Symposium Introduction

As Karen Kilby notes in her response later in this symposium, Simeon Zahl’s The Holy Spirit and Christian Experience is a difficult, if fascinating and compelling, book to review. A good part of the difficulty lies in the sheer breadth of intellectual ground the book covers and the depth of its analysis. There is the recovering of discarded affective dimensions from early Protestant theology. There is the detailed theological interpretation of critical New Testament texts and close engagement with relevant biblical scholarship. There is the sustained methodological use of affect theory to build, among other things, a constructive pneumatology. There are critical interjections, leveraged by Zahl’s intriguing theorisation of “affective Augustinianism,” into some of the most significant debates within the doctrine of soteriology. There are the ecumenical possibilities this book might enable between Protestant theology and Pentecostal and Charismatic theologies. And there’s much more still. All this, in Zahl’s skilful hands, gets folded around a central thesis: experience, emotion and embodiment cannot be excluded from Christian doctrine. So, for Zahl, doctrine is resourced by experience (i.e., it supplies the raw material for belief-production alongside, classically, Scripture, reason, and tradition) and doctrine is “felt” in the experience of actual people (i.e., on bodies and behaviour, and in the highs and lows of life and everything in between).

Simeon puts it well when he says in one of his replies: “The real question is not whether we are to incorporate our experience in theology, but how to do it well, given the fact that we are always already doing it.” Naturally, Barth—the archenemy of experience—is fair game for a rough ride in Zahl’s genealogy. If Christiane Tietz’s biography is anything to go by, it’s not that Barth didn’t incorporate experience into his theology but that he didn’t know he was doing it, and if he did, he didn’t know how to do it well, and this had damaging effects on his dogmatics and perhaps on his life and the lives of those around him. Barth is a useful case in point to illustrate another of the fundamental arguments of this book: you can’t really speak about experience without speaking of the Holy Spirit. No wonder theologians wondered where the Spirit went in Barth’s dogmatics given the ostensibly underdeveloped way he approached the category of experience. Unlike Barth, Zahl has a much sharper grasp of this somewhat slippery concept, which is sharpened further by the tools of affect theory. Zahl’s use of affect theory surfaces with full clarity in chapter 4 and is given extra articulation by Simeon in his reply to Natalie Carnes.

First up in this symposium’s attempt to mine some of the riches of this book is Natalie Carnes and her questioning of whether Catholics have been let off the hook a little too easily, and her encouragement to consider the implications of Zahl’s proposals for theology’s form. Then comes Daniel Castelo and his call for a deeper dive into exactly what’s gone wrong in modern theology for the occlusion of experience to take hold in the first place. Next, David Fergusson taps into Zahl’s anti-abstraction thesis and invites further reflection on the need to make theological sense of the possibility of the experience of God outside of the church. And Karen Kilby ends this symposium with an identification of some of the main contributions to contemporary theology Simeon makes, and picks up where Carnes left off with some further reflections on the form-question.

That this is a difficult book to review has also something then to do with the nature of writing about experience. Following Carnes and Kilby, writing about experience presents particular challenges to the form this sort of theology should take. Is systematic theology, as a discipline with a fairly narrowly conceived set of formal conventions, inherently self-limiting? Perhaps one of the shifts in systematic theology this book might inspire—alongside getting theologians to think seriously and theologically about experience—is to invite theologians of the systematic sort to write a bit more creatively, with a bit more permission to draw from experience as a valid source of theological enquiry and integrate these experiential insights into the form as well as content of their writing. There are good reasons the sort of ground clearing work contained in this book needing to take the form it does (so Simeon’s reply to Kilby), but with the foundations Zahl has laid, the fullest possible integration of theology and experience might need a different default genre. There’s a model here in Ashon Crawley’s Blackpentecostal Breath, which Simeon cites later, and also, more recently, in Natalie Wigg-Stevenson’s Transgressive Devotions. These could be worked examples of the sort of theology Zahl is ultimately calling for. With Wigg-Stevenson there’s a further methodological shift into empirical research methodologies, and especially of the qualitative sort, that Zahl doesn’t himself take in this book but could bring his work into closer empirical contact with the real lives of real Christians in order to dismantle further the “subtle but powerful walls between theology and lived experience” (5).

From the rubble of these dismantled walls, I share with Simeon a hope that bridges can be built between Protestant theology and the Pentecostal and Charismatic traditions (and the “untapped” [p. 5] pneumatological resources they hold). Further to these ecumenical possibilities are, as David mentions in his response, the bridges this book builds between systematic theology and practical theology as well as various theologies of liberation committed to Zahl’s fundamental claim that you can’t do theology without drawing on lived experience. For this, the book is a major contribution.

For Zahl, as will become clear, part of what it means to speak usefully of experience lies in affect theory. While Zahl sets affect theory to work in relation to the doctrine of salvation (chapter 3), sin and grace (chapter 4), and then sanctification (chapter 5), it’ll be up to others to apply Zahl’s argument to different doctrinal loci; and my heart for one is strangely warmed by the prospect of further work that seeks to reexamine the “affective salience” of the whole nine yards of Christian doctrine. This book will generate new thinking. But for now, we turn to the details of the book itself and hear from the first of our four contributors.

My final word, before clearing aside, is a hearty thanks to everyone involved in this symposium for producing such sharp and provocative contributions amidst the pressures the pandemic continues to place on our bodies, experiences and emotions.

Natalie Carnes

Response

What about Rattling Medals and Talking Images?

“[The Duke of Norfolk’s] joints seem knitted together of supple chain links, and indeed he rattles a little as he moves, for his clothes conceal relics: in tiny jeweled cases he has shavings of skin and snippets of hair, and set into medallions he wears splinters of martyrs’ bones. ‘Marry!’ he says, for an oath, and ‘By the Mass!,’ and sometimes takes out one of his medals or charms from wherever it is hung about his person, and kisses it in a fervor, calling on some saint or martyr to stop his current rage getting the better of him. . . . He thinks book-reading an affectation altogether, and wishes there were less of it at court” (Wolf Hall, 134).

I begin with this passage from Hilary Mantel’s historical novel Wolf Hall in appreciative imitation of Zahl, who opens The Holy Spirit and Christian Experience with an epigraph from George Eliot’s short story “Janet’s Repentance.” Threading a strand of that story through his introduction, Zahl attends to Eliot’s reflections on how the “poor ghosts” of ideas are sometimes “made flesh,” acquiring for us a powerful and passionate presence (1–2). Eliot helps Zahl set up his rehabilitation of “experience,” which has suffered, if not exile, then studied avoidance in much contemporary theology. As a theological category, experience is particularly vexed for Protestants. And yet, Zahl argues, experience is also deeply important in two ways: first, through its implicit function in “the affective salience of doctrine;” and, second, through its formal function as a source of theological reflection together with Scripture, reason, and tradition (46). Hailing Eliot thus seems a fitting opening gesture for two corresponding reasons. First, novels are generally more attuned to their affective salience than doctrinal exposition is; and, second, novels provide an opportunity to observe the affective lives of others, perhaps even to discern how experience functions as a source for a character’s own theologizing about life. Beginning with Eliot, Zahl introduces his readers to an approach to theology and experience that is as clear as it proves fertile.

My particular homage to Zahl through Wolf Hall is meant to build on Zahl’s work by pressing some questions about other forms theology’s relationship to experience might take. It draws on that second way novels can help us think about theology and experience by considering how experience shapes a character’s own theology in order to ask whether there might be a way of construing the relation of theology and experience uncaptured by the formal and implicit options Zahl outlines. The Mantel passage presses for me the question: Have Catholics been let off the hook too easily? And relatedly: How does the picture of theology’s relation to affect shift once Catholics are also held to account for experience?

Early in his book, Zahl explains why experience isn’t the problem for Protestants that it is for Catholics. He writes, “At the eve of the Protestant Reformation, Catholic theology already had a sophisticated way of addressing the question of pneumatological discernment: the authority of the magisterial teaching office of the Church” (17). He later refers to the Catholic approach as the “magisterial-ecclesial solution to the problem” (17). Yet the magisterium offers no real solution to the problem of experience, nor does it obviate the difficulties and exigencies of discernment. Magisterial pronouncements about experience—of miracles, apparitions, saintliness—always lag behind myriad individual and communal forms of discernment. Pope Francis pointed to this in the Thanksgiving mass for Oscar Romero’s canonization, when he chided the church hierarchy that was late to recognize Romero and implored bishops to listen to the people who can “smell holiness.”1 The acts of discernment required in a church with a magisterium multiply rather than contract: people make an act of discernment about a saint and particular miracles attesting to her sanctity; the hierarchy makes acts of discernment about the saint and the people’s acts of discernment; and people again discern the adequacy the magisterium’s response, which is sometimes overturned in later years. In terms of declaring saints, recognizing apparitions, and affirming miracles, the hierarchy almost always follows popular movements, which are constituted by multiple people reflecting on and discerning their own experience of the Spirit.

My point in raising the role of experience in the Catholic Church is not to quibble with Zahl about whether Catholics have found a way to render experience less tendentious. His claim about Catholicism is a minor point he makes on the way to describing the heart of his project, when he turns to early Protestant theology both to correct misreadings of it (convincingly, to my mind) and to show the work that affect theory can do (powerfully, in my judgment). I raise this point because I believe Zahl is advocating an important shift in systematic theological work, and I want to think with it and push it further. For I wonder if in excluding Catholic theology, he has also impoverished his resources for answering some of his principal questions, including “Why are some theological ideas lifechanging for certain people, but dry as dust for others? Why are theologians so prone to developing systems of great intellectual coherence and elegance, but which bear only passing resemblance to the lives Christians actually seem to lead?” (4) How, I wonder, would turning to Hilary Mantel rather than George Eliot give us a different way into these questions?

The fictionalized Duke of Norfolk is not, I admit, a compelling picture of saintliness in Wolf Hall. He’s vindictive, snobbish, fury-prone, and obsessed with worldly status—though Zahl has pointed out to us the way “affective intransigence,” the opacity of the heart, and the freedom of the Spirit disappoint hopes of tidy paths from sinner to saint (221–29). And yet in his life, the Duke sees God, via the saints and martyrs, via the medals and relics hanging on his body, soothing his wilder rages. His passions are bound up with these material sites of divine presence; he kisses them, swears with them, subdues by them. He does not, the passage makes clear, turn to the verbal articulations of doctrine found in books. Nor does the consoling power of the Duke of Norfolk’s soteriological commitments come to him by the ghost of an idea acquiring presence and power through a persuasive interlocutor. Consolation comes to him through the sound and feel of his rattling medals and relics, which assure him that God is present to him, that he has not been abandoned by the divine, that God can be transformatively with him even during his most vicious rages. How might cases like the Duke’s expand what theology engaged with affect theory and experience elucidates? What kind of pneumatology might come from attention to his case? What soteriology?

Let’s take a more compelling figure of saintliness than the Duke and turn instead to the figure in Christianity most universally recognized as a saint: Francis. Thomas of Celano represents an important moment of conversion in his second Life of the saint:

Led by the Spirit he went in to pray and knelt down devoutly before the crucifix. He was shaken by unusual experiences and discovered that he was different from when he had entered.

As soon as he had this feeling, there occurred something unheard of in previous ages: with the lips of the painting, the image of Christ crucified spoke to him. “Francis,” it said, calling him by name, “go rebuild My house; as you see, it is all being destroyed.”

Francis was more than a little stunned, trembling, and stuttering like a man out of his senses. He prepared himself to obey and pulled himself together to carry out the command. He felt this mysterious change in himself, but he could not describe it. So it is better for us to remain silent about it too.

From that time on, compassion for the Crucified was impressed into his holy soul. And we honestly believe the wounds of the sacred Passion were impressed deep in his heart, though not yet on his flesh.2

There is much that is fascinating here, but I limit myself to highlighting three ways in which it is particularly interesting to think about with Zahl’s terms. First, it ascribes agency to the Spirit and so presents itself for pneumatological reflection. Second, it describes an affective transformation in Francis that ends, not in delight or consolation, but in receiving stigmata on his heart that foreshadow the later ones he will receive in the flesh. Third, it attributes the occasion of this transformation, not to a doctrine or idea, but to an encounter with an image, which speaks to him as Christ. One interpretation of this event is that in it, experience functions purely formally, as a source for theological reflection. Another interpretation sees the image as itself theologically significant (what does it mean that the Franciscan Order facilitated the rise of images of a suffering Christ at a time when the triumphant Christ had been dominant?) and so interprets experience as also functioning here implicitly, as mediating theological claims affectively, though not purely verbally.

I wonder, then, if Zahl’s two descriptions of how experience relates to theology might need to be muddied a bit, or scooted aside to make room for a third. Can we conceive a relation of theology to experience in which the latter is neither something external to theological reflection, something that needs to be coordinated with it as a source, nor wholly internal to doctrine, as in the affective salience of doctrines? What do we make of the fact that the moment Augustine affectively transforms is not when he grasps the doctrine of the incarnation but when he receives the words of Scripture as a site of divine encounter because he remembers the story of Saint Antony’s conversion? Might an affective Augustinian interested in how doctrines “make bodies move” need to attend to the myriad mediators by which that faith is given, reshaped, and strengthened—beyond the rhetorical power of the theology and yet not apart from theology as if a separate source? I wonder if experience can name a field in which doctrinal commitments are mediated to us nonverbally, in which images embody perspectives on the Incarnation and speak to us about our vocation, wounding our hearts.

I raise the question of Catholicism, then, because I see the type of theological experience I am considering here—what we might call nonverbal affective theology—as more obvious and prevalent in the Catholic Church than in most Protestant churches, which were born in a suspicion of the very mediations I want to consider. In some ways, early Protestant theologians like Melanchthon need their doctrinal formulations to do affective work because they’re filling the emotional and corporeal gaps that images, relics, and other forms of saintly veneration once occupied. And once this expanded possibility of theological experience is received, then I wonder how we can return to one of Zahl’s central concerns, which is how theologians might approach theology in ways that take pneumatology, experience, and affect theory more seriously.

On that note, Zahl ends with a rich and thoughtful conclusion about how the content of theology should change—should expand—in light of his study. I wonder if there are also implications about theology’s form. Could his work help make sense of and appreciate, for example, a growing trend among feminist theologians to write theology as literature. In recent years, Janet Martin Soskice wrote a book of creative nonfiction; Elizabeth Johnson wrote eco-feminist theology in dialogue form; Tina Beattie, Susan Brookes Thistlethwaite, and Mary Judith Ress have all written novels related to themes in feminist theology. 3 Are these feminist theologians writing theology in a way that recognizes this third type of experience, the way reading literature can be an affectively-potent mode of forming, transforming, and shifting theological commitments, not because they articulate doctrine but because in their stories and imaginative worlds, they offer theologically-mediated ways of encountering God afresh? The work Zahl has done to expand theology’s relationship to experience is exciting and generative; is their room for more expansion still?


  1. Pope Francis went off script in making this remark, so it is does not appear in the official Vatican transcript. However, records of it can be found in various reports of the event, including this one from the Diocese of Oakland, which reports Pope Francis as saying, “The people of God smell holiness. They know when their leader is on the right path to sanctity.” Michael Jurich, “The People of God ‘Smell Holiness,’” Catholic Voice, November 12, 2018, http://www.catholicvoiceoakland.org/2018/11-12/frontpage3.htm.

  2. Thomas of Celano, “The Remembrance of the Desire of a Soul,” in Francis of Assisi: Early Documents, vol. 2, The Founder, ed. Regis Armstrong (New York: New City, 2001), 249.

  3. Tina Beattie, The Good Priest (Troubador, 2019); Mary Judith Ress, Blood Flowers (iUniverse 2010) and Different Gods (iUniverse, 2018); Susan Brooks Thistlethwaite, Where Drowned Things Live (Wipf and Stock, 2017) and Every Wickedness (Wipf and Stock, 2017). In addition, Janet Soskice wrote creative nonfiction in Sisters of Sinai: How Two Lady Adventurers Discovered the Hidden Gospels (Knopf, 2009).

  • Simeon Zahl

    Simeon Zahl

    Reply

    Reply to Natalie Carnes

    Natalie Carnes makes an eloquent case for expanding my account of the relationship between theology and experience to take better account of material religion than she finds I have done. She urges me not to forget the nonverbal, physical, sensory dimensions of the life of faith that live and move in the dynamic space between theological ideas and the affects that Christians experience, and she suggests that “experience” can and should also “name a field in which doctrinal commitments are mediated to us nonverbally.” And in doing so, through a series of well-chosen examples she provides a remarkably full, subtle, and persuasive account of the power of material dynamics in Christian religious life.

    I am unreservedly in agreement with her claims about nonverbal mediations of doctrinal commitments in experience; and I tried at several points in the book to head off the impression that my account of Christian experience is concerned solely with the relation between verbally articulated theological ideas and affective experience (15, 40–42, 215–25). In this response I want to elaborate on the importance of materiality in my account Christian experience, and in the process argue that Carnes and I are in closer agreement than on this front than it might appear. More central to the book’s account of Christian experience than the discussion of experience and theological reasoning is its extended appeal to the category of affect, especially as affect has come to be understood from the perspective of affect theory. In recent years affect theorists have generated a number of exciting new insights about affect and emotion that strongly inform the account of experience I am working with in the book.1

    To summarize those insights here, as I now wish I had done more explicitly in the book: (1) affects are powerful motivating energies that go a long way towards making sense of what human beings do (as Schaefer puts it, “what makes bodies move”); (2) affects are not just occasional episodes, but are continuously and dynamically operative in human experience at every moment; (3) affects are often encountered as “intransigent,” in the sense of being highly resistant to attempts to shift them through information, argument, or discursive practice; (4) affects are not simply private properties of individual bodies, but “circulate” across persons, times, objects, spaces; (5) affects have cultural, biological, social, and personal “histories” (Ahmed) and as such are laden with information; (6) affects are deeply connected to physical bodies as well as environments and as such are never less than material realities.

    It is this last characteristic that is especially relevant as I seek to explain both why I agree with Carnes and why I don’t think this dimension is as absent from my account as she suggests. As a number of affect theorists have emphasized, affects are deeply caught up with materiality, for example in the ways they emerge from and are mediated by specific systems in the human body, or in how they are shaped in complex ways by our embeddedness in physical spaces and environments.

    It is on this basis that some scholars of affect also speak about “affective technologies.” This wonderful term, which I first learned from Donovan Schaefer (Religious Affects, 74) seeks to capture how cultural artifacts of various kinds function to modulate and elicit affective experiences. It can be applied to a very wide range of objects: roller coasters, soaring cathedral vaults, antidepressants, liturgical books, prison architectures, and mindfulness apps are all affective technologies of one kind or another. And so, it seems to me, are the Duke of Norfolk’s reliquaries, and for just the reasons Carnes elucidates. Here sensory experience, religious consolation, and a particular cluster of theological ideas (about saints and holiness, about grace, about embodiment, about what theology actually does in the life of a Christian person) are vibrantly at work without a word needing to be spoken.

    Given the importance of the materiality of affects for the account I am seeking to bring to bear in Christian theology, and the ways I draw out that dimension in the discussion of affective economies and histories in chapter 5, I don’t view the theological vision of the book as restricted mainly to the verbal domain. I see now that this dimension of my account was not as clear as it could have been, and that it would have improved my argument to delve further and more explicitly into the account of materiality and experience than I managed to do. No doubt Carnes is also right to suggest that my decision to focus primarily on Protestant figures and themes may have resulted in less granular attention to the material implications of my arguments than I than there might otherwise have been.

    Having now clarified my position, I wonder if a rather different interpretation of the book’s theological vision might emerge than the one Carnes has presented us with. Rather than having attended inadequately to Catholic theology and experience and as a result to the significance of nonverbal mediations of theological commitments, as Carnes suggests, what if The Holy Spirit and Christian Experience were read the other way around? What if the book were in fact a set of arguments seeking to persuade skeptical Protestants of the theological importance of materiality and embodiment, but on recognizably Protestant terms, and, eo ipso, to present Catholic and Orthodox theologians with evidence that their traditions do not have so complete a theological monopoly on embodiment as is sometimes assumed?

    Certainly this was my intention in writing the book. At the heart of the project I have tried to show, contrary to prevailing assumptions in Anglophone theology, that it is not necessary to move away from core theological convictions of classical Protestantism like the doctrine of justification by faith in order to affirm the importance of embodiment and emotion in religious life and in theology. A better path, I argue, is to retrieve from Augustine, Luther, and Melanchthon a more affectively integrated account of the work of the Holy Spirit, and especially of the operation of justifying grace.

    It is true that my opening gambit in the book is to argue that theological propositions are often powerful affective technologies—this is part of what I have in mind in calling for attention to the “affective salience of doctrines.” But rather than excluding materiality by prioritizing the emotional power of words, I take this move to be making way for renewed emphasis on materiality and embodiment in the face of traditional Protestant anxieties about religious subjectivism.

    Once we recognize that affects are central and unavoidable in Christian experience (rather than downstream and episodic), that affects are things that happen in and to bodies in space and time, and that salvation and sanctification are very often described in the New Testament and in later tradition in terms of affective experiences and transformations, then it seems to me that we have already opened the theological door to the wide world of material religion—including, in principle, the rich variety of material mediations of the Spirit’s work.

    There are a number of exciting implications of this finding, at least as I see it. Particularly relevant to the present response is the implication that questions about religious objects and idolatry, traditionally so important to Protestants, would appear no longer to reduce as easily as before to questions about materiality or “externality” as such. Of course divine grace can be mediated through objects and other material realities—in a very real sense, in this world it nearly always is. But that does not mean the old Protestant worries about idolatry are simply set aside. Here Augustine’s old distinction between “use” and “enjoyment,” and Luther’s derivative distinction between “use” and “substance,” become extremely important. The theological questions to be asked of the Duke of Norfolk are about use, about the nature of his heart’s relation to the objects he carries, rather than the mere fact of their materiality or of their location outside of his body.

    For theological reflection on material religion, the thematic of “use” thus becomes, I think, fundamental.2 But it also proves to be very difficult. This is for two reasons. First, although I agree with Augustine that the heart is the primary engine room of sin as well as the primary faculty on which grace operates, I also agree with him that the heart is in so many ways an enigma and a mystery. If theological ethics—say, attempts to discern whether idolatry is at work in a given Christian’s relation to a feature of the created world in a given instance—is significantly about how an object is “used” rather than just its inherent nature, then motivation is theologically crucial, and yet motivation is often troublingly opaque.

    The second difficulty is related, and follows from the affirmation that desire is embodied. If affects and desires are materially embedded phenomena, then the heart is not simply an “inner” reality that operates at a remove from bodies and their world. Rather, desire is always caught up with bodily systems and environments, with personal, social, and cultural histories, and with the whole range of forces that act upon us in the world to shape what we feel and what we do. The heart is both theologically central and irreducibly porous and extended.

    The challenge then becomes how to speak well about the heart and “use” dynamics without either claiming too much knowledge about motivation (tidy accounts of why human beings do what they do have a tendency to dissolve in the acids of experience, if they aren’t first undone by the Spirit that “blows where it wills”), nor too little (theologians are bound to try to say something true, and scripture and tradition are not silent about what God is like or how God relates to Christians). A major burden of chapter 5 of The Holy Spirit and Christian Experience is to navigate these challenging waters. Readers will have to look there to determine whether I have foundered in the rapids or found a way through.

    To return to the main theme: at its best, theological attention to affect of the sort I am advocating in the book interestingly subverts traditional binaries between the verbal and the material, between “rational” ideas and “bodily” emotions, between “internal” feelings and external objects, and between theological propositions and bodily transformations. I would argue, and I expect Carnes might agree, that these subversions are really exciting, and for ecumenical reasons not least, and I am grateful to her for pressing me to draw out the material dimensions of my account of the Spirit and experience more explicitly. As Carnes points out, they also have important synergies with recent moves to expand the range of genres and writing styles available to modern theologians—a topic to which I will return in my response to Karen Kilby. For now, I hope it is clearer why I think Carnes and I are in fundamental agreement about the relationship between affectivity and material religion, why I welcome her urging that we pay closer attention going forward to the domains of the material and the nonverbal in experience of the Holy Spirit, and why, despite appearances, The Holy Spirit and Christian Experience is not just a book for Protestants.


    1. Affect theory is of course no monolith. I draw specifically on the work of Eve Sedgwick, Sara Ahmed, Lauren Berlant, and Donovan Schaefer, as well as related work in religious studies by Manuel Vásquez.

    2. On this point, see especially Simeon Zahl, “Tradition and Its Use: The Ethics of Theological Retrieval,” Scottish Journal of Theology 71.3 (2018): 308–23.

Daniel Castelo

Response

A Proposal with a Future

Simeon Zahl’s The Holy Spirit and Christian Experience is a timely and generative study. It provides diagnostics, analyses, and proposals on a myriad of themes that are often neglected or passed over in theology. For this reason, it should be an important, oft-cited work for years to come.

One of its main contributions is to put forward the pressing thesis that when identified is quite perplexing: Theologians make many claims as to the availability and activity of God within their proposals, but they have an exceedingly difficult time accounting for this availability and activity in ways that are not overwhelmed by some clearly demarcated extremes. Because of this orientation, what one is left with is an obvious sense of what the “boogeymen” are, so to speak, but also an accompanying, latent dissatisfaction with what emerges affirmatively. The pivot points have to do with matters related to the God-human interface broadly and to the characterization of specific theological proposals as divinely authorized particularly. This problem is largely a Protestant one in Zahl’s work. The “boogeymen” in this case are thinking of experience as either “the foundation for all dogmatic claims” (in the vein of Schleiermacher) or as a theme “hopelessly compromised by idolatry and sinfulness,” thereby meriting its exclusion in the outworking of theological claims (16). Undoubtedly, the “boogeymen” are worth avoiding in some sense: Theology can easily be usurped by anthropology, and humans are notoriously weak in allowing their own flaws and vices to project unto their theological claims, especially in light of an unbridled subjectivism. The challenge here, of course, is not to deny the significance of experience as a result of avoiding these extremes, for in doing so, Zahl knows where this will lead: “We cannot hide behind either methodological anxieties or metaphysical generalities. To do so . . . would be to eclipse the Spirit from our theology” (72). That is precisely what has happened in many sectors of Western Christian theology. Often, “you wonder where the Spirit went” in these contexts (to riff on an article title by Robert Jenson). The point stands not just for specific proposals but for much of modern theology; in fact, plenty of people do not even bother to wonder the point at all while (ironically) claiming strong trinitarian commitments. As Zahl hints in the book, this neglect may not be so much a result of intellectual shortsightedness as it is a function of a multitextured form of anxiety. When it comes to these questions, theologians often show terribly burdening, occluding, and debilitating anxieties. These anxieties are real and powerful; they are also stubborn and (to use Zahl’s language) intransigent.

Through the means of a book, what Zahl can do in response to these anxieties is limited. He can and does identify them. Such is a strong feature of the work. He can offer theories as to why they are so. On this point, the book may have benefitted from a more robust account of wider claims—a deep dive, if you will, as to how and why these anxieties took place, given the kinds of historical, pastoral, cultural, and intellectual currents that are operative in specific cases. I realize that is quite a bit to ask, and Zahl does some of that work, but I am convinced that more has to be done so as to make his proposals deeply resonant in the contemporary setting of anglophone culture. My concern is that without this kind of deep probing, anxieties have a way of reproducing and reshaping themselves in uncritical and routinized ways. Take the case of the Protestant fixation on establishing that “works” are not soteriologically meritorious. In my view, the anxiety makes much more sense within the context of sixteenth-century Europe than it does today in north transatlantic culture, yet, according to my experience, in many (often nonacademic but rather ecclesial) settings, the anxiety is still at work and reproduced/morphed in the name of doctrinal fidelity. Yes, as Zahl points out, we should not let cultural circumstances exceedingly relativize what can be ascertained as long-standing features and patterns within the human experience generally and the spiritual life particularly, but we also cannot generalize and equivocate on this point since the anxiety of one setting will be textured differently from another. In one setting, an anxiety can be a practical threat; in another, it can be an existential threat; and still in another, it can be a hypothetical threat. Each is a different experience and involves a different degree of abstraction. And, one may add, the antidote or alternative need not be, as Zahl points out, a default rationalism. The dangers of enthusiasm need not be resisted by what is given a pass as “safe,” namely a “rational” approach (whatever that may mean). The dangers of enthusiasm are rivalled by the dangers of rationalism, yet the former tend to be prioritized as more of a threat than the latter in formal academic settings in the West. This state of affairs is problematic and in need of problematization.

Via a book, one can also offer new analyses, categories, and proposals, and happily Zahl does this throughout the work. Examples include qualifying and demarcating the kinds of experience operative in theologizing; a focus on and inclusion of affect theory for theological reasoning; references to mood congruent cognition, attachment theory, and their relevance to spirituality; the theme of affective salience; and so on. I especially appreciate the emphasis on the “practical recognizability” of the Spirit. Such an approach resists the tendencies towards abstraction and vagueness in theological proposals and in turn offers some sense of concreteness to pneumatological discernment, which is something direly needed in the present discussions. As I take it, the direction here is to give an account of changed/transformed lives and in turn to bridge the conceptual and disciplinary gap between theology and spirituality.

Toward the end of the book, Zahl focuses on rereadings of Philip Melanchthon, Martin Luther, and Augustine. These are, of course, significant figures with vast secondary literatures surrounding them. Once again, Zahl highlights these figures so as to stress omissions in terms of how they have been subsequently read and appropriated. Given the way affect plays a role in the thought of these figures and the way affect ties directly to the person and work of the Holy Spirit, one can see quite readily through Zahl’s analysis that they have been neglected for their pneumatological contributions. At the same time, I suspect that operative in this neglect is a kind of background orientation, to which Zahl references early in the book: “Why have so many contemporary theologians found flawed arguments about major Protestant distinctives to be compelling, and why have these theological narratives encountered so little resistance? The present study has arisen to a substantial degree out of reflection on these questions. I have become convinced that the underlying issue in each case is less about the particular readings of the Reformers involved than it is about deeper theological assumptions and methodological commitments that have created conditions under which misreadings such as these can flourish” (5). I find this intuition to be spot-on. In fact, Zahl reckons that in the case of Luther and Melanchthon, the misreadings and neglect of earlier themes (as stressed in the pre- and post-Schwärmerei Luther and in the move from the Apology to the Formula of Concord) took place within a matter of decades. Zahl was attuned to this point early in the work. As I mentioned earlier, I wish he would have unpacked more the factors contributing to these shifts. Why is it that people and movements tend to transition so readily in the neglect of the Spirit? We need to hear time and time again why theologians continue to operate in such a way so that we can be clearheaded so as not to perpetuate these patterns moving forward. I sense that avoiding these tendencies would constitute a massive shift within Western theology, one that I (and, I would imagine, many in the global South) would welcome heartily.

Overall, I am very grateful for this work. Zahl has given us a contemporary and suggestive account of the Holy Spirit and experience that should bear fruit for years to come. It is the kind of rare and special work that has the potential to unleash research trajectories. I look forward to seeing that kind of activity, for it should constitute an important development in Christian pneumatological reflection.

  • Simeon Zahl

    Simeon Zahl

    Reply

    Reply to Daniel Castelo

    Daniel Castelo finds The Holy Spirit and Christian Experience effective in its exposure of contemporary theological anxieties about embodied experience and the work of the Spirit, but incomplete in its account of where these anxieties come from. I am very heartened indeed to see that Castelo and I are in close agreement on the main points: that something has gone wrong in modern theology that has resulted in a strange eclipse of experience from a good deal of theological thinking, and that this occlusion of experience follows in some sense from a failure to take adequate account of the reality and work of the Holy Spirit.

    Particularly illuminating to me is Castelo’s characterization of this development as the result “not so much . . . of intellectual shortsightedness as it is of a multitextured form of anxiety.” Modern theology has been shaped very deeply by an anxiety about embodiment, about experience, and about claims to unmediated activity of the Spirit of God. This problem seems to be most acute in Protestant traditions, but is not limited to them. Castelo and I also agree, I think, that the rise of this anxiety is a peculiarly modern development, at least in its strong forms.

    In many ways The Holy Spirit and Christian Experience is a sustained theological attempt to help repair this anxiety. I have sought to give theologians new tools, some borrowed from affect theory and some intrinsic to the doctrine of the Holy Spirit, for thinking theology’s relationship to emotion and experience, and I have offered an account of the work of the Spirit that puts these tools into practice to develop a more pneumatologically and experientially integrated approach to salvation and sanctification.

    But, as Castelo presses me to remember, effective healing begins with effective diagnosis. With all the good will in the world, it remains the case, as he puts it, that “people and movements tend to transition so readily in the neglect of the Spirit.” If as theologians we are to avoid reproducing this pattern, then we need to have as clear as possible a sense of why it occurs. So the question becomes: where has modern theology’s anxiety about embodiment and experience come from? What are its sources?

    In chapter 1, I suggest a particular answer to this question. My basic proposal is that the most important sources of modern theological anxiety about experience are to be found in the Reformation era, as skepticism about institutional authority in Christianity, combined with the need to find a plausible basis for certain new theological claims, served to focus theological attention on two main alternative theological authorities: religious experience and scripture.

    Building on some of my earlier work on Luther, I argue that Luther himself bequeathed this anxiety to later Protestants in the form of an unresolved tension in his thought. On the one hand, Luther appealed explicitly and extensively to affective experience in developing both his hamartiology and his theology of justification, especially in the years through 1521.1 His pessimistic anthropology was significantly shaped by reflection on his own experience of the insuperability of sinful affection, and his theology of justification was in many ways developed as a practical theology of consolation for anxious Christians.

    These appeals to experience, I suggest, cannot be fully reconciled with Luther’s theology of the Word, which developed slightly later. The latter strongly emphasized the role of scriptural and sacramental mediation in the work of the Spirit, and reached its mature form as a response to a more unrepentantly subjectivistic approach to piety that Luther encountered in the 1520s, which he famously dubbed Schwärmerei, or “enthusiasm.” Initially, the theology of the Word was understood as a bulwark against an incipient Pelagianism that was perceived to follow from “unmediated” theologies of the Holy Spirit. But, I argue, it included within it a fundamental skepticism about appeals to religious subjectivity that is at odds with how Luther’s early theology was developed and argued for.

    After Luther’s death, under pressure from the radical reformers as well as Andreas Osiander, it was the skepticism about religious subjectivity over and against the objective Word that came to dominate in Lutheran theology. Initially the form this took was quite subtle: the development of narrower accounts of the doctrine of justification by faith that explicitly excluded reference to its experiential context and effects, as can be found for example in the Formula of Concord. But the unintended byproduct of these new, more strictly anti-subjectivist articulations of justification by faith was a broader skepticism about embodied experience in mainstream Protestant theology. Movements like Pietism and Methodism soon arose as attempts to recover a sense of the importance experience in Christian life and piety; unsurprisingly, they were often dismissed by more traditional Protestants as “enthusiasts.” Modern theology has continued to reproduce this old debate and the anxieties that lie behind it in new forms; the paradigmatic example is Karl Barth’s ferocious rejection of the theological legacy of Friedrich Schleiermacher, as I seek to show in the chapter.

    Castelo seems to find this account useful enough, but he does not seem to be convinced it is adequate for giving a full account of modern theology’s anxiety about experience. I think he is ultimately right. But first it is worth saying a little more in defense of my genealogy of Protestant experience anxiety.

    First, the more deeply I dived into the history of the “enthusiasm” debate in the generations after the Protestant Reformation, the more I became convinced that, although it is not exhaustive, the basic story held up surprisingly well. “Enthusiasm” was a subject that was endlessly debated and fretted over in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries especially. It received extensive attention from philosophers as well as theologians (for example, Locke, Shaftesbury, Hume, and Kant all give classic treatments), and was a key polemical term in the critical reception of John Wesley’s ministry, amongst many others. Although there is much more to unpack here, including not least the ways the meaning of the “enthusiasm” altered and developed (for example, the way it came to be deployed as a counterpoint to rationality, not just the scriptural Word), there is little question that Luther’s polemics against the Schwärmer are at the headwaters of these discussions.

    Second, I found that the “enthusiasm” narrative also holds up much better as an account of Protestant anxiety about embodied experience than one of the leading alternatives: the well-known genealogical account of modernity as the ultimate product of philosophical moves made in the Middle Ages by Duns Scotus and William of Ockham. According to the latter story, Protestant theology was divorced from interest in the created order, including the created human bodies that have emotions and experiences, in a sense before it even began due to its implicit commitment to nominalism. This philosophical substructure, John Milbank and others have influentially contended, led inevitably to an “extrinsicist,” implicitly rationalist soteriology of justification. As I show at length in chapter 3, although the Scotus and Ockham narrative can seem compelling from ten feet in the air, it has a habit of falling apart quite rapidly once you start looking at what someone like Luther or Melanchthon actually wrote about justification or at how Protestants have actually deployed forensic soteriological categories in preaching and ministry.2

    And yet, reading Castelo’s response, I find myself nodding in vigorous agreement. He is surely right that there are many other factors to be explored than the legacy of the “enthusiasm” debate as we trace the roots of modern theology’s anxiety about embodied experience, and he is also right that the shape and significance of that anxiety will vary across contexts and time periods. The fact that one narrative genealogy seems to explain much more data than another does not mean that it explains everything! Indeed, I find the vision Castelo paints of “unleash[ing] new research trajectories” aimed at filling out this picture more comprehensively very exciting indeed. If my book does anything at all to inspire new work of this kind, it will have more than served its purpose.

    But Castelo also leaves me wondering what trajectories in particular he had in mind. The eclipse of the body in modernity is hardly something that only theologians have noticed. So where has this work already been begun, both in theology and beyond? I can think of a number of trajectories that have already borne fruit, such as Willie Jennings’s identification of the roots of theology’s dislocation from bodies and spaces in the history of transatlantic migration and especially the forced migration of slavery, or Ashon Crawley’s arguments about the legacy of Enlightenment philosophy in “a turning away, an aversion for the materiality of objects,” rooted not least in racial aversion to “certain anthropological bodies . . . in particular” (Blackpentecostal Breath, 115), or investigations into the history of gendered accounts of reason and emotion from scholars like Genevieve Lloyd, to name just three.

    I have been reading a good deal of Bruno Latour lately, and one very simple idea he has reinforced for me is the importance of remembering, when analyzing complex phenomena, that few things are monocausal. The best accounts are likely to illuminate networks of interrelated causes. The art, then, is to account for such complexity and multicausality as fully as possible, but without producing an account so complex it doesn’t really tell you anything actionable about the phenomenon being analyzed. I suspect that the sort of full-orbed account of theology’s experience anxiety that Castelo is pressing for would look something like this. Most likely, it will need to take the form of a cluster of works by a range of scholars, some exploring broader tendencies, and others examining dynamics of pneumatology, experience, and embodiment at a much more local level, in relation to particular historical moments and figures (and I am delighted to say that a number of doctoral students here in Cambridge are currently doing both with fantastic results).

    Ultimately, however, genealogy and diagnosis are just one focus of The Holy Spirit and Christian Experience, which seeks equally to begin the constructive work of repairing modern theology’s anxiety about experience. I am convinced, as I think is Castelo, that the most effective critiques are the ones that are paired with constructive alternatives—that open up viable new horizons rather than just identifying the very real problems with old ones. I have sought to do this in the book by suggesting what an experientially and pneumatologically integrated theology of grace might look like in a contemporary key (what I call “affective Augustinianism”). And yet Castelo’s word of caution is a salutary one. It is all too true that “people and movements tend to transition so readily in the neglect of the Spirit.” If the old patterns are not to be repeated, we must not rest until all their roots are exposed.


    1. See Simeon Zahl, “The Bondage of the Affections: Willing, Feeling, and Desiring in Luther’s Theology, 1513–25,” in The Spirit, Affectivity, and the Christian Tradition, ed. Amos Yong and Dale Coulter (University of Notre Dame Press, 2016), 234–52, and “Non-Competitive Agency and Luther’s Experiential Argument Against Virtue,” Modern Theology 35.2 (2018):199–222.

    2. For detailed versions of this argument, see chapter 3, as well as Simeon Zahl, “Non-Competitive Agency.”

David Fergusson

Response

Experiencing God Outside the Church

Simeon Zahl’s monograph is a creative recovery of a concept that has too long frightened us. Critiques of experience abound in the theological literature of the twentieth century, particularly in Protestant thought. Its use as a source in Schleiermacher and Herrmann was held to betoken a subjectivism in which God was sought within the psychological depths of the individual. From an epistemological perspective, this could only compromise the objectivity of the Word of God, or silence its claim upon us. And, from a soteriological perspective, a stress on Christian piety was adjudged to result in a presumptuous addition of our affective and moral responses to the once for all work of Christ. Furthermore, with the later accrual of philosophical and anthropological influences, it became commonplace amongst post-liberals to argue that all experience is theory laden and therefore shaped by language, culture, and practice. To this extent, religious experience was to be regarded as the effect of faith rather than its cause or setting.

Zahl challenges these nostrums in different ways, while recognising that they are not wholly without validity. The language of experience needs to be foregrounded, otherwise we have too little to say about grace, faith, participation in Christ, sanctification, and our actualisation of the Word of God. Theology cannot function without reference to the experience of Christians. This is the domain of the third article too often neglected or diminished, but now requiring revitalisation, not least in light of the global growth of Pentecostalism. This was forcefully illustrated for me recently by an African woman in our (Scottish Presbyterian) congregation. To our shame, she confessed that she had to suppress her emotions while attending Sunday worship. Zahl’s study suggests that the fault is not hers but a tradition that has for too long been nervous around the public expression of emotions.

His book contains a surprising number of moving parts as he develops an approach to Christian experience, while also tilting at various claims that have recently populated the field. Several elements of his position have already been iterated in a succession of important journal articles which also repay careful study. Despite the risk of oversimplifying his central thesis, I shall seek to delineate its key components before pressing several questions. Recent Protestant theology—the work of Torrance and Tanner is regularly cited—recognises the need to combine the priority of Christ’s work with a rich account of its effects within the Christian life. Though not wrong, these suffer from an unhelpful degree of abstraction that fails to specify exactly how our human participation works. What effects and affects take place in the life of the faithful? Attempts to answer this question often lapse into theological rhetoric or unintentional vagueness. Thomists, by contrast, generally have a much clearer account of what is involved through their exposition of the acquired and infused virtues. Yet there is both a drift from the christological setting of faith and an unrealistic appraisal of what is possible. The phenomenon of “Christian mediocrity” here raises its head. And this Nietzschean problem may also affect much recent Protestantism. Though Zahl doesn’t quite put it this way, if all these accounts of sacramental, spiritual, and moral practice are indeed accurate, then should we not expect Christians to perform much better than they actually do? This seems to me an important corrective to inflated estimates of the moral formation actually achieved by sacramental communities.

In response to this set of problems, Zahl intertwines insights from recent affect theory with a recovery of some distinctive Reformational insights. Recent work in psychology counteracts the aforementioned thesis that affective experience is linguistically constructed. Our material and bodily condition prevents such plasticity, thus ensuring a greater degree of constancy across cultures. This also helps to explain the phenomenon of “affective intransigence.” Within the life of faith, the constraints and impulses of our embodied nature continue to shape us, often exposing unruly elements of the self that are never wholly mastered or extinguished even in the most saintly of lives. Here Luther’s simul iustus et peccator needs to be heard again, though Zahl finds this more fully worked out by his Wittenberg colleague, Philip Melanchthon. In working faith within us, the Holy Spirit enables us both to receive the good news of a righteousness in Christ that God imputes to us, while simultaneously leading us into a new way of life. As the gospel is announced, there arises a profound sense of liberation with an entry to a mode of existence which is characterised by different delights attended by characteristic emotions. We are to think of justification and sanctification as distinguished but never separated. The constants of the human condition, moreover, entail that imputed righteousness remains normative not just in a sixteenth-century context of sin, guilt, and fear, but for every generation similarly afflicted no matter how differently this expressed. And this has important experiential outcomes for the Christian. The life of faith too can exhibit a moral and spiritual advance even amidst the continued antagonism of “flesh and spirit.” Here a further move takes place, as he appeals to an Augustinian notion of delight as the alternative to virtue theories that prescribe actions to which we are initially averse, in order eventually to acquire the requisite habit.

In this short sketch, I cannot do justice to the subtlety and complexity of Zahl’s argument. What is evident, however, is his accomplished historical scholarship, a welcome interaction with recent literature in critical theory, acute but fair exposition of opposing views, and an ability to weave together an impressive set of arguments in support of a position that is both evangelically adequate and pastorally plausible. As a sympathetic and appreciative reader, I offer the following queries some of which he has already gestured towards in his concluding remarks.

The discussion intends to release the concept of religious experience from earlier epistemological and apologetic projects. If we no longer deploy it as the starting point in theology, then it can be rehabilitated in more constructive ways by Christian self-description. That seems right to me, but it leaves open the question of whether there is an experience of God outside of the church that might characterise, however abstractly, our universal human condition. Calvin’s use of the “sensus divinitatis” was an attempt to give a phenomenological account of this, without reference to an epistemological foundation or an apologetic strategy. On one reading, Schleiermacher’s “feeling of absolute dependence” serves a similar purpose. I see no reason why Zahl’s project cannot accommodate such notions, nor indeed a wider sense of the Holy Spirit’s agency beyond the walls of the church. His project is of course about “Christian experience,” but it raises the question of whether there are other forms of religious or spiritual experience which can be set in relation to this, whether constructively or critically. His discussion of Christian religious affections also generates some normative questions. Should our assessment of theological claims be determined in part by an account of the affective and practical contexts in which these arise and flourish? The regular appeal to various projects of deconstruction, especially queer theology, seems to confirm this, as do the important remarks about “affective salience.”

A key question is whether Zahl’s own pneumatology satisfies the criteria by which he judges alternative approaches. In other words, can he avoid a lapse into either theological abstractionism or overinflated claims for the Christian life? Although, for the most part, he is constantly alert to this problem, I worry a bit about some of his remarks on conversion. “A theory of Christian identity also needs to do justice to New Testament descriptions of the punctiliarity of baptism in the Spirit and of the powerful affective immediacy often involved in Christian conversion” (212). The appeal to a sudden and momentary transitional experience appears to be the affective counterpart to the doctrine of justification here expounded. To be sure, one can appeal to some brief and dramatic examples of such punctiliar moments in the New Testament. But are these strikingly telescoped accounts to become normative for all subsequent Christian experience? Might there not be a multiplicity of ways of coming to faith which resist conformity to a single model? This strikes me as at least requiring further scrutiny, particularly in light of recent psychological literature on religious conversion which discerns a temporally extended process rather than a single event.1

This last point leads me to wonder whether the process of being socialised into the Christian faith may require greater use of notions of practice and habit than is generally conceded. Some alliances with Thomism may be required here. (At one point, admittedly, the argument seems to move in this direction.) In the context of recent work on neurophysiology, Simon Harak has written of the development of virtuous passions through spiritual exercises.2 Repeated habitual practice can reshape our bodily responses to stimuli, at least in some measure. Our worse selves can be constrained, tempered, and even redirected. Might there be ways in which a more Augustinian approach can appropriate this work? Do wise counselling and pastoral instruction not sometimes proceed along lines that encourage the development of new habits of body and mind? As he notes earlier in the book, Protestantism has often drawn upon Thomism. Zahl might worry here about the reappearance of a moralism that overburdens people and suppresses the more joyful notes elicited by the gospel tidings of comfort and joy. I share this anxiety, as I suspect did Torrance in his relentless critique of the psychologising tendences of seventeenth-century Reformed thought. But is the formation of good habits at least one element in the Christian life?

Zahl works hard to show the continuities between the anxieties of the sixteenth century and those of our own age. While much of this is persuasive, some things have undoubtedly changed. In particular, most of us seem much less terrorised by the prospect of hell than our sixteenth-century forebears. We do not share all the fears of the past in relation to divine retribution, though, as he points out, we may have generated some of our own signature anxieties in cravings for self-esteem and public recognition. But this leads me to ask whether some forms of Protestantism need to be adapted. Are we at risk of so stressing the depravity of our condition, perhaps to accentuate its solution, that we overburden people with long prayers of confession and impossible demands that further threaten their sense of self-worth? As Stephen Pattison has argued, a sense of shame is all too easily reinforced rather than dispelled.3 To put it bluntly, people should leave church feeling better about themselves in light of God’s grace, not worse. In this respect, Pentecostal worship is instructive, as are the studies of the faith of postmillennials. This is difficult territory with many pitfalls—the same doctrine of the church may have widely contrasting contexts and affective accompaniments in different locations—and it says much for Zahl’s approach that he has further raised our awareness of this. And, in doing so, he has impressively overcome the baleful division of systematic and practical theology. His fine book is a mature and accomplished treatment of a theme deserving renewed attention. He leaves us wanting more and looking forward to his next production.


  1. For example, Raymond F. Paloutzian, “Psychology of Religious Conversion and Spiritual Transformation,” in Oxford Handbook of Religious Conversion, ed. Lewis R. Rambo and Charles E. Faradien (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014), 217.

  2. G. Simon Harak, Virtuous Passions: The Formation of Christian Character (New York: Paulist, 1993).

  3. Stephen Pattison, Shame: Theory, Therapy, Theology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000).

  • Simeon Zahl

    Simeon Zahl

    Reply

    Reply to David Fergusson

    A fundamental project of The Holy Spirit and Christian Experience is the rehabilitation of “experience” as a theological category in the context of a long legacy of Protestant suspicion. It is in the Reformed tradition that some of the most formidable opposition to such a project has historically arisen, and I am therefore encouraged to see that my colleague David Fergusson, one of that tradition’s leading contemporary voices, has found my efforts to have been essentially successful. At any rate he finds my position “evangelically adequate and pastorally plausible,” which is good enough for me!

    Fergusson then presses me to think further on a number of points. Here I focus on three in particular.

    First, he asks whether my vision of the theology of the Holy Spirit is able to speak about the work of the Spirit, and especially experience of the Spirit, “outside of the church,” at least in the minimal sense that we find, for example, in Calvin’s account of the sensus divinitatis. I take Fergusson to be asking not about God the Spirit’s general sustaining presence in and to all creation, the assertion of which is theologically uncontroversial, but in the thicker sense of what in the terminology of the book might be called “practically recognizable” experiences of God.

    Reflecting on this question, I find myself running up against the problem of scholarly location—a problem made yet more acute in a book that calls for theology to be tested in experience. A key dimension of my argument about the Holy Spirit is that claims about the Spirit’s work in creatures can and should be informed and indeed tested, with various caveats, in experience. Thus a number of directions of argument in the book are consciously shaped, prompted, and galvanized by my own experience as a Christian and as a member of Christian communities. Although this methodological procedure is not explicit in the book in the sense of my recounting personal experiences directly on the page (as, for example, Ashon Crawley has done to such effect in recent work), nevertheless to the careful reader it will come as little surprise that my dissatisfaction with “legal fiction” critiques of the doctrine of justification by faith, my desire to make more room than one often finds in recent academic theology for sudden and dramatic encounter with the Holy Spirit, and my skepticism about strong claims for virtue ethics as descriptive of the primary engine of Christian transformation, are all directions of travel that are intellectually prompted by my own experience to one degree or another.

    In chapters 1 and 2 I argue that it is not actually possible to avoid drawing on experience in theology—as theologians we are always doing this whether we are aware of it or not—and indeed that as a methodological procedure the appeal to experience finds robust support in the doctrine of the Holy Spirit itself. But as a formal approach, testing theological claims in experience, even with all appropriate hedging, also has limitations. In this case, it restricts my ability as a theologian to speak with insight or confidence about experiences of God “outside of the church.” Although I would very much welcome the application or testing of any of my arguments to experiences “outside the church,” and I hope the book has helped open some worthwhile doors to such work, I wonder if this is a task best suited to someone other than myself.

    But that is not all that can be said. Taking a step back from discussion of claims about experience of God, I have sought to draw attention to how the categories of affect and emotion can provide a powerful conceptual and analytical bridge between the work of Christian theologians and that of other scholars interested in religious experience and religious practice. Here, as readers of chapters 4 and 5 will be aware, I have learned a great deal from affect theorists like Eve Sedgwick, Lauren Berlant, and Sara Ahmed, as well as scholars like Donovan Schaefer and Manuel Vásquez who have brought such insights to bear so promisingly in the domain of religious studies. Affect on its own terms is no sensus divinitatis, but attention to affect does seem to bear within it a generative troubling of too-easy distinctions between experiences “inside” versus “outside” the church.

    A key insight of recent affect theory is that affects are not simply epiphonema of discourse. Although language and cultural practice, including religious language and religious practice, can and do have shaping effects on affects to some degree, affects also exhibit an agency and an intransigence that significantly precedes and exceeds the discursive contexts in which they arise. A vital implication of these insights, I increasingly believe, is that analysis of affective experience has the potential to become a major new frontier in ecumenical and comparative theology, and indeed to scramble some of the old battle lines between theology and religious studies.1

    Fergusson also asks whether the affective account of the theology of salvation that I provide in the later chapters of the book gives too much precedence to relatively sudden and dramatic conversion experiences. He wonders whether I have risked making certain New Testament accounts of the receipt of the Spirit and the kindling of Christian belief “normative,” when in fact there are “a multiplicity of ways of coming to faith,” and he rightly points out that even very dramatic conversions prove under scrutiny to involve a “temporally extended process.”

    This too is an astute question, and I found myself wrestling with it repeatedly as I worked on the book. To start, I would contest the characterization that I have made a particular kind of conversion experience normative. In chapter 5 I devote a lengthy section to this concern (“The Enigma of the Heart”), concluding that “the fact that one can speak usefully about certain affective patterns involved in the experience of divine grace, and indeed that the theologian is bound, on scriptural and pastoral grounds, to attempt to speak wisely about such patterns, must always be held together with the equally scriptural and pastoral insights about the Spirit’s freedom and the heart’s inscrutability” (208).

    My argument, as I see it, is less concerned with making dramatic and punctiliar experiences normative than it is with a tendency in some theological writing to use a few obvious theological problems that can emerge in simplistic accounts of such experiences as an excuse to avoid taking such experiences seriously at all in theology. When we are too quick to deconstruct Pentecostal, pietist, and evangelical claims about dramatic conversion experiences, for example, as theologians we risk (a) rendering the experiences of vast numbers of contemporary Christians theologically invisible, and (b) eliding the undeniable emphasis on experience of the Spirit as an irruptive, dramatic, identity-altering event in key sections of the book of Acts as well as the Pauline epistles.

    What is needed, rather, is an account that can do justice both to the quiet and the gradual and to the dramatic and the punctiliar in Christian conversion. And it is just this that I have sought to provide in The Holy Spirit and Christian Experience through a focus on the experiential category of affect, which is well suited to accounting for both dimensions. How successful I have been is of course a different matter!

    Fergusson’s final question is the one that points most clearly beyond the book to new horizons of inquiry into Christian experience. In arguing for more significant commonalities between the anxieties of the sixteenth century and those of the present than has lately been assumed in Christian theology, he asks, as Castelo also does, have I failed to do justice to some of the real experiential differences that nevertheless obtain across eras?

    Certainly it is true that in chapter 4 I draw on affect theory to protest the common assumption in recent theology and biblical studies, associated not least with postliberal, cultural-linguistic accounts of doctrine, that experience is best understood to be firmly downstream of cultural discourse and cultural practice. According to this perspective, affects are so plastic, and affective experience so socially constructed, that we must be rigorously careful to avoid assumptions of continuity when comparing the experiences of Christians across contexts and time periods. In a key section of chapter 4 (“Affective Predicates of Salvation”), I engage in an extended analysis of Krister Stendahl’s classic and still influential article “The Apostle Paul and the Introspective Conscience of the Modern West” to show that its argument depends quite precisely on constructivism of this sort.

    While researching the book, I became convinced that in the wake of Sedgwick’s watershed essay “Shame in the Cybernetic Fold” (a founding text for much contemporary affect theory) a strongly constructivist account of affective experience like Stendahl’s is simply no longer tenable on its own terms. For example, to imply, as Stendahl’s account ultimately does, that the “fear of death” referred to in Hebrews 2:15, the “terror of death” described in Melanchthon’s sixteenth-century Apology of the Augsburg Confession, and the feelings that gripped me on the way to the hospital for an unexpected cancer scan a few years ago, are likely to be profoundly incommensurate experiences because they occurred in different epochs and cultural contexts, is just too simplistic to be convincing after Sedgwick.

    And yet of course discursive contexts shape our experience in significant ways, and of course the concepts and practices available to us have a nontrivial effect on what labels our affects get attached to, how we interpret our experiences, and what we do with them. It is self-evidently not the same thing, on a range of fronts, to manage anxiety by going to a priest for confession, as one might have done in Melanchthon’s time, and to manage it by going to a psychiatrist for a benzodiazepine prescription, as we might do today. But it does not follow from these differences that theologians must throw up our hands in despair at ever communicating with the “foreign country” of the past. What it means instead, I would suggest, is that the most interesting questions and the most persuasive answers are likely to lie in the wide, exciting space between constructivist and essentialist accounts of human experience.

    To take Fergusson’s important example of the widespread diminishment of fear of hell over the past four hundred years: if we want a historically persuasive as well as theologically viable analysis of this phenomenon and of its implications for an experientially engaged Christian theology, we must start by ridding ourselves of simplistic assumptions of deep, potentially unbridgeable discontinuity between past and present fears of impending judgment or retribution. What we must look for instead is a variegated assemblage of factors, some more continuous, some more discontinuous. It is only then that we can begin to ask the really interesting questions with the right level of granularity: questions about the relationship between older theologies of sin and contemporary accounts of moral pathology; questions about the social cognitive texture of past generations’ fears about hell (for example, was there also a fear of permanent social and emotional loss at work alongside fears about physical torment, and if so what were its contours in particular cases?); questions about social and theological imaginaries and how they shape our conceptions of death and afterlife, and how they are built out of affective assemblages that also have significant power to resist discursive transformation; questions about how and why soteriological universalism has become a widespread (if often tacit) operative position in much contemporary academic theology, and about how this assumption so often shapes contemporary readings of early and premodern Christian texts.

    As I hope these questions begin to indicate, recognition that affective experiences are neither simply epiphenomena of culture nor fixed, ahistorical universals opens the door for a much richer analytical vocabulary for making sense of Christian experience than either perspective has been able to achieve on its own. If The Holy Spirit and Christian Experience can play some small role in drawing theologians’ attention beyond the old constructivist binaries of Stendahl and the cultural-linguistic school and toward this new hermeneutical horizon, then a major goal of the book will have been achieved.


    1. This is the subject of Donovan Schaefer and my current Templeton-funded collaborative project, “Affect and Knowledge-Production in Theology and Religious Studies.”

Karen Kilby

Response

Zahl’s Contributions

Simeon Zahl offers a many-stranded, carefully constructed argument of The Holy Spirit and Christian Experience. It is a rich and complex work. Different readers will focus on different aspects of the whole: for me, three contributions to contemporary theology particularly stand out.

The first is Zahl’s defence of the importance of experience. In many quarters of course this will not sound like news. But for those influenced by Karl Barth and by George Lindbeck’s rejection of experiential-expressivism in the Nature of Doctrine, Zahl’s argument here is highly significant. He offers a historical account of how modern theology, especially in Protestant form, came to be so nervous about experience; he does conceptual work to distinguish among different ways experience can play a role in theology (engagement with experience is not always apologetic, not always seeking a universal foundation for theology); he develops an analysis of the role of mood, emotion and affect within all reasoning; he points to central moments in the tradition where theological reflection manifestly draws on experience (from Peter in Acts and Paul in Galatians, to Augustine in relation to grace and Luther in relation to justification),1 and to classic theological debates where defence of a doctrine includes an argument about its “affective salience,” the consequences the doctrine will have for the emotional life of the believer. The cumulative effect of these different strands of argument is powerful: after Zahl, it is going to seem silly, and dated, to imagine that one could engage in a traditionally rooted theology while turning one’s back on experience.

I can attest to the significance of what Zahl does here by reference to my own work on Karl Rahner. Rahner is often dismissed by ecumenically minded Protestants, and some Catholics, on the grounds that he represents a liberal/modern /apologetic/foundationalist version of Catholicism. If Zahl’s book had been in existence earlier, then my own arguments to show that Rahner’s emphasis on the category of experience does not make him an apologist or a foundationalist would have been a great deal easier, or perhaps not even necessary. In relation to this particular figure, one might say, I have also made an attempt to push back against modern theology’s anxiety around experience, but Zahl has done the work at a much more general level, and in a much more thorough way.

A second component of Zahl’s larger argument I found particularly significant is his diagnosis of a tendency to abstraction in contemporary theology. In many cases, when systematic theologians get to a point where one expects them to be talking about something that connects to life, to experience, to the concrete, to that which is “practically recognizable”—when for instance, they are discussing the role of the Spirit in sanctification and one anticipates comments on the way people do and don’t change—there is a sudden and mysterious “swerve” away. The “subtle but powerful walls” that modern Christian theology has built between theology and lived experience make themselves felt, and we are offered nothing but abstract claims which could mean nearly anything in terms of the concrete shape of a life.

I am persuaded Zahl is right about this tendency to “swerve”—he provides some striking examples, and it would not be hard to find others. It is an analysis which, among other things, can give focus and precision to a widely held worry about the separation of theology and spirituality. And yet there is something in the way Zahl frames the issue that is troubling. He is very clear as to what recent theologians do not do, which is to write about real experience, in time, in bodies, in relation to emotions and desires and things that happen to people in “practically recognisable” ways. What they do instead, he suggests, is to veer into an ontological or metaphysical language. Once one notices the recurring distinction between the metaphysical and ontological, on the one hand, and the temporal, embodied, affective, and recognisable, on the other, it becomes puzzling. I don’t think Zahl intends to set up a contrast between two spheres, between a world of emotion and concrete things on the one hand, and a timeless, disembodied realm beyond all experience on the other. And I don’t think he means to suggest, in using the language of “ontology” in relation to the latter, that only the disembodied and timeless truly have being. But this is the direction in which some of the language points. The very framework within which he is trying to promote attention to experience, bodies and affect seems to presuppose, and give a subtle priority to, an alternate timeless and bodiless realm. On this front, it seems to me, there might still be a little work to be done. But Zahl accomplishes so much in this volume as a whole, it is only fair on his part to leave a little work for someone else.

The third element of the argument that stands out for me is Zahl’s retrieval and defence of classical Protestant patterns of thought around justification by faith and sanctification. He pushes back against a range of critics who want to move away from the classic “forensic” understanding of justification in favour of a more participatory account: on the one hand the critics are wrong to cast justification by faith as mere “legal fiction” and mere propositionalism; on the other, the participation-centred understandings of salvation do not do what they claim, because they remain abstract, finding little purchase in experience.

Zahl’s retrieval of themes from Luther and Melanchthon (and behind them, Augustine) is, I think, a brilliant piece of ressourcement, faithful to the tradition to which it is a return while also a fresh and challenging intervention into contemporary debate. Justification by faith and the classical Protestant “disjunctive” understanding of the working of grace become, in Zahl’s hands, genuine possibilities for belief in our own time: psychologically plausible, experientially concrete, realistic and compassionate. Zahl is capable of bringing out, in a way that can be understood by an outsider, the deep and continuing attractiveness of these traditional Protestant patterns of thought. His retrieval of an “affective Augustinianism” will have, I think, a particularly wide appeal.

I would like to end this review of The Holy Spirit and Christian Experience by taking a step back and reflecting a little on the sheer difficulty of reviewing it. I am conscious in what I have written so far of plucking three elements from a larger, carefully interwoven whole, and of doing a certain violence to the whole in the plucking. While focusing on classical Protestant ressourcement, for instance, I haven’t mentioned the illuminating discussions of recent neo-Thomism. I haven’t touched on the careful treatment of biblical, especially New Testament, texts and scholarship which is a rich strand through the volume, nor the fascinating combination of unexpected sources—the way at one point insights from queer theory, for example, are shown to illuminate and reinforce Augustine’s thought. I haven’t directly discussed pneumatology or affect theory, either of which might be viewed as the centre of the volume; I have not even fully laid out the connections between the three components of the argument that I do discuss. My review is not, in other words, doing any kind of justice to the architecture of the argument as a whole. One reason for this is that I can hope for other Syndicate reviewers to cover other aspects of the book, but my neglect also arises from the fact that Zahl’s seems to me quite a hard argument to capture well in a brief piece of commentary. This is a clearly written book, but it is also an unusually intricate one. Zahl fights on many fronts, knitting his argument from interventions in a range of distinct debates, and it makes for a complexly structured whole.

It is not an easy thing to meet all the expectations placed on a systematic theologian, and one way of thinking about the intricacy of Zahl’s argument is that he shows what emerges when someone actually does manage to meet all these expectations. This is what it looks like, one might say, when a theologian genuinely works in a way that is biblically rooted, historically rich, and engaged in contemporary debates, while also combining commitment to a particular tradition with ecumenical generosity and interdisciplinary expansiveness, bringing together careful conceptual analysis with practical and pastoral relevance, and when all this is done with proper attention to the scholarly literature in each of the areas touched upon, and with a self-reflexive clarity. It might be possible to use Zahl’s book, then, as a case study with students, to show them everything that is expected in putting together an argument in systematic theology—or one might hesitate to do so, for fear of leaving them daunted.

Another way to think about the intricacy and complexity of the argument, however, is that it contributes to a certain tension in this book, a tension between what Zahl says and the way he says it. This is a book which argues very effectively that experience and affect permeate every aspect of Christian doctrine—how it arises, how it is reflected on, how it is defended, what it is aimed at. And yet the careful, scholarly, academic idiom in which he argues for all this is one which seems to detach the argument from any particular person’s experience—the author’s or the reader’s—and invite us to reflect on texts and ideas and theories at some distance from ourselves. Zahl defines his terms with admirable care, for instance, and tends to return to them repeatedly, in a way which supports the precision and clarity of the argument, and helps hold it together in its complexity, but this is not necessarily a strategy one would use if one were more focused on the “affective effect” of one’s prose. (“Affective effect” is a phrase Zahl uses a number of times, and to my mind it itself captures the issue quite nicely. It is more precise than reference to “emotional impact” or “gut response” would be, but it is also—or at least so it seems to me—a much more emotionally distancing term.)

Ultimately, it wouldn’t be fair to hold this element of tension between style and content against The Holy Spirit and Christian Experience. Zahl is attempting to challenge the anti-experiential instincts of a major strand of modern theology. These instincts are deeply held, and are not likely to be given up lightly. If his argument is to have an impact, he has to couch it in a language and style which gives his audience no easy option to dismiss it. He is unlikely to succeed in undercutting such a long-held prejudice, in other words, if he unfolds his own argument as anything other than systematic theology of the most transparently rigorous and scholarly kind. So if a conclusion to draw from The Holy Spirit and Christian Experience might be that theologians should wear their rigour and their scholarship lightly so as not to detract from the experiential and emotional impact of their work, this is not something it would have been wise for Zahl to attempt in The Holy Spirit and Christian Experience.


  1. Might it have been possible to add Karl Barth’s rejection of liberal theology to this list? Was it not precisely Barth’s experience of shock and disappointment in his teacher’s actions in the run up to the first world War which proved decisive in shaping the direction of his theology?

  • Simeon Zahl

    Simeon Zahl

    Reply

    Reply to Karen Kilby

    Karen Kilby has shaped my thinking as strongly as any contemporary theologian, and I am very grateful for her generous and characteristically incisive comments on The Holy Spirit and Christian Experience. I want to pick up two threads from Kilby’s response. The first is about my critique of theological work that operates in a primarily ontological or metaphysical register, and the second is about the book’s rhetorical and argumentative style.

    As Kilby observes, a central distinction throughout the book is between theological work that engages with “practically recognizable” experience—experience that takes place in the realm of bodies and affects and concrete histories—and theological work that fails to engage with such experience, exhibiting instead a kind of complacency with theological abstraction. My claim is that one subtle but common mechanism by which attention to embodied experience has been eclipsed in modern theology has been a de facto restriction of theological claims about how grace works on the human person through the Spirit to claims about how grace works on their soul or on their being.

    Thus when T. F. Torrance claims that “we must regard the activity of the Holy Spirit as actualizing our union and communion with God through Christ in the actual structure of our human, personal and social being,” but then fails at any point to specify what effects this union has in the embodied experience of a Christian (see pp. 95–101), I argue that this is evidence of a pneumatological and soteriological deficiency in his thought that is also observable in a good deal of modern theology more widely. As I put it in the book, here Torrance is deploying “a widely used register of theological speech that relies on ontological language that may sound and even be theologically ‘correct’ but which serves in practice to obfuscate questions of how doctrines actually come to have experiential impact in human lives” (73).

    What is this “ontological” language? In soteriology, classic terminologies that can serve the obfuscating function I am describing include union with Christ, participation in God, and theosis, as well as more general references to the work of the Holy Spirit in the soul or else the “being” of the Christian. That these categories have in fact been deployed in this way in modern soteriology well beyond Torrance is a phenomenon I document at length in chapters 2 and 3 of the book.

    Kilby points out a significant problem latent in my distinction. In characterizing the abstracted register of theological speech that I am targeting as a complacency with “metaphysical” or “ontological” language, as I regularly do, she wonders if I am unwittingly—even despite myself—committing myself to the very unconvincing idea that things that happen in the realm of experience and embodiment are less ontologically real than that which is “disembodied and timeless.” Am I unintentionally reinscribing the very bifurcation between “ontology” and experience I am trying to critique?

    I think Kilby is partially right but not completely right. Certainly I must concede that I have not adequately foreclosed such a reading of my argument, and I am glad for the opportunity to clarify here.

    First, as Kilby is aware, I draw the language of “ontological” accounts of grace from Karl Rahner, who in his essay “Religious Enthusiasm and the Experience of Grace” critiques theologies of grace that seem operate in the realm of “purely ontological reality” and thereby fail to be able to say anything about what happens in what he calls the “realm of consciousness.” I found Rahner’s use of the language of ontology in this context helpful for explaining what I was finding elsewhere in my research (Torrance, for example, constantly describes the operation of grace in terms of its effects on the “being” or “existence” of Christians).

    Second, and importantly: my intention throughout these discussions in the book is to reintegrate metaphysical and experiential discourses in the theology of grace rather than to oppose them or to prioritize one over the other. This is why, for example, I am very careful to avoid claiming that assertions like Torrance’s about the “actualization” of communion with God “in the structure of our being” are untrue statements simply because they deploy this “ontological” register. My argument is rather that the way these terminologies are deployed often perpetuates a pneumatological and soteriological deficiency in contemporary Christian thought, serving in practice to provide theological cover for avoiding dealing with embodied experience in Christian theology.

    Indeed, if Kilby’s worry is that I am still implicitly assuming that “only the disembodied and timeless truly have being,” if anything I suspect my argument may actually press in the opposite direction. In my view, it is the claims made using “purely” ontological language to describe the work of the Spirit in the operation of grace that are most at risk of failing to designate what is actually real. Thus my critique in chapter 5 of accounts of sanctification that simply assert a change in Christian moral powers via the instantaneous infusion of grace in the soul through baptism, rather than also explaining how this infusion actually works in bodies and minds (here I give examples from John Webster as well as neo-Thomism), is that such accounts are not falsifiable in experience. In other words, they make room, in principle, for the Christian to claim “ontological” holiness without having actually to do, think, or feel anything holy; they open a space where the language of holy being can at times be at odds with “actual” being.

    My response to Kilby, then, is that when I am critiquing recent theological deployments of ontological language and categories in the theology of grace, I am not yet discussing ontology as such. Rather, I am critiquing a “register of theological speech” that relies heavily on ontological language and terminologies while being strangely silent about experience.

    Even so however, I must admit that Kilby’s observation still has bite. Through it she presses me—gently, shrewdly, firmly—to spell out my own philosophical presuppositions more explicitly than I have done in the book. Every theology has a metaphysics underlying it, and my “affective Augustinianism” is no exception. But the task of articulating that metaphysics will have wait for another piece.

    I turn now to Kilby’s discussion of my rhetorical and argumentative style in The Holy Spirit and Christian Experience. Here I also want to respond to Carnes’s similarly illuminating comments about the affective potential of doing theology as literature.

    Kilby, like Carnes, recognizes “a certain tension” in the book “between what Zahl says and the way he says it.” Although a core theme of the book is the irreducibility of affect and experience in theological discourse, Kilby points out that you wouldn’t necessarily know it from the “careful, scholarly, academic idiom in which he argues”’ Anglophone theology today is increasingly open to formal experimentation, and many of the most effective recent examples—Carnes’s Motherhood: A Confession is an excellent case in point—explicitly foreground the author’s subjectivity and experience as one of their tools of persuasion and imagination-shaping. Why did I not do so too? Why, as a theologian deeply concerned with the reintegration of experience and emotion in theological work, did I choose a scholarly idiom that seems deliberately to “detach the argument from any particular person’s experience,” as Kilby puts it?

    The first, relatively mundane answer is the one that Kilby anticipates: I was aware from the outset that I was trying to say some things that I expected to be controversial. To critique the widespread theological embrace of the category of participation, or the recent ascendance of virtue ethics as the primary theological theory of sanctification, or the ecumenical near-consensus since the 1980s that forensic justification has become a bankrupt category in soteriology, is to challenge deeply held contemporary theological convictions, and so to invite resistance. I had also learned the hard way while presenting this material at conferences and seminars that the category of “experience” is one that is unusually prone to theological misunderstanding and terminological confusion. My way of responding to these pressures was to double down on tools like textual support and argumentative clarity, and to avoid language that I was concerned might sacrifice conceptual precision in order to gain rhetorical power.

    But there is a deeper point worth making here too. To write and argue in this sort of “emotionally distanced” way, as Kilby puts it, is not the same thing as ignoring the power and centrality of affective dynamics in knowledge-production. Certainly it is true that modern scholarly idioms have at times served to repress or sublimate experiential dynamics in theology. And it is equally true that formal stylistic devices like personal narratives, self-referentiality, incorporation of non-textual art forms, or the use of non-linear and poetic forms of discourse can be powerful tools for reintroducing a lost experiential register into our theology. If my arguments about the Holy Spirit, emotion, and experience are on the right track at all, then Carnes is surely correct in her suggestion that my approach aligns with contemporary dismantlings of modern myths of affectless scholarly objectivity, and as such is highly sympathetic to these more experimental and innovative approaches.

    However, it is also the case that a theologian’s personal experience can inform their writing in ways that, while less on the surface than in formal techniques like these, remain powerful. As I argue in the first chapter of the book, in our theological reasoning and writing we are in fact always deploying experience to one degree or another. The real question is not whether we are to incorporate our experience in theology, but how to do it well, given the fact that we are always already doing it anyway.

    And as I have already mentioned in my response to Fergusson, a number of key directions of argument in The Holy Spirit and Christian Experience were consciously shaped, prompted, and galvanized by my own experience as a Christian and as a member of Christian communities. Here I can put it even more strongly: in a very real sense, the book is an extended theological meditation on my own encounters with the Spirit of God in the contingencies of my particular life and community in light of the wider witness of the church. The fact that these experiential dynamics are not always visible on the surface of the writing does not make them any less real or any less significant for the work. If theology’s future is one in which the theologian’s biography, location, and affective life might be regarded as powerful assets rather than just as dangerous methodological liabilities, then it seems to me that we need to develop a wide range of registers for integrating experience into our work, including but also not limited to the literary techniques described above.

    The Holy Spirit and Christian Experience is an experiment in one such register. It is a work of theology that is birthed in experience and saturated in experience. But it is also one that recognizes that sometimes affects and experiences are most effective in generating practical change when they are first transmuted and distilled into formalized claims in order to make them available for a particular kind of discussion, dissemination, and critique.

    As I see it, ideas, arguments, and the terminologies that go with them are not opposite to affects—not even when they are expressed in an “emotionally distancing” manner. Rather, they are (amongst other things!) technologies that carry affects and allow them to circulate. As I argue in the book, if we want to get fully to grips with theological ideas we need to recognize that they often have powerful affective salience for Christians in their lives, generating feelings and experiences relatively directly as well informing practices that regulate feelings and produce experiences in more mediated ways. Related to this is the fact that ideas and arguments often tap powerfully into existing affects, surfacing them, transforming them, and redirecting them. This is a point that theorists like Rita Felski and Sara Ahmed have drawn out so effectively—drawing attention, for example, to the archaeologies of suffering and anger, fear and hope that undergird cultural critique and render it persuasive. And that is not all: ideas and terminologies also bear the traces of past experience and past emotion within them. Understanding a concept or a distinction well includes tracing the histories of feeling that we always find etched into the structure of ideas once we start looking. To take just one example that is central in my own work: there would be no Protestant theology of justification without a monk from Wittenberg who at some point between 1505 and 1515 CE became desperate for consolation. As I hope I have shown in the book, the history of feeling that lies behind Luther’s famous doctrine is not some epiphenomenal residue of a more fundamental conceptual work; it is actually vitally relevant to contemporary wrestlings with the theology of salvation.

    Each of these examples merits much further unpacking than there is space for here. For now, I hope that they have given some indication of why I think it is possible for affects and experiences to be “distanced” from concrete experiences of the feeling body—in this case, by being intellectualized and argued over in a particular idiom—without thereby being underestimated, or indeed ceasing to be powerfully present. In our overdue recognition of the irreducibility of affect and experience in theology, we must not forget that ideas, too, are technologies of experience.

Shares
Verified by ExactMetrics