Seriously Dangerous Religion
By
9.13.15 |
Symposium Introduction
At one point near the end of Iain Provan’s Seriously Dangerous Religion: What the Old Testament Really Says and Why it Matters, Provan writes, “I hope. . . I have done a decent job of explaining biblical faith.” Such a modest statement belies an underlying sense of frustration concerning the necessity of such an explanation. Though the book acts mainly as a biblical theology driven by a narrative critical reading of Genesis, SDR also acts a response to a “thoroughgoing modern assault on the Old Story from all sides,” namely, proponents of the so-called “Axial Age,” “Dark Green Religion,” and “New Atheism.”
In his previous book, Convenient Myths: The Axial Age, Dark Green Religion, and the World that Never Was, Iain Provan soberly dismantles the idea that the key to solving our ecological crisis is to give up on monotheism and retrieve earlier myths that arose between the 8th and 3rd centuries BCE or in prehistoric primitivism, respectively. In Seriously Dangerous Religion, Provan includes other subjects of his frustration, namely, the “New Atheists” and really anyone else who ignorantly dismisses the Old Testament as a trustworthy guide to modern life, or worse, considers the Bible a dangerous tool promoting violence against people and the earth.
Seriously Dangerous Religionis a more constructive response to Christianity’s critics than Convenient Myths. Most chapters begin by posing broad philosophical question—”What is the World?” “Who is God?” “Who are Man and Woman?” etc.—which Provan answers through close readings of Genesis. Genesis, he explains, is the foundational story upon which we “can build a moral vision,” and though his book is primarily theological, the moral vision Provan details in his exegesis of Genesis makes up the heart of SDR—the “why it matters” from the title. “How am I to relate to God?” asks one chapter, followed by “how am I to relate to my neighbor?” (‘Love all, trust a few, do wrong to none’) “How am I to relate to the rest of creation?” (by “look[ing] after the earth on behalf of its owner”), and “Which society should I be helping to build?” (“biblical faith does not advocate passivity with respect to politics, but it does not advocate, either, a utopian approach”). These questions are all answered based on Provan’s exegesis of Genesis in the context of the Canon while directing the reader back to the earlier chapters that lay the theological foundation for his ethics.
One of the more unique aspects of SDR comes at the end of each of the chapters where Provan compares what the Old Testament says about the world, God, and our neighbors to other religions, including, but not limited to Ancient Near Eastern polytheism, Platonism, Confucianism, Buddhism, Hinduism, and Islam. Thus, SDR is no less than a biblical theology, a collection of detailed exegeses, a biblical ethics, and comparative religion, all packaged in the conceit of a response to the Bible’s critics.
Though Seriously Dangerous Religion ostensibly continues an ongoing conversation (argument, really) between Christianity and its cultured despisers using a multiplicity of tools to construct a sound argument, one cannot help but notice a sideways glance toward a large contingent of Christians themselves—those who hold the Bible in one hand while in the other hand degrade God’s creation, exploit the poor and weak by destroying the Sabbath, mistreat the foreigner, and more. The exegesis and interpretation, therefore, shows that the Bible is not what the New Atheists, Dark Green Religionists, and Axial Agers think it is, but nor is it what many of the Bible’s popularizers think it is, either.
As careful and reasonable Provan is in his writing, he still participates in an argument and argument invites response, even by those largely sympathetic to his positions. What follows is a dialogue between Christian scholars of the Old Testament and Theology and Provan, himself, regarding SDR. Ephraim Radner expresses concern that the very nature of apologetics is not dangerous enough to warrant the title of the book, despite Provan’s skills in undertaking the project, especially given the mysterious nature of suffering in the matrix of human life. Sara Koenig questions the assertions of truth underlying Provan’s argument and which he addresses directly in chapter 13. That is, is “what the Bible really says” really just “what Iain Provan prefers the Bible to say?” Douglas Earl expresses a similar concern regarding the certitude of Provan’s claims, arguing that SDR is more colored by Christian tradition than is let on in the description of his exegesis. In other words, SDR is not “what the Bible really says” but what Christian tradition says the Bible really says. Stephen Chapman expresses a related concern, but wishes Provan had engaged more explicitly with Christian tradition in his book. More importantly, Chapman is impressed by the breadth of Provan’s engagement with other religions and wonders how accurate are the descriptions of those religions’ beliefs. Lastly, Barnabas Asprey is concerned that Provan is repeating some of the mistakes of the biblical theology movement by offering a perspective, “detached from any reading tradition.” Provan has responded to each of these panelists and we invite the conversation to continue between them and you.
Panelists
Ephraim Radner
Sara Koenig
Douglas Earl
Stephen Chapman
Barnabas Aspray
About the Author
Iain Provan is the Marshall Sheppard Professor of Biblical Studies at Regent College in Vancouver, BC.
9.16.15 |
Response
Which Story Do You Prefer?
AFTER I FINISHED READING Ian Provan’s Seriously Dangerous Religion, I was reminded of Yann Martel’s novel The Life of Pi. In the final chapter, the title character—Pi Patel—is interviewed by men who are seeking an account of why the ship on which he was traveling sank, and how he survived for over six months at sea. Pi tells them two stories: the first is a fantastic one about being on a lifeboat with a fully grown Bengal Tiger, and the second is a gruesome account in which the few other human survivors kill and cannibalize each other. Neither story gives a precise explanation as to why or how the ship sank, so Pi then asks his listeners, “Which story do you prefer? Which is the better story?” They answer that the story with the animals is the better story, to which Pi responds, “Thank you. And so it goes with God.”
Provan is doing something similar to Pi, but obviously, “similar” is not “the same.” One major difference is that instead of simply asking questions of preference or comparison, as Pi does, Provan tells his readers that the biblical story, or, as he calls it, “the Old Story” is better than others. Those others include the three other major metanarratives he introduces in the introduction: the story of the axial age, the story of the dark green golden age, and the story of the scientific new age. Provan discusses the first two in greater detail in his other book, Convenient Myths, which he describes as a “companion” to this one. The third metanarrative, that of the scientific new age, is the one told—and preferred—by the new atheists. Throughout Simply Dangerous Religion, Provan highlights how his reading of the Old Story differs from these other “competing” (348) narratives.
Provan also compares and contrasts “the Old Story” with Western and Eastern thought, including philosophers like Plato and Confucius, and other religions such as Buddhism, Hinduism and Islam. While he points out places of overlap and similarities—such as how individual elements of Buddhist thought are compatible with biblical faith (215)—he is particularly concerned with clarifying the differences. For example, Provan writes, “There is one important respect, however, in which Plato’s thinking about the natural world is somewhat similar to biblical thinking, so long as we are prepared to make some important distinctions” (243). And in reference to the question “How am I to relate to my neighbor,” Provan explains, “The case of Confucianism is instructive, not least because it illustrates well the problem in assuming that any particular religion or philosophy is similar to another in its overall teaching just because it happens to possess certain apparent similarities in the details” (217). Indeed, Provan is especially concerned with sweeping generalizations about religions that reduce them all to a common core (218, 392). The character Pi understands himself to be a Hindu, a Christian and a Muslim. When told by religious leaders that he must choose, Pi responds by saying, “Bapu Ghandi said, ‘All religions are true.’ I just want to love God.” Such a response may seem to fall into the generalizing or reductionistic traps that Provan seeks to avoid. However, I find in Pi’s answer something important about the relational aspect of religion that rings true with my own confessional stance as a Christian seeking to have a relationship with a personal God.
Another place where Provan differs from Pi is that in the novel, choosing one story over another is a question of preference, while for Provan it is a question of “truth.” Early in Seriously Dangerous Religion, Provan explains that he is not primarily interested in the historical and scientific veracity of the biblical texts and instead seeks to explore its religious and philosophical claims (15–17). Toward the end of his book, in chapter 13, Provan examines the question of truth, which includes such sub questions as, “Is it coherent? Is it true to the facts, and does it make sense of them? Is it truer to the facts and does it make better sense of them than competing stories?” (348). Provan desires for Christians to use reason and logic to examine their claims of faith, and he provides a model for this when he writes, “I accept the obligation to justify what I said in chapter 1 . . .” (353). Much of Seriously Dangerous Religion reminds me of other theologies of the Old Testament, such as those written by Walter Eichrodt, Gerhard von Rad, and Walter Brueggemann. Chapter 13 caused me to think that instead, Simply Dangerous Religion is a book of apologetics, more concerned to clarify “what we should believe,” than simply “what we believe” or even “why we believe.” For von Rad and Brueggemann, in particular, the Old Testament is a record of Israel’s testimony about God, and while testimony does have a persuasive element to it, testimony is never solely about the facts. Truth—in testimony—becomes something more experiential than something that is simply factual. Whenever I think about the nature of truth, I cannot help but be reminded of Pilate’s question to Jesus in John 18:38, “What is truth?” It has always struck me as ironic that Pilate asks the question to the one who is truth incarnate. In John’s gospel, in particular, truth is not simply a philosophical or intellectual preposition, but is embodied, desiring a relationship of love.
Provan is honest about his personal preferences for “the Old Story.” He argues that the biblical story is a compelling one, a story that deserves to be taken seriously as a series of truth claims about the world and human place within it (17). Against accusations of biblical faith as escapist, he asserts that biblical faith calls humans to work for good in the world (152–53). What makes the biblical text dangerous is its insistence on good, and its ability to clearly point out—and ideally work against—what is not good. Provan even asserts that “when the biblical story is properly understood, it provides a point of departure for precisely the path out of trouble and into a better future, for humanity and for the planet, for which its detractors are often looking”(353).
In fact, one of the problems is that the biblical story has been misunderstood or told in inaccurate ways. Provan explains that there is a “gap between what the OT really says and what the modern storytellers claim it says” (13). He also explains that misunderstanding has affected both outsiders and insiders; moreover, it is some of the insider mistakes that have influenced the views of outsiders as to what it says, particularly insofar as outsiders level accusations against “the God of the OT.” In reference to Richard Dawkins, specifically, Provan asks, “Is he even reading the literature that he so freely criticizes, or is he simply picking up his opinions about it secondhand?”(71–72). While I cannot speak as to Dawkins’ reading or lack thereof, I would offer two other possibilities. First, perhaps those who misunderstand are reading selectively. It is not easy to read the entire Old Testament—a fact which probably gives me some job insurance—but reading texts in conversation with other texts, as a canonical whole, does help prevent taking particular texts out of context. Second, every reader reads with a particular lens.
These two possibilities—that those who misunderstand are reading selectively, and that we all read with a particular lens—point to my areas of concern about Provan’s work. First, I found that Provan’s focus on Genesis meant a neglect of other troublesome OT texts, including those in Deuteronomy, Joshua and Judges about ancient Israelite war, but also other texts where God seems overly angry such as Numbers 11 or 16. A few disclaimers are in order here: first, Provan explains why he focuses on the book of Genesis; because it is the canonical beginning of the story, and because it has been so misunderstood. Indeed, there has been a long-waged culture war between those who read Genesis scientifically, and those who read it more literally or confessionally, so it is clearly important to enter the skirmish. Second, Provan has already published in other areas of the Old Testament, including Ecclesiastes and Song of Songs, and one must limit one’s focus. Third, Provan does send feelers out to other biblical texts as he answers the questions about the nature of God, human beings, etc. And third, I found many of his particular observations about Genesis insightful and astute; I made marginal notes to share with my students his work with certain Hebrew words, for example, and his insights about Cain and Lamech. But in particular reference to the assertion that God is good—a confessional stance I would personally take—I wanted to read what Provan would say about the book of Joshua, or Psalm 88, or those other texts that call God’s goodness into question. Then again, I am—as Provan himself acknowledges!—not his ideal reader. This is not only because I am among those colleagues in the academic community (18–19), but also because I see in the biblical story less clear-cut answers, particularly when texts are read as a whole.
And while I also seek to read biblical texts in conversation with other texts, as a canonical whole, I also view the whole in a different way than Provan does. Though that is my second concern with this book, it may just be that he and I have different methodologies. Provan refers to “the” biblical story in the singular, as a metanarrative. I understand “the biblical metanarrative” to be a helpful framework to understand, for example, how the canon was organized, or how the children of Jacob become the twelve tribes of Israel. But a metanarrative is always reductionistic, and for that reason, I prefer to read the Bible as a canonical collection of varied and various books, in which different testimonies and counter-testimonies of God are placed in conversation with one another. I also read those conversations as genuine dialogues, in a Bakhtinian way, where there is more truth in the “both-and” than there is in a single or singular answer.
My third area of concern is that I did not find where Provan directly acknowledged that we all read with a particular lens. He hints at this on p. 22 when he writes, “We do not simply enter a world at birth: we are, in fact, progressively given a world in which to live. In this world, meaning and significance are already attached to things, and we are guided by other people in ‘making’ what we ‘make’ of them” (22). And, in reference to Islam, Provan explains that Allah’s mercy and compassion is the frame of reference within which everything else in Islam must be understood (73). Indeed, anyone who reads the Old Testament does not simply read it, but does so within the framework presented to them by teachers, communities of faith or lack thereof. Thus it was surprising to me to read this quote on p. 347: “I hope that in chapters 2–12 I have done a decent job of explaining biblical faith. If so, it should at least be clear how the Old Story told in the two Testaments of the Bible answers the enduring human questions we have been exploring. If that is the case, then I have at least rescued the Old Story from the violence that has threatened to silence it, and it has been allowed to speak for itself.” In particular, those last four words gave me pause, especially given that Provan acknowledged that he was “explaining it.” For the Old Story does not, in my experience, “speak for itself.” Even if that were possible, we still listen with particular filters.
This point—that we read with a particular lens, and listen with particular filters—came up for me recently as I was grading final reflection papers from my introductory Bible class this spring. A number of students, at the end of the quarter, ended the class as Marcionites, still convinced that God in the Old Testament was angry and cruel. Notwithstanding my own self-doubts about my teaching abilities, I have come to believe that one must start with a belief (or at least a willingness to believe) in the goodness of God in order to read that in the text. Once I have that lens, I will see evidence to support God’s goodness throughout the Old Testament books, but is it not something that simply happens “sola scriptura.”
I found Simply Dangerous Religion to be incredibly thought-provoking, and am grateful for the opportunity to reflect on it. Though the book may not have been convincing to me in the way Provan hoped it would be, again, it was not written primarily for me. I already could say that I prefer the Christian faith and its stories, and I find in them better resources to help me, as Pi said, love God.
9.21.15 |
Response
What the Old Testament “Really Says”
PROVAN’S TIMELY BOOK REPRESENTS a comprehensive attempt to clarify what the Old Testament (OT) “really says” and reestablish its enduring value in the light of various recent readings within competing worldviews in which its witness and role in shaping a vision of life is discredited. He does this primarily through a reading of Genesis in the context of the OT and its ancient Near Eastern context under ten themes relating to God, the world and life in the world lived out in relation to God and each other. Each theme forms a separate chapter (chapters 2–11). The themes are also discussed using other philosophies and religions as a foil, such as Western philosophy, Eastern philosophy and Islam. The distinctive voice of the OT is then brought out in dialogue with its recent critiques by, e.g., Richard Dawkins and Karen Armstrong. These main chapters are framed by an introductory chapter setting out Provan’s interpretative framework, and three subsequent chapters dealing with new dimensions arising from the New Testament (NT) (chapter 12); questions of truth (chapter 13) and consideration of whether the story is dangerous (chapter 14).
Provan’s interpretative framework involves inhabiting a story (3), where he considers what the OT “really says” on its “own terms” (11–13). He considers it to have often been misunderstood, partially by reading through the NT, even if the OT is to be reinterpreted through the NT after inhabiting the OT story itself (14). Provan grounds his book in Genesis, but branches out “to connect each theme with other Old Testament texts” (14), focusing on questions of what the text says in regard to informing how we should live (religious and philosophical questions), rather than on historical and scientific questions (15–17). He will conclude that the story is indeed true to the facts and makes better sense of them than competing stories, even if the story does not engage with questions of modern science for instance (chapter 13). He concludes that the story is dangerous for those who do not wish to think of every other human as their image-bearing neighbour (chapter 14), and reflects on the erosion of the biblical idea of humanity in the context of contemporary Western societies that move towards permissive attitudes to abortion and euthanasia (386), bringing the book into dialogue with contemporary issues.
Whilst there is much that I appreciate in Provan’s project, I would like to probe his assumptions. First, he assumes that one may identify “what the Old Testament really says.” For Provan there is an identifiable fact-of-the-matter both regarding the OT’s contents and what it advocates. He talks freely of “biblical faith” or “the biblical understanding,” suggesting a univocal conception is given. However, it is not clear that is the case for the literature at hand, or indeed appropriate for narrative literature read as story generally, which is what Provan claims to do.1 Any “serious” narrative, including biblical narrative, invites multiple construals, some of which may be poor and some good. Various good, faithful construals are generally available. So for instance the NT witnesses to several different construals of Abraham’s story (esp. Gen 15 and 22) in Romans 4; Hebrews 11:8–19; James 2:18–24. These differ again from traditional Jewish readings.2 Presumably on Provan’s account I must choose what the OT text really says? Either the NT witnesses to multiple faithful construals of Abraham’s story or multiple examples of poor interpretation. The latter option seems problematic. So the challenge is to show why construals of the OT by Dawkins et al. are poor, and what family resemblances we expect good construals to possess. Thus I am not convinced that the task of contemporary Christian interpretation of the OT is to recover what it “really says”—often associated with the modern philosophical tradition of identifying this with authorial intention (cf. 59)—but rather it is to develop ways of reading the OT well in the contemporary context so that it nurtures our mutual growth in the Christian life.
Perhaps the decisive difference between Provan and (e.g.) Dawkins is in the texts they take as being hermeneutical keys to the whole. In this I suspect that Provan’s choice is more informed by the Christian tradition than he grants, with readings such as his running more on the invisible tracks of tradition than on what the text “really says.” How does one construct a hermeneutic to account for the OT’s “multiple voices”? Is it possible to read the same narrative in different ways and draw different conclusions regarding, say, the issues of divine jealousy, wrath and judgement and remain “faithful” interpreters, both to the text and to the Christian faith? Given the breadth of vision of the OT one can choose to place different weights on different texts dealing with different themes, choosing which texts to select as the hermeneutical keys to the whole. This choice is part of the interpretative task. So a contemporary Christian apologist such as Provan might emphasize the significance of texts dealing with divine mercy, love, forbearance, etc. whilst a secular critic such as Dawkins might focus on texts dealing with violence, etc. The trouble is that both kinds of text run through the OT. The result, it seems to me, is often then that people “talk past” each other with different readers giving different priorities to different texts, or different forms of interpretation. The issue is that of why one prioritizes one set of texts (or form of interpretation such a symbolic or literal) over another. Provan’s treatment of the problem of texts advocating violence (in the context of God’s jealousy and vengeance) seems all too brief, with his main discussion spanning little over a page. He adopts the well-trodden (although I find unconvincing) apologetic account that justifies Israel’s Canaanite “conquest” in terms of divine justice and the sinfulness of Caananites (70–72). Perhaps one might (rather crudely) characterize the trajectory of this approach as Augustinian-Calvinist-Evangelical, but it is worth remembering that within the resources of the Christian tradition there is another approach, exemplified by Origen and Gregory of Nyssa, in which moral (and historical) difficulties in narratives are seen as hermeneutical cues to a figural or symbolic hermeneutic (to adopt contemporary categories), a hermeneutic flowing out of the revelation of the love of God in Christ. There is much more to be said here, given the gravity of the issues and their centrality to the OT’s critics.3
Provan moves freely between Genesis and the remainder of the OT in a way that he seems uncomfortable with as regards moving between the OT and NT. This appears problematic in the light of Walter Moberly’s thesis, The Old Testament of the Old Testament.4 Moberly probes the commonly observed difference between “patriarchal religion” (a construct based on the Genesis narrative) and “Mosaic Yahwism” (a construct based on the revelation of God to Moses and its outworking in the OT). He argues that the hermeneutical relationship between Genesis and the remainder of the OT has important analogies with the relationship between the OT and NT. Indeed, the question of the extent to which the patriarchs followed the Mosaic Law has troubled interpreters for centuries—witness the book of Jubilees. So the relationship of Genesis to the OT requires attention just as the relation of the OT to the NT needs to be addressed. So how does one assess the observation that the marriages of the patriarchs were incestuous according to Leviticus 18:9–18, and that Joseph is (perhaps) portrayed as practising divination (Gen 44:1–17)? What then is the significance of Genesis “on its own terms” as a resource for the Christian life? If one accords it significance on its own terms then, on a literal reading, it seems possible faithfully to worship God in an incestuous relationship, or whilst having several spouses. If one does not accord it significance on its own terms, then according to Moberly’s analogy, reading the OT on its own terms seems less illuminative than Provan implies, and we return to the question of interpretation as guided by the tradition of which the text is a (foundational) part.
My next concern relates to Provan’s appeal to the concept of accommodation as demonstrated in his discussions of subordination in certain relationships, especially female subordination and slavery (chapters 4 and 12). He suggests that Genesis 1–2 offers a vision of “right relationships” in contrast with descriptions of what actually follows (92). In chapter 4 he discusses attitudes to women in other religions and philosophies, but does not consider NT perspectives or those from the Christian tradition in any detail, in line with his stated overall interpretative approach. However, it seems curious that here he quotes Augustine as a foil, being a paradigmatic example of the church’s misinterpretation of Genesis 1–2 for Provan (90). Presumably though, Augustine’s reading was shaped by the NT, and is thus a candidate for what Provan repeatedly claims as the “biblical understanding.” In chapter 12 Provan discusses slavery and female subordination in terms of accommodation and conformity to cultural norms and social reality, especially via NT texts (339–40; cf. 1 Pet 3:1–2; Titus 2:9–10). He suggests that people “see the biblical accommodation, but mistake it for the biblical moral vision” (341). I think that appeal to accommodation is helpful here. But it seems problematic for Provan’s claim to the existence and normativity of the constructs of “biblical faith” or the “biblical understanding” and their relevance to the Christian life. In what sense can one trust the Bible as a guide for a moral or ethical vision, for a vision of faithful Christian living? How may one separate the real Christian moral vision from the shifting sands of cultural accommodation? This is a question of contemporary relevance. Is the vision of a monogamous heterosexual marriage part of the enduring Judeo-Christian moral vision, or is it one of accommodation to certain cultural norms? How might one decide? To take another issue of contemporary relevance, is the prohibition of charging interest on loans part of the enduring moral vision formed by the OT (Exod 22:25; Ps 15:5; Ezek 18:17), as the church supposed throughout much of her history, or of contextual accommodation that seems rather quaint?5
Provan pays careful attention to reading the OT in its ancient context so as to illuminate the text, reflecting a well-established hermeneutic of the modern era. Yet rather less is said in relation to the significance of the contemporary horizons of the reader for engagement with the text, the significance of which has been highlighted by recent sympathetic interpreters of the Bible such as Paul Ricoeur. Provan offers some helpful remarks on the significance of Darwinian evolution (which he takes to be compatible with biblical thinking), noting (helpfully) that design is not antithetical to process (356–58). However, given the pervasive influence of a scientific if not scientistic worldview on contemporary Western readers, I wonder if a much fuller engagement is not called for? How might one construe the nature of humanity according to the trajectory from Genesis 1–3, through Romans 5, to contemporary evolutionary biology if one wishes to take all these seriously, and accept that contemporary scientific worldviews significantly affect the expectations of contemporary readers, even at an existential level?
Finally, Provan suggests that implicit in the contemporary perception that the OT is problematic, no longer effective, and dangerous is the supposition that it is untrue. He considers the question of truth to be paramount. The OT story is in fact true (or truer) to the facts than competing stories (17, 348). My impression is that Provan is helpfully moving discussion away from debates surrounding biblical inerrancy and historicity toward the question of whether the OT story as a whole offers a true description of God, humanity and the world. I think that Provan adopts a concept of truth along the lines of Paul Ricoeur’s in his discussion of truth-claims of fictional narratives;6 roughly, that truth in fictional narrative is a “true-to-life” concept rather than a “correspondence with historical facts” concept. This is helpful, but I still wonder if “truth” is the best category to use. Philosophical analyses of the concept of truth indicate that it is a surprisingly slippery concept.7 Moreover, the Christian story encourages existential engagement perhaps more than intellectual assent to propositions (cf. Jas 2:14–26). Might it be preferable to frame discussion in terms of Scripture’s trustworthiness, in the context of a living tradition, as our fundamental witness to and resource for our flourishing in relationship with God? Is anything lost by reframing the discussion in this way?
I appreciated reading Provan’s book. It contributes toward the important goal of reestablishing trust in a theological “meta-narrative” stemming from the OT upon which flourishing communities can be built. Indeed, perhaps many of today’s problems stem for the loss of this narrative. However, I think Provan claims too much in claiming to identify what the OT “really says,” and does not acknowledge his debt to the living Christian tradition in responding to the critics. A greater pluralism of faithful readings of the OT sharing some family resemblance seems appropriate, with the tradition of the interpretation of the church (broadly speaking, and provisionally and fallibly) pointing toward faithful enacted interpretations that we may trust to be more fully life-giving than other narratives, as testified to in Christ.
See, e.g., Paul Ricoeur, Interpretation Theory: Discourse and the Surplus of Meaning (Fort Worth: Texas Christian University Press, 1976), esp. 79.↩
E.g., J. D. Levenson, The Death and Resurrection of the Beloved Son (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1993).↩
See Origen, On First Principles, Latin Text, IV.ii.9, in G. W. Butterworth, trans., Origen: On First Principles (Gloucester: Smith, 1973), 285–87. I deal with these issues in detail in The Joshua Delusion? Rethinking Genocide in the Bible (Eugene, OR: Cascade, 2010) in dialogue with Chris Wright. See also the essays in H. Thomas, J. Evans, and P. Copan, Holy War in the Bible: Christian Morality and an Old Testament Problem (Downer’s Grove: IVP Academic, 2013) in which these issues are wrestled with in depth from various Evangelical perspectives.↩
R. W. L Moberly, The Old Testament of the Old Testament (Minneapolis: Fortress, 1992).↩
See “Usury in the Hebrew Bible / Old Testament,” http:/C:/dev/home/163979.cloudwaysapps.com/esbfrbwtsm/public_html/syndicatenetwork.com4.yourfaithyourfinance.org/money-and-faith/usury-and-the-theology-of-money/usury-in-the-hebrew-bibleold-testament/.↩
P. Ricoeur, “The Narrative Function,” Semeia 13 (1978) 177–202.↩
See, e.g., B. Taylor, Models, Truth and Realism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006).↩
9.23.15 |
Response
Shopping the Marketplace of Ideas
IAIN PROVAN’S NEW BOOK usefully defies customary genre expectations. Is it an Old Testament theology? A work of apologetics? A study in comparative religion?
In fact it is all of these. The main emphasis throughout lies on describing the content of the Old Testament, as the book’s subtitle indicates (What the Old Testament Really Says and Why It Matters). As part of an introductory statement about the fundamental importance of “story” and “worldview,” Provan draws a contrast between the “Old Story” of the Christian tradition (i.e., the biblical story) and its contemporary competitors—stories of an “axial age,” a “dark green religion” and a “scientific new age.” Provan isn’t content, as others have been, merely to criticize the weaknesses of these competitors. Instead he intends to do the constructive heavy lifting needed in order to demonstrate how the worldview on offer in the Old Testament is preferable to its alternatives.
To this end Provan begins each of his following chapters by treating a particular aspect of the biblical witness. Chapters 2 through 6 explore what he calls “the five central questions of human existence” (163), each time beginning with the Genesis narrative and working out toward the rest of the canon from there. Each time Provan also engages in detailed comparison between the Old Testament’s “worldview” and the “worldviews” found in other major philosophies and world religions. This is how his book becomes just as much a work of comparative religion and apologetics as an Old Testament theology. I am unaware of any biblical theology that attends in such detail to other religious traditions. The scholarly ambition and range of this particular feature of Provan’s project is most impressive.
After treating basic questions about the world, Provan proceeds in chapters 7 through 9 to discuss the moral vision of the Old Testament. Chapters 10 and 11 treat politics and eschatology. Chapter 12 considers the relationship between the two testaments of the Christian Bible, and whether the New Testament confirms or corrects the Old. Here Provan strikingly insists on a high degree of continuity: “The New Testament does not tell a new story. It only takes an older story further—further up and further in” (346). In his two final chapters Provan returns to the conceptual framework with which he began. In chapter 13 he considers the truth of the Old Testament’s worldview in comparison with other modern claimants to truth. In chapter 14 he takes up the charge of “danger,” which has persistently been levied against the Old Testament in modernity, and stands it on its head. For those who wish to destroy the environment, erode respect for life and evade social responsibility, yes, the Old Testament is indeed “dangerous.” But understood correctly, the Old Testament is eminently reasonable. It is not only true, it is rational and accountable to evidence and logic (351–53).
Provan’s strong appeal to reason may thus threaten to confuse and undermine the force of his main title (Seriously Dangerous Religion). On the one hand, as suggested by the cover illustration of Samson overturning the pillars of the Gaza temple, Provan’s point seems to be that the message of the Old Testament is itself dangerous (although the illustration is also so dark that it is difficult to see clearly; the cover designers get bad marks for this). Indeed, Provan offers statements to that effect: “Biblical faith is dangerous . . . to those among the powerful who would like to be left alone to use and oppress the weak and those among the rich who would like to be left alone to use and oppress the poor” (385). But as this quotation also suggests, Provan’s polemic turns on an ironic use of the term in which the true danger of the Old Testament finally confronts only those who misunderstand, misuse or contradict it. Is the Old Testament in and of itself really dangerous or not? Can it be all that dangerous if in the end it is so very reasonable?
Nevertheless, the first thing to say in terms of evaluation should be an expression of gratitude. These days anyone who takes the Old Testament “seriously” enough to reflect on it theologically deserves thanks and admiration. This particular book is especially brave because it opens itself to all sorts of criticism from scholars of comparative religion and religious thinkers in other traditions. Who can truly achieve the academic competency necessary for this kind of work? And yet Provan has given it a valiant effort, which is far more than most of us could do and certainly more than I will ever be capable of. In fact I do not even feel fully competent to review the comparative aspect of Provan’s project. I hope that others will do so in detail. His interreligious claims should receive considered response.
I do want, however, to make two general comments about this aspect of the book. First, whether Provan is finally correct in all his details or not, his work urges an important caution with regard to the way in which other religious traditions are often romanticized in contemporary culture. Perhaps this phenomenon occurs in part due to a sense of cultural fatigue with Christianity and to the allure of novelty. Some of it may also be rooted in the foundational myth of religious studies, namely, that “religion” is a single thing occurring in various local manifestations, that all “religions” are ultimately the same. They are not all the same, Provan insists, and discernment is needed in order to draw appropriate distinctions among them. (See, e.g., his devastating treatment of the “Wikipedia belief” about the universality of the Golden Rule, 218.) Provan is surely right that in an increasingly multicultural world, all religious adherents will need to be more discerning about their own beliefs and the beliefs of others, even as they are also more charitable.
But—and this is the second point—I felt an increasing sense of unease about a possible absence of methodological parity within Provan’s comparative arguments. In describing the worldview of the Old Testament, Provan relies on his own scholarly engagement with the biblical text. Indeed, it is necessary for him to do so, he reports, because many “insiders” (i.e., Christians) have misunderstood their own story (13). He therefore writes theologically and normatively on his own authority, at times correcting the history of interpretation (e.g., the treatment of the “curses” in Genesis 3, 134; the christological reading of Gen 3:15, 286; the subordinate role of women, 320–21). Sometimes this correcting is explicitly acknowledged, but sometimes it is not. Provan’s discussion of God’s goodness thus skirts numerous difficult passages (e.g., Isa 45:7) in order to make the best possible case. While he concedes the reality of divine anger, jealousy and vengeance (62–72), he explains them quite tidily as entailments of God’s love.
The point again isn’t whether Provan is right in these claims, but whether he applies the same burden to the Christian tradition that he employs with regard to other religions. When he describes the teachings of Buddhism, Hinduism or Islam, he builds upon the comparative work of descriptive religious scholars rather than “theologians” or practitioners within those religions. Christianity, or a Christian understanding of the Old Testament, would take on a different character in a study produced by that kind of religious scholar. Of course, Provan means to be normative, to contemplate questions of truth, and I welcome that intention (although others may fault him for it). My worry is instead that if Provan is going to characterize Christianity normatively and sympathetically, then would it not be fairer and more charitable to cut other religions the same sort of slack? (See, e.g., how Provan acknowledges the possibility of a more sympathetic view of gender roles within modern Islam during his discussion of Sura 4:34, pp. 99–100, but then proceeds to discount that possibility in favor of how the text has been understood “historically”). Would it not be more charitable to engage the emic presentations of theologians in other religious traditions rather than to rely upon the etic academic textbooks featured in Provan’s footnotes? To be fair, I do realize that such internal, participant-oriented descriptions can be challenging to locate and use.
However, this worry leads to my next critical observation. For a book about the Bible and theology, this one has remarkably little explicit engagement with biblical scholarship and the Christian theological tradition. Again, to be fair, Provan announces in his introduction that he wants to write broadly for a nonspecialist audience. Yet there is no reason why he might not have engaged biblical and theological scholarship more fully even while maintaining such a goal. He does provide isolated references, for example, to Athanasius (approvingly, 281), Theophilus of Antioch (critically, 283), Aquinas (approvingly, 284), Irenaeus (critically, 286) and Augustine (approvingly, 90, 346). But the impression given is that these figures are finally only other “readers” of the biblical text from history. There is not really a sense of a Christian tradition of interpretation or, for that matter, any significant role for the church. Doctrinal statements are not employed as providing a “grammar” for theological discourse or rule of faith. There is little sense of a “people of God.” Rather, the stress falls on the way that individual readers of the Bible can “help build” society according to the biblical vision of a “kingdom of God” (337).
Yet this handling of the biblical material also sounds distinctly Reformed. The emphasis on reason, the view of salvation history as a series of increasingly narrower covenants (294), the advocacy of a social “common good” are all deeply Reformed reflexes, as is the fundamental category of “worldview,” a notion that has had a major impact on contemporary pedagogy in Reformed circles. Indeed, Provan’s treatment of the Old Testament reads very much like an outgrowth of this kind of educational theory—with the possible exception that Provan treats the Old Testament largely in cognitive terms, as a collection of beliefs that can be isolated, identified and compared with similarly isolated beliefs in other religious thought-systems. But even worldview-type Reformed thought has moved away from this old-fashioned reliance on the cognitive aspect of religion in order to appreciate more fully the precognitive, affective formation of individuals within religious cultures. (See, e.g., James K. A. Smith, Desiring the Kingdom: Worship, Worldview, and Cultural Formation [Grand Rapids: Baker Academic, 2009].)
By treating the Old Testament as a cognitively-framed worldview, Provan is certainly able to draw useful distinctions. But he also runs the risk of confirming that the Old Testament is just one more product on offer for individual consumption in the modern religious marketplace of ideas. By reading the Old Testament as a collection of worldview beliefs, Provan’s study may ultimately be a symptom of the same consumer-sickness that he is attempting to treat, as his easy and acknowledged reliance on Leon Kass’s The Beginning of Wisdom (Free Press, 2003) would appear to confirm. (Kass’s book is a fine study in its own right; what I mean to call attention to is the oddity that its secular perspective should dovetail so neatly with Provan’s avowedly Christian approach.)
Provan’s handling is also evangelical and socially conservative. Although he offers strong support for Christian egalitarianism (317–20), he argues for “design” in creation (356–57), against abortion and assisted suicide (386–87), and for a “nonnaked public square” (401–3). On these and other points, whether readers agree or disagree with Provan, it seems fair to say that the biblical witness is not quite as clear as Provan wants his readers to think. Or at least that Christians in fact disagree on such matters in good conscience and appeal to differing aspects of the biblical witness in making their case.
From the purview of Old Testament scholarship, it appeared to me that Provan sometimes made possibly anachronistic historical claims (e.g., his assertion that Israelite temples were aniconic, 82). His claim that in Genesis 1 God “simply speaks” creation into existence has been successfully contested. (See, e.g., Terence E. Fretheim, God and World in the Old Testament: A Relational Theology of Creation [Nashville: Abingdon, 2005], 37–38.) I was also disappointed to see Provan characterize all sacrifice in the Old Testament as operating on “the principle of substitution” (66), without acknowledging any debate, given the large body of work now contradicting this position. However, I found Provan’s discussion of biblical ethics as “subversive accommodation” (339–42) to be intriguing and helpful. I would be happy to read a follow-up account from him in which he went into greater detail about this way of understanding politics and the Bible.
I hope that I have been able to pose a few incisive questions in response to Provan’s impressive work. Nothing here is intended to diminish the significance of his accomplishment. Seriously Dangerous Religion is a major synthetic statement of unparalleled scope, deserving a wide readership. It illuminates and challenges, even as it confirms that rumors of the Old Testament’s demise are greatly exaggerated.
9.25.15 |
Response
Belonging to a Reflective Tradition
UP UNTIL LAST YEAR Iain Provan was primarily known for his “maximalist” approach to Old Testament historicity in A Biblical History of Israel, as well as a few commentaries on individual OT books. In this new volume we have a different kind of book altogether. It is nothing short of a “cracking good read”: academically rigorous, accessible, and devotionally edifying—three virtues rarely found together.
Not many books today successfully bridge the gap between academy and church, and those that do are almost never rooted in the Old Testament. Apart from the inherent difficulties in making academic research accessible, the discipline of OT scholarship has further struggles to overcome. Anyone wishing to demonstrate the contemporary relevance of the OT must first acquire an opinion about its overall theological message, and the current structure of the discipline is implicitly hostile to such an enterprise. Instead, it encourages (1) fragmented expertise limited to tiny portions of the biblical text, and (2) research that is restricted to historical description alone, purged of any theological implications. To raise one’s head above the parapet and say something about the “theology of the OT” in general, is to invite criticism from everyone defending their own territorial area of research. It is easy to tear down someone else’s generalisation by insisting that they have failed to take your own biblical passage seriously, and preferable to say nothing yourself that steps outside the boundaries of that biblical passage for fear of receiving the same treatment. The result is an increasing mass of disconnected historical research, and a dearth of “big picture” attempts to cohere that research into something theologically robust and relevant.
In the face of these obstacles, Provan has written a daring retrieval of the OT’s answers to the questions that form a worldview: What is the world? Who are human beings? Who is God? What is wrong with the world? What is my role in putting it right? Provan is not afraid of generalising the OT’s answers to these questions—nor should he be. It is the task of philosophy to generalise, and the human mind must do so in order to form a foundational worldview. That being said, in what follows, I offer a (hopefully gentle) critique of Provan’s hermeneutic as being overly modernist and not aware of the limits of its own historical location.
Modernist Methodology and the Limits of Reflection
Although Provan’s book avoids many of the mistakes made by the biblical theology movement, he has not escaped one of the most inscrutable of them—the temptation to epistemological autonomy.
In the heyday of biblical theology (ca. 1940s–1960s), there was much enthusiasm about throwing off the shackles of ecclesially-imposed dogma and instead reading the Bible afresh on its own terms. Like the subtitle of Seriously Dangerous Religion, their slogan could easily have been “What the Bible really says” where the substance of that “really” was a stripping away of doctrinal constraints and their replacement by rigorous historical-critical investigation.
But within only a couple of decades the elusiveness of such a project became apparent. An anarchic multitude of conflicting theologies arose, which disagreed profoundly with one another over their most basic assertions. Eventually scholars such as James Barr and Brevard Childs exposed the problematic assumptions behind the entire project, and by the 1970s it had been laid to rest.
Looking back, we can see the extent to which every biblical theologian’s work in that period was shaped by their historical location, how much their interpretation was inescapably filtered through the lens of a pre-reflective cultural outlook. What emerged clearly from the movement’s demise was that there will always be multiple tenable readings of the Bible, each one academically defensible yet none victorious over the others. Whether consciously or unconsciously, we all bring our presuppositional framework to the text, and the line between exegesis and eisegesis is harder to draw than it might at first appear. The mistake made by the biblical theologians was to adopt a methodology that Bernard Lonergan labels the “principle of the empty head.” This principle, says Lonergan,
bids the interpreter forget his own views, look at what is out there, let the author interpret himself. In fact, what is out there? There is just a series of signs. Anything over and above a re-issue of the same signs in the same order will be mediated by the experience, intelligence, and judgment of the interpreter.1
And of course, the interpreter’s experience, intelligence and judgment are shaped profoundly by his or her own place in history. Such embeddedness within history should not be seen as a deficiency or problem—otherwise we are wishing for the Platonic detachment from the world that Provan is so keen to combat. Rather, awareness of our created nature leads to a refreshing humility about the limits of our human perspective.
What worries me about Provan’s book is that there are times when he seems to slide unwittingly into the error of assuming a superior, transcendental perspective, detached from any reading tradition or place in history. For example, in several places he talks about the OT (like the biblical theologians do) as if all we need to do is read it “on its own terms.” He writes, “Later interpreters of the Old Testament may have understood [x], however, the Old Testament itself does not lead us to read [y] in such a way” (135). Or, “[A certain] conclusion . . . appears to me to be obviously correct. Many other readers . . . however, have not come to such a conclusion” (90). Even more disturbingly, he talks of reading the OT through the lens of the NT as if it were an “unfortunate tendency” and then speaks as if nothing were easier than reading the OT “for its own sake” (13).
If Provan is saying here merely that we must avoid jumping too quickly to the New Testament in order to dismissively explain the Old—that the Old and the New must instead mutually interpret one another, rather than the New simply trumping the Old—then it is hard for any Christian to disagree with him. But if he means that we can have access to “what the OT says in itself” and that the NT would be a hindrance to discovering this, then he is assuming a critical distance from any reading tradition including the Christian one. The problem, as Robert Jenson observes, is that “when reading Old Testament texts christologically or ecclesially is contrasted with another reading which is said to take them ‘in themselves,’ or in their ‘original’ sense, the churchly reading inevitably appears as an imposition on the texts.”2
If we believe the New Testament when it says that Christ is the true meaning of the Old Testament, then that is what the Old Testament “in itself” has always meant, and to see Christ in its pages is not an imposition of meaning. To be a Christian is to read the OT through the lens of the NT. Not to be a Christian is to read the OT through another equally mediated lens—an Enlightenment, or Jewish, or historical-critical tradition—which is no more neutral than the Christian one. The supposition that we have unmediated access to the text is a temptation to be avoided, especially if it includes the assumption that others have blurred vision due to their traditions, while we alone see clearly. As Paul Ricoeur neatly summarises:
Modern exegetes are like us. They work and think at the end of a history. In this sense, the one thing that would be criticisable would be the naïve claim of an exegesis that held itself to be without a history, as though it were possible to coincide, without the mediation of a tradition of reading, with the original signification of a text, even with the presumed intention of its author.3
We “work and think at the end of a history” not only when interpreting texts, but when interpreting reality more generally. As Heidegger has taught us, our grasp of reality has the complication that we are always inside it and a part of it, never removed to a critical “objective” distance. Unfortunately, Provan attempts the same critical detachment from history in chapter 13, in which he presents an apology for the worldview he finds in the Old Testament. The goal of that chapter is to assess whether the philosophy gleaned from the OT is “truer to the facts, and [makes] better sense of them than competing stories” (348). How are we to determine this? The answer is, apparently, through the light of natural reason and evidence (353).
First, Provan criticises the attitude of the “practical man” (quoting Keynes) who, by being unreflective, is captive to certain philosophical ideas from the past without realising it (349). He then goes on, by means of rational reflection and evidence, to correlate the Old Testament’s claims with those of modern science (354), with basic observations about human nature (368), and with “historical reality” (371).
Several questions present themselves here. First, if simple observation and reflection should lead us to see the biblical account as most plausible, then why have so few people in history ever naturally coincided with the biblical worldview? Why are there so many alternative philosophies and religions and how did people come up with them? What is wrong with them that is not wrong with Iain Provan? How is he able to see so much more clearly than everyone else that the facts of science, history and reason point in the direction of the Bible? Is he just more reflective and rational than anyone else? Or are his powers of reason and observation as much under the influence of preceding philosophies (in this case, the Old Testament itself) as everyone else?
It is noteworthy that in chapter 13 there is a shift in Provan’s tone from the preceding chapters. Where previously the Old Testament text was foregrounded through Provan’s training and expertise in its interpretation, in this chapter we find instead a plethora of subjective admissions: “it seems to me” (355, 368), “I believe that it is” (353, 359), “I am convinced” (356), “I think” (357), “I suggest” (358, 377), “I myself find [x] congruent/persuasive” (366, 371). Suddenly Provan’s own perspective is in the foreground. What has happened here?
Probably this is an implicit admission that what seems plausible to him may not, even after much reflection, seem plausible to others. But if true, this carries more significance than Provan gives to it. It means that, as Paul Ricoeur put it, “reflection always comes too late”:
The idea that one can somewhat neutrally reflect on theology and detachedly consider experience, tradition, and the Scripture is challenged by the emphasis that humans emerge in tradition and experience that is already shaped in deep and pervasive ways that can hardly ever be brought to conscious reflection.4
The creeping danger here is that of intellectualism: to imagine that if we simply think hard and clearly enough then we will arrive at the truth. In fact even the most intelligent, rational and reflective being among us is still under the influence of philosophies and ideologies from the past, and the sooner we admit that, the sooner the intellect and reflection will find their rightful place in theology.
Provan’s excellent book would have been even more excellent if he had built into it an explicit awareness of its belonging to a philosophical/religious tradition and speaking on its behalf, rather than an ostensibly autonomous analysis of the veracity of the Old Testament. If he had done so, the book may have contained less of the half-hearted apologetics of chapter 13, and more striking insights like the one in chapter 14 that human rights are far from “self-evident,” and “the ‘Western’ view of human rights is intrinsically connected with the [Biblical] Story that has historically shaped Western culture” (385–86). This insight goes against the grain of chapter 13, in which reality, properly understood, does “self-evidently” support the biblical worldview.
In 2010 I took my first class with Iain Provan. It totally transformed my relationship to the Old Testament, opening my eyes to its philosophical power and relevance. I am delighted that I now have on my bookshelf a volume encapsulating much of that experience, and I will not hesitate to recommend it enthusiastically to anyone seeking a robust, coherent, and devotionally rich understanding of the Older part of the Old Story to which we all belong.
Lonergan, Method in Theology (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1972), 157.↩
Jenson, On the Inspiration of Scripture (ALPB, 2012), 30.↩
André LaCocque and Paul Ricoeur, Thinking Biblically: Exegetical and Hermeneutical Studies (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998), 332.↩
Dan Stiver, Ricoeur and Theology, Philosophy and Theology (London: T. & T. Clark, 2012), 55.↩
Ephraim Radner
Response
Not Dangerous Enough
IAIN PROVAN HAS GIVEN us a tremendously exciting venture in Scriptural apologetics. As he explains his purpose in his introduction, Provan wants to present the biblical story in a way that can confute various alternative modern “stories,” ones that often misrepresent and misread the Scriptures. The “old story,” as he describes the Bible, has a compelling integrity in the face of the perennial questions of life that modern stories, despite their pretensions, fail to address adequately.
As Scriptural apologetics, the book is wonderful and unique. I can’t think of anything else quite like it, and with such broad and detailed scope. Christian apologetics pursues a winsome presentation of the truth, in the face of specific questions posed to the gospel. In this case, Provan addresses a range of central contemporary questions, through the lens of the biblical story: What is the world? Who is God? Who are man and woman? And several other key questions involving ethics and politics. In each case, he compares the Scriptural outlook on the matter with alternative stories—the pertinent claims of so-called “axial” religions, like Islam and Buddhism, or of contemporary versions of primitivist naturalism (“dark green religion”), or finally of scientific positivism.
There is always a theological risk inherent in apologetics: winsomeness gives in to the gravitational pull of the culture and its questions. The challenges posed, for example, by a culture of egalitarian justice might drive a Christian apologist to downplay the culturally difficult realities of embedded social or magisterial asymmetry bound up with Christian existence. Thus, a specifically Scriptural apologetics such as Provan provides should guard against this tendency. He engages the Scriptures deeply and concretely, focusing most fully on Genesis, before reaching out from its foundational chapters for confirmation in other Old Testament texts. At the end of the book, Provan establishes continuities of vision between these Old Testament contours to the biblical story and the New Testament (“Further Up and Further In”). The biblical story is robustly established as the vantage point here, to the point that some readers might worry about a loss of apologetic persuasiveness. After all, when Scripture becomes the only rhetorical instrument used in responding to cultural questions and to intellectual assault upon the gospel, the response itself often devolves into proof-texting. Provan’s carefully structured model, that progresses from thematic question to in-depth Scriptural discussion to narrative comparison, rightly attempts to avoid such a pitfall.
The result here is impressive, even as the method is laudable. Despite the critique that follows, I need to emphasize that I would happily put this book into the hands of an intelligent inquirer or Christian teacher and learner. I am not, however, sure how far the method succeeds, which is more a reflection on the project of Scriptural apologetics itself than on Provan’s skills. I will take one example only—though it is central to his argument—in order to follow this intuition out. In this particular case, my sense is that even a large bundle of Scripture such as he deploys cannot resist the cultural tide undermining its power, when that Scripture is made to function apologetically as an “answer” to a question, or as a “story” told to an inquirer, or as an argument made to a skeptical critic. The example I will use is Provan’s posing and answering of the question “Why do evil and suffering mark the world?”—a question that bleeds into the next one on his list: “What am I to do about evil and suffering?”
Provan wants us to read Genesis 2–3 as a story about suffering and evil, but not exactly as a thorough explanation of their reality. I think this is fair. Genesis doesn’t give us a theodicy in any systematic way. He works his way through the biblical text, with its serpent, temptation, choices, consequences, divine curse, and exclusion from the Garden. In all of this, Provan argues that we must place the story within a larger narrative of God’s goodness and creation’s instrumental context as a movement towards the fulfillment of God’s beneficent purpose. Whatever we may think of suffering and evil, they find their way towards divine resolution. This positive contextual construal is very important for Provan, because it allows him to propose certain concepts for evaluating evil through its proper categorization: some evil or suffering is, he says, “intrinsic” to creation; and some is “extrinsic” to its form. Intrinsic suffering is suffering that comes with the territory of being alive and living in the world the good God has created. “Sunk costs,” as it were. Such suffering is to be accepted and discounted. Without the fall and the divine curse, that is, childbirth would still have been “painful,” and farming would still have “hurt.” There is a good deal of pain and hurt that are simply a part of being alive; but since being alive is “good,” this kind of intrinsic suffering is not fundamentally problematic.
By contrast, “extrinsic” suffering, as Provan defines it, is that evil which derives from our own actions and wills. We impose it upon our created existences. Extrinsic evil is something we choose or that we are embroiled in because of the choices of others like us. So, for instance, the pains of childbirth referred to specifically in the curse of Genesis 3:16 go beyond the simple travails of delivery that are bound up with being alive; now they envelop family systems (Provan makes deft use of some word studies here). Farming, under the curse, will now no longer simply require hard work, but will be met with resistance from the earth, and will sometimes be accompanied by the environmentally horrendous consequences of human disorder.
When it comes to living in such a fallen world, Provan answers in terms of human character and of responsible and faithful behavior. Provan returns to the intrinsic/extrinsic suffering dichotomy for help here: the world as creation is not in fact “blighted” (Provan uses the term from Thomas Hardy only to reject it), because it is in fact still “good.” A lot of suffering is just what we must get through because we are alive. If the world is “fallen,” that is only to the extent that we experience the consequences of human choices—extrinsic evil. Hence, the proper human response to evil and suffering is continued, if often difficult, labor within the context of original goodness, as given in Genesis 1 and 2: the male-female order of family and community, and then the chosen practices of devotion to God within a context of sometimes existential resistance. In addition, our responses to extrinsic or moral evil must involve ways of making things better, within the limits of our capacities and contexts. In both cases, we need to engage practices like endurance, prayer, compassion and hope. Ultimately, Provan adheres to an “Irenaean” vision of divine pedagogy, as he tells us in an endnote (452n56): God is “in the business of ‘soul-making.’ Suffering, much of which (Irenaeus agrees) is indeed intrinsic to the way in which the good world works, is also necessary in pursuit of that goal, both in the present world and in the next. It teaches us knowledge and compassion, and it builds our character as we make good choices in the face of it.”
Provan admits that this isn’t how many in the Christian tradition have read Genesis. As in Athanasius’ perspective, the tradition has tended to view the fall in the Garden as the site of a spiraling descent into death and nothingness, which only the incarnation’s critical intrusion could reverse, like a knife thrust into a wicked heart. The Garden on the day of the fall was a place where horrendous events occurred through our first parents, rending from top to bottom the fabric of the world. For Provan, by contrast, evil is a decidedly human phenomenon. The natural world remains reassuringly normal, if sometimes unruly, but for our misdeeds. He is certainly right that the opening chapters of Genesis do not delineate, and to that degree do not concern themselves with the full scope of sin and evil that later Jews and Christians especially came to attribute to the narrative’s significance. But his reading is nonetheless inadequate, I think, to the fuller scope of Scripture’s own repeated struggle with the world that Genesis only briefly limns. Genesis may well found the rest of the Bible’s revelation of God and creation; but it is also only a prelude to a long and often agonized Scriptural description of that reality. This is why, in part, Genesis was rightly read figurally and allegorically within Jewish and Christian tradition: its words were saturated with deeper meanings in a self-evident fashion, just because the world is the way it is, and Scripture says what it does in all of its diverse ways.
Thus, Provan’s talk about “natural” evil disarmingly picks up on contemporary scientific claims—plate tectonics and the rest—that are both familiar to our own cultural store of knowledge, but that are also themselves untethered to the Scriptures. The latter have no interest in how continents shift upon the crust of the earth, or of seismic faults and unstable planetary liquids. Provan assures us that the earth’s “molten interior is essential to life on the planet, because it is responsible for the shield around the earth that protects it from radiation (which is itself a product of nuclear fusion, which is necessary to life)” (370). The Bible instead, when it comes to earthquakes and volcanoes, famine and disease, speaks of God who “looketh on the earth, and it trembleth” and who “toucheth the hills, and they smoke” (Ps 104:32); or who “makes peace and creates evil” (“weal and woe” in the RSV’s nice alliteration; Isa 45:7). Provan chooses to engage the challenge of natural or intrinsic suffering, with respect to God, by adopting a Leibnizean response—when it comes to the shape of natural existence, we live in “the best of all possible worlds.” This may be theologically compelling at the end of a powerful argument that grapples with the nature of being itself, in the manner of a Job-like logic. But here it savors more of the domesticated uncertainties of our era’s exhaustion with divine metaphysics.
Our culture doesn’t know how to talk about suffering or about evil in religious terms. The political philosopher Judith Shklar dated one of the “modern age[’s] many birthdays” to the Lisbon earthquake of 1755, which, on a brilliant Sunday morning during mass, destroyed the city and tens of thousands of its inhabitants. “It was the last time,” she writes, “that the ways of God to man were the subject of general public debate and discussed by the finest minds of the day. It was the last significant outcry against divine injustice, which soon after became intellectually irrelevant. . . . From that day onward, the responsibility for our suffering rested entirely with us and on an uncaring natural environment, where it has remained” (Faces of Injustice [Yale, 1990], 51). While I hardly believe that Provan would embrace this modern shift, I worry that he has become too attuned to its settled inevitability as an apologetic given. The dichotomy between extrinsic and intrinsic evil is not only too easy, it is arguably unbiblical, and finally impossibly applied in any case. And once applied, much is obscured.
The Christian tradition, after all, rarely made the distinction itself, but struggled with whether it could be made at all. Is creation itself horribly out of whack? To what degree are the orbits of the planets, or the molten mantle of the earth’s undercurrents themselves the product of sin? How does one see the ordering of providence, given the various alternatives? These were all live questions for centuries. Indeed, it was only with the “modern birthday” of the eighteenth century that suffering itself was no longer cast in terms of objective evil, through and through. In one famous Leibnizian reflection on the Lisbon earthquake, Louis de Beausobre wondered why it was any worse to have thousands of people die all at once, as opposed to separately over the course of their still-limited lifespans. Suffering, after all, is simply what it is for each of us, whether in a heap or one at a time; it has no intrinsic moral weight. The same question still engages philosophers. But these are specifically modern attitudes, that have little historical or theological rootedness behind them.
Hence, I was indeed startled to see Provan dismiss the suffering of childbirth as itself “cursed.” After all, childbirth has been positively deadly, and not simply “painful,” for mother and child for all of human history until recently. Is such deadliness “intrinsic” or “extrinsic”? Just “the way of the world,” or bound to the radically evil reality of our situation? I am not suggesting that the answer is obvious; just the opposite. Job’s family losses hardly makes a mention here; the intensely lurid rites of purification after childbirth; the laws in Deuteronomy over still-births and dead mothers; the infant death of David and Bathsheba’s son, and its strange moral context—none of this seems to have any traction in Provan’s discussion. Something is missing here, whose loss the supposedly clean line between intrinsic and extrinsic suffering cannot contain.
By contrast, Provan moves his discussion of suffering into the New Testament in a striking way. In the face of evil and suffering, he underlines a human-centered response as the important aspect of the “story”—we are to live with faith, hope, endurance, compassion and prayer. Jesus, to be fair, is not simply a moral example in this, but is God himself, something that Provan stresses over and over. In Jesus, God becomes a servant, and in the New Testament that servanthood is displayed as utterly trustworthy. But the gift given in the fact of Jesus, Provan argues, is a newly powerful way for human beings to live through suffering and evil, a way that is similar to Jesus. And to this extent, the exemplarist payoff is finally the central one: in a world of suffering, what is important is how we navigate it faithfully, neither with a sense of fatalism nor of arrogant mastery. Hugely telling here is the almost complete absence of the cross.
But how can one offer a Scriptural apologetic without the cross? The question raged in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries during the so-called Chinese Rites Controversy (early Jesuit missionaries in upper-class contexts deliberately avoided discussions of the Passion until after baptism, so repellent were they to educated Chinese sensibilities). Provan’s Genesis-platform and generally literal hermeneutic perhaps makes it difficult for him to identify the cross centrally within the Old Testament. This is worth another discussion. But even without touching on issues of Scriptural reference and canon we can see what happens when this hermeneutic is made to carry a significant doctrine of God. His approach is to move out from Genesis, and only from that direction, never backwards into Genesis. Not that one should appeal to the cross as a solution to the challenge of suffering and evil. But the cross was never presented as such in Scripture in any case. Rather, the cross stands in the New Testament as a strange opening to something that is always there in Law, Prophet, and Psalm, but that we cannot grasp morally outside of its revelation. Moving from New Testament to Old Testament, we discover the forms of that which disturbs us at all times: Judas, driven by an interior devil, can now figurally name the divine spirit who leads Ahab to his death with deceptive counsel . . . God hovering over all. A Leibnizian theodicy, Scripturally embraced, should drive us into directions that are inherently unsettling: if this is God’s “best” world, his most loving world, love itself, then God is much more mysterious than we had realized. Of course, the Old Testament itself works towards a new realization of God as much as does the New.
Provan’s story is one of American Christian realism: evil is real, and the human vocation is self-limiting and sober; yet evil is also a thing to be confidently wrestled with, so that our sober vocation is also a tremendously activist one as well. On this score, his treatment of the New Testament mirrors precisely his vision of the Old: the world is good but tough, people are often bad, and we are called to humbly persevere in resisting what is wrong, with God as our help and hope. It is a good Reformed approach, in all its modest Puritan ethos. But a huge part of Provan’s realist apology is to present a biblical case for an optimism about God. So that, what goes missing from the Puritan ethos are the strange apprehensions regarding realities like election, depravity, and the awful counsels of God. Who shall explain the suffering of the world except the crucified creator, whose giving of the world to itself is too wrenching a beauty for words? I much prefer Provan’s writing over Jüngel’s; but God as the Mystery of the World is by far the better title.
Precisely because “divine mystery” implies neither optimism nor pessimism, divine mystery is not an obvious apologetic claim. And on the other side, the quite apologetically winsome claim that the Bible is a “better story” than other contemporary stories is not quite Scriptural. It is true, as Provan compares the Bible’s discussions of good and evil, creation and human personhood, creatures and compassion—it is true that, compared to the conceptual orders of other major religions and of today’s primitive naturalism and scientism, the Bible comes off as richer and more compelling. But the Bible is not a story. It is filled with stories, to be sure. As a category, however, the Bible is a Word, in the person of God, which comes in many rhetorical forms. Taken as a whole, it is the divinely communicated “this is the case” of reality. Something is the case in the world, the Scriptures disclose, and it is the case so deeply as to defy our ability to offer alternatives. Impossibilities are rarely winsome. When we encounter them, we accept them only through a kind of conversion.
I am wondering, then, if Scriptural apologetics can ever really work. If it is Scriptural, it will upturn us; if it is apologetic, it will feed our dulled desires. The two aspects lie in an almost violent embrace. For what is the case is only one thing: God as we encounter God in this world that is entirely God’s. Yet the fact that this is the case, means that what is the case is so powerful as to rend our rebellions themselves. We cannot reason ourselves into the truth; we can only be shaped, made, broken, and remade by it. Gentle persuasion? Or rather what is frightening and astonishing.
I am deliberately exaggerating here, but just a little. Provan turns to his own title at the end of his volume, and explains that “biblical faith is dangerous only in the sense of promoting the good” (380). I am certainly persuaded by the “good” that Provan outlines in the course of the book. But that is because I can grasp this good through something that unseats all my goodness itself; and because he creates goodness itself; and because he creates that which is and in the face of whom all that is is shown to be nothing but what his grace has given it to be. I am persuaded of the good because I am “dominated” by it—dominus, Lord, from which comes the English word “danger.”
As I said, Provan has written a wonderful book. But in the end, Seriously Dangerous Religion is still not dangerous enough.
9.13.15 | Iain Provan
Reply
Not Dangerous Enough? A Response to Ephraim Radner
I am honoured that these five colleagues should have taken time to engage with my new book Seriously Dangerous Religion with such seriousness and attentiveness, and I am glad for the opportunity to enter into a discussion with them about its contents. I am also delighted with the tone of the conversation so far, and I hope that we can maintain this throughout our engagement with each other, even though we shall be writing to each other rather than speaking face to face, which always creates certain problems. I apologize in advance for any infelicities of speech that may cause irritation or offence—I hope that all participants may be assured that it is not my intention to cause such, but only to respond just as seriously to their reviews as they have sought to respond to my book in the first place.
I was unsure how to order my responses, so I decided that I would simply take the essays in reverse order, alphabetically—and therefore, Radner, Koenig, Earl, Chapman, and Asprey.
Not Dangerous Enough? A Response to Ephraim Radner
First of all, I am grateful for Ephraim’s enthusiasm for the book! I have been living with this ambitious project for a number of years, and it is close to my heart. I have been, therefore, more than usually nervous about the kind of reception it was going to receive from academic colleagues, given the various prevailing moods in biblical studies. As Ephraim deduces, the strategy I adopted in writing it was carefully chosen, after much thought. I was aiming at reasonably “cool” communication for the most part—a descriptive rather than an overtly argumentative style, as a result of which I hoped at least to clarify what our biblical story has to say about important human questions, for those who may not have engaged much with that story for themselves. Only in the closing chapters does the book become more overtly argumentative, by which time I hope that I have bought “credit” with the reader that allows this argument to be heard. The “intelligent inquirer or Christian teacher and learner” represent precisely my intended audience, so I am delighted that Ephraim would put the book into such people’s hands.
As to the substance of his critique, I take it to center on a concern, generally, that “the project of scriptural apologetics” is problematic, because it must always dull the edge of Scripture in seeking to make reasonable connections between the world as we find ourselves embroiled in it, on the one hand, and God’s address to the world, on the other. And then, specifically, he thinks that as a matter of fact I have myself allowed this “dulling” to occur, at least in my “Irenaean” treatment of evil and suffering: “Even a large bundle of Scripture such as [Provan] deploys [here] cannot resist the cultural tide undermining its power, when that Scripture is made to function apologetically as an ‘answer’ to a question, or as a ‘story’ told to an inquirer, or as an argument made to a skeptical critic.” My reading of these themes he finds “inadequate . . . to the fuller scope of Scripture’s own repeated struggle with the world that Genesis only briefly limns,” and the distinction that lies at the heart of my argument (between extrinsic and intrinsic evil) is “not only too easy, it is arguably unbiblical, and finally impossibly applied in any case.” The consequence is that “in the end, Seriously Dangerous Religion is still not dangerous enough.” Interestingly, Peter Leithart said almost exactly the same thing about the book in First Things: “At many points Provan tilts his explanation of X ever-so-slightly toward the prevailing outlook of contemporary culture,” such that the distinctive voice of Scripture on those points is not fully heard.
As to whether the general project is essentially problematic—perhaps it is! And yet Christians all through the ages have engaged in it, evidently firmly believing that scriptural truth ought to cohere with other kinds of truth and that there is merit in trying to show that this is in fact the case. “We cannot reason ourselves into the truth”—of course, that is true. Yet the truth that Scripture proclaims is truth about the real world in which we live, and we are surely obliged to try to work out what this means, not least when it comes to what we modern people call “scientific truth.” Origen and Augustine certainly thought so; so did Calvin. Is there a danger that in entering into this apologetic space we shall compromise the truth of Scripture, and end up by allowing culture to domesticate God’s Word? Yes, the history of biblical interpretation is littered with examples of this. But isn’t there at the same time a danger in not entering into such an apologetic space? Isn’t there a danger that even Christians might then find it difficult to connect God’s Word deeply with the world that he has also created—and people outside the church even more so? Isn’t it valuable at least to try to remove some intellectual obstacles that might prevent people from seriously considering the Christian faith? Isn’t it even valuable, in bringing extra-biblical truth into conversation with biblical truth, thereby to prompt Christians to consider whether their current understanding of Scripture is truly the best understanding available?
As to whether I myself, in this particular project, have caused the power of Scripture to be undermined—well, I hope not. I would be distressed if I came to believe that this were so, since my very purpose has been to allow Scripture itself to speak out clearly on some very important matters—something that I believe it can and should do (as will become clearer in the course of my responses to other participants in this symposium). But here everything depends, of course, on what we believe that Scripture does in fact teach. Somewhat like Goldilocks with her three bowls of porridge, it has not been my intention to write a book that is either more or less dangerous than it ought to be, but only a book that is exactly dangerous enough. I fully acknowledge that my reading of Genesis (and indeed the OT as a whole) varies in some degree from how other Christians have read Scripture (although for the most part, I must say, it seems to me that I have friends in the reading tradition on the various particular points). Yet I am conscious-bound to propose, nevertheless, what I believe the best way of reading to be. And I stand by what I have said in the book when it comes to evil and suffering in particular, especially on the point about how much of what we call by these names is, in fact, best thought of as intrinsic to the goodness of the world that God has made. Much hangs on how we parse out “creation” and “fall,” and their relationship to each other, as Ephraim notes; I’m just not convinced that some of the parsing, historically, has been sufficiently attentive to Scripture. Is Genesis 3:16 really intended to tell us about childbirth, for example? I profoundly doubt it; and I doubt it, in the end, not because of cultural pressure upon me to believe otherwise, but because of the likely meaning of the Hebrew words on the page. Does this make my book insufficiently dangerous on this point? Well, if I’m right, it surely makes it just as dangerous as it wants to be—no more and no less.
Have I said everything, in this book, that might be said about a Christian view of evil and suffering? Undoubtedly I have not, and Ephraim is right to point this out; it is already a very long book. But I hope that I have said enough to help people to begin to think biblically about such matters, and then to build further on a solid foundation as they go on to expand upon what I have said and make further connections with other things. I look forward to further conversation about whether this is actually true!