live by metaphors—at least partly. Noticing the metaphors in the texts does help us locate the values of the biblical cultures. But it turns out that it is not just about metaphors (and Lakoff and Johnson are well aware of this). Metonymies, semantic frames, image schemas—an array of features that cognitive linguistics can help us locate and parse—also are key to understanding the stories and the morals of the Story. John Sanders lands here in the book, where he explains why principle-ist reading strategies like Walter Kaiser’s are so thin and overly rigid (Sanders 2016, pp. 157–68). They are also culturally inept and misguided in a number of ways.
Sanders also turns to Joel Green and others of us who are advocating for an “exemplar” model for Scripture and ethics (Sanders 2016, p. 168). The aim is to move beyond the old read-and-apply methods and those that try to distill the ethical content to rules and so-called “timeless propositional” truth. Exemplar-focused interpretation asks what challenges and situations the characters in the text faced, and then tries to notice how they located the issues before them. What did they struggle with? What were their questions? How did they talk to each other?
It matters what we choose to read and study, in the biblical canon and beyond. These days I am turning again to 1 Peter, and I notice a surge of interest in some churches in studying Habakkuk. Interesting. Lately, I sense my “alien and stranger” status in my own country acutely. But we need to talk about it in depth and detail. If my Bible study friends and I assign ourselves the “stranger” role, will we also be able to respond as Jesus would to actual strangers—Muslims and Mexicans, for example? How are American Christians reading and interpreting “I was a stranger and you welcomed me” in our present context? We are not all running the same simulations as we read this text.
Finally, I recall Russell Moore’s 2016 Erasmus Lecture—which Krista Tippett posted on her On Being site just before the election—in which Moore called for a more robust evangelical ethics. Moore said, “Evangelical commitment to the Bible means not just that we’re committed to shaping our lives and our politics by a set of doctrines and principles derived from Scripture but more so by experiencing the world through a sense of place in the biblical story” (Moore; and see Krista Tippet’s remarks). What John Sanders is offering us is a basic cognitive linguistics toolkit for noticing that Story, the big one and all the little ones in Scripture, attending well and deeply, so we can let it shape our theology and our lives.
References
Bergen, Benjamin K. 2012. Louder than Words: The New Science of How the Mind Makes Meaning. New York: Basic Books.
Brown, Warren S., and Brad D. Strawn. 2012. The Physical Nature of Christian Life: Neuroscience, Psychology, and the Church. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Fauconnier, Giles, and Mark Turner. 2002. The Way We Think: Conceptual Blending and the Mind’s Hidden Complexities. New York: Basic Books.
Lakoff, George, and Mark Johnson. 1980; 2nd edition 2003. Metaphors We Live By. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press.
Lakoff, George, and Mark Johnson. 1999. Philosophy in the Flesh. New York: Basic Books.
Moore, Russell D. “Can the Religious Right Be Saved?” 29th Annual Erasmus Lecture, October 27, 2016. Video: https://syndicate.network.firstthings.com/media/can-the-religious-right-be-saved. Article: https://syndicate.network.firstthings.com/article/2017/01/can-the-religious-right-be-saved.
Speer, Nicole K., Jeremy R. Reynolds, Khena M. Swallow, and Jeffrey M. Zacks. 2009. “Reading Stories Activates Neural Representations of Visual and Motor Experiences.” Psychological Science 20, no. 8: 989–99.
Tippett, Krista. “A Generation-Defining Speech by a Conservative Religious Leader That Is Good News for All.” On Being. https://onbeing.org/blog/a-generation-defining-speech-by-a-conservative-religious-leader-that-is-good-news-for-all/.
Turner, Mark. 1991. Reading Minds: The Study of English in the Age of Cognitive Science. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
10.2.17 | John Sanders
Reply
Response to Howe
Language is the tip of an enormous cognitive iceberg. Just as some of the ice is visible above the water but most of the ice remains unseen below the water line, so there are visible and aural aspects to language that we perceive but there is a tremendous amount of cognitive activity going on beneath the surface. Cognitive linguistics seeks to understand the entire iceberg, both above and below the waterline. It studies the “visible” aspects of language such as grammars, word usage, and the like but it draws upon cognitive science to understand what is going on behind the scenes. It seeks to elucidate the mental tools we use to understand our lives and the world we inhabit.
One of the first tools to be examined was metaphor. Conceptual metaphor theory, in particular, is now one of the most empirically tested, refined, and cross-linguistically studied approaches to metaphor. It has been applied to fields such as music, law, literature, biblical studies, psychology, and politics. Due to its immense explanatory power, it has become a dominant academic approach. Theologians have said many helpful things about metaphor, but few have drawn upon the incredible insights of conceptual metaphor theory. Many philosophers and theologians continue to think of metaphors as rhetorical devices instead of as mental tools we use to reason about topics such as God, justice, and truth. A conceptual metaphor is when we understand A in terms of B. For instance, we understand God in terms of a husband. Conceptual metaphors have inferences so ancient Israel was invited to live out the culturally expected behaviors of wives in relation to Yahweh, their God. In Theology in the Flesh, I discuss two studies by Eve Sweetser and Mary Therese DesCamp that examine which domains of human experience biblical authors selected to understand God and to conceptualize their own rights and responsibilities. The studies also elaborate the principles governing metaphor use. They are not used arbitrarily but intentionally within the shared values and expectations of the culture in which they lived. Hence, conceptual metaphor theory is quite helpful.
In her contribution to this symposium, Bonnie Howe rightfully notes that cognitive linguistics is about much more than metaphor. Some of the other mental tools that I explore in the book are image schemas, metonymy, conceptual blending, categorization, and frames. Cognitive linguistics offers an integrated set of models and methodologies based on the ideas that (1) there is a set of principles which governs all aspects of language and (2) language makes use of the same cognitive tools humans use in other areas of life such as perception and memory. Hence, cognitive linguistics draws upon what is known about the embodied mind from an array of disciplines. Theology in the Flesh applies an “embodied mind” approach to various theological topics to shed new light on them. For example, it offers ways of defining concepts such as “Christian” in light of prototype theory and shows why both realist and anti-realist approaches to truth have some things right and some things wrong. Overall, the book calls us to humility in our claims to knowledge in part because there is often more than one legitimate way to construe topics such as God, truth, and salvation.
Another key point that Howe makes is that language prompts for meaning construction. There is usually more than one way to understand a text. There is a range of possible meanings and our minds actively assemble the most likely meaning from sparse information. Language prompts the mind to construct meaning by bringing in lots of background information. For example, one scholar who read the book wrote me that he appreciated many things about the book but he considered the title “Theology in the Flesh” absolutely horrible. The reason why is that the word “flesh” triggered in his mind one possible meaning of “flesh”—as sinful. Why do theology from a sinful perspective? Perhaps that understanding would sell more copies but I had a different construal of “flesh” in mind. The embodied mind approach affirms that the particular type of human bodies (flesh) we have, particularly our specific types of sensory and motor capabilities, deeply shapes the mental tools we use to understand our experience. Human embodied existence is what I mean by “flesh” which is a common understanding of the term in the Old Testament and is used by the Gospel of John when it says “the word became flesh” (1:14). This illustrates how our minds construct meaning.
A final point of Howe’s that I wish to comment on is her statement about the importance of cross-cultural understanding. Cognitive linguistics draws upon anthropology and cross-linguistic studies to compare and contrast understandings between various cultural groups. Many dozens of examples of cross-cultural differences are discussed in the book in order to help Westerners in general, and North Americans in particular, grasp the benefits of learning how peoples in ancient times or in different geographic regions understand a topic. For example, it is rather easy to fall victim to Anglo ethnopyschology—using the psychological categories and understandings of modern Western peoples as normative for all times and places. The book discusses several studies by biblical scholars using cognitive linguistics to understand the similarities and differences between ancient Israel’s prototypical scenario of anger (who is allowed to display anger, the object of anger, how it is manifested, and how it is evaluated) and the scenarios found in many cultures around the world. It is important to see how even familiar concepts such as “anger” are understood differently in various languages.
Cross-cultural studies have pointed out a number of intriguing differences. Here are some of the examples that I discuss in the book. Cultures that employ an honor/shame framework often think of justice, including divine justice, in ways that are different from guilt-based cultures. Americans are highly individualistic and so American Christians tend to construe “fairness” quite differently from Christians in China and India. Shaped by different cultural values Christians in Tanzania, Russia, and America read the parable of the Prodigal Son in significantly different ways. Christianity is two millennia old and is a global religion. It has been indigenized into various cultures from its inception. Christians in different cultures can enrich one another through conversations about what they share in common and how they see things differently. The book seeks to show that Christians have widespread agreement on some general ideas along with cultural variation on most topics. Understanding why this is the case should help us be more humble in our claims to possess the correct theology and to appreciate what others have to teach us. Cognitive linguistics is a very useful tool to assist in this process.