Hegel’s Social Ethics
By
7.1.19 |
Symposium Introduction
Molly Farneth’s Hegel’s Social Ethics: Religion, Conflict, and Rituals of Reconciliation doesn’t try to make Hegel into a grassroots democrat. But, that doesn’t mean Hegel isn’t important for our current political times. Indeed, Farneth wonderfully balances clarity and concision when offering Hegelian epistemological and ethical insights in our shared political culture. In the conversations that follow, our panelists will probe into and challenge Farneth’s Hegelian offering for grassroots democrats. We’ll explore questions of power and authority, ritual and practice, Marx’s revolutionary praxis and Hegel’s own critique of private property, and—perhaps surprisingly—what Farneth’s Hegelian social ethics has to say to the bad faith troll.
Farneth’s lucid reading of Hegel is enough to merit attention. Many ethicists, anthropologist, sociologists, and philosophers have recently turned to the topic of “social practices.” Religious historians often approach this topic via lived religion, for example. Some philosophers and religious ethicists, however, are turning to a non-metaphysical, post-Kantian reading of Hegel’s Phenomenology. This Hegel is paradigmatically found in the pragmatic semantics Robert Brandom has been developing over the last three decades culminating in his recently released A Spirit of Trust. Farneth ably navigates this difficult secondary literature on Hegel in chapters 2–5, offering her own social ethical account where Hegel is primarily concerned with evaluation of relationships, practices, and institutions. Readers interested in getting a clear and insightful grasp on what Hegel is doing in Phenomenology should turn to Farneth’s book. In the rest of the book (chs. 6 & 7), and in this symposium, the conversation turns to demonstrate why such a reading of Hegel matters for our shared ethical and political lives.
By social ethics, Farneth does not mean the field of Christian ethical thought first invented in the United States by Francis G. Peabody and other social gospelers at the turn of the twentieth century. Hegelian social ethics and social practices have to do with normativity, authority, accountability, and responsibility implicit in shared activities of an ethical community. If we are to imagine a better political and ethical world, then the constructive work begins with the remains of the decaying one that currently exists. In the conversations that follow (especially in the essays by Joseph Winters, Ali Aslam, and Peter Capretto), it will become clear that Farneth and her respondents are not optimistic about the democratic viability of the current political institutions and structures. Once optimism is disregarded, the question that remains is a practical (and ethical) and epistemological one: what practices need to be cultivated in order to more deeply live into a democratic society where authority is legitimately established and held accountable to the demos. Farneth’s final two chapters attempt to illustrate this, and in doing so she illustrates how religion is nearly always a part of the conversation with Hegel, and so offers us illustrative rituals of reconciliation in confession and forgiveness. But Farneth also points to “relational organizing” exemplified in figures like Septima Clark and Ella Baker, and which I also see in broad-based community organizing affiliates like Faith in Action (previously PICO), IAF, and Gamaliel.
Winters and Aslam approach Farneth’s book with similar yet distinct questions relating to power and hope in practices of reciprocal recognition. Adorno, decolonianity, the dire limits of the liberal capitalist state are part of the conversation here. Then Vanessa Wills gives a rich Marxist critique of what might be a latent conservatism in Hegelian social ethics, and Farneth’s careful response engages material in the Phenomenology not utilized in her book. Capretto’s essay returns to questions of power and the political condition of practices of reciprocal recognition, but in a unique and interesting light: what to do about the bad faith troll? Pearson wraps up the symposium by asking for a finer grain analysis on what exactly Farneth means by “social practices.” Pearson’s question is a welcome one to my mind, because in the social practical literature it seems that just about anything can be a “practice” and what precisely is “shared” or “social” is often unclear. Farneth gives each of these questions their due, while offering avenues for future conversation.
7.8.19 |
Response
Power or Persuasion:
Social Ethics and the Possibility of Repair
As I write, special prosecutor Robert Mueller has not completed and submitted the results of his investigation into whether then-candidate Donald Trump colluded with Russian government operatives to influence the outcome of the 2016 US presidential election. Yet almost from the start of the investigation, President Trump and his legal team have been building a public case against the special prosecutor in order to discredit the work of his team and whatever findings they may deliver. Along with his attacks on the FBI, Trump has actively sought to create a context for the investigation in which his most fervent supporters can reject the final report’s conclusions. That situation points to how the relationships and practices of trust in which “facts” and the authority upon which naming facts rely have broken down.
Norms of trust and cooperation are the “social ethics” upon which the institutions of democratic governance rest, and are at the heart of the coming crisis the Mueller report represents. “Social ethics” is Hegel’s term for the complex interplay among social relationships, practices, and institutions that constitute a political society. As “democracy” has become at once hegemonic over other forms of government and more loosely defined outside a narrow framework of legal institutions, the appreciation for the role social conditions and practices play in undergirding those institutions that is visible in the earliest critics of modern democracy has been pushed to the background. Molly Farneth’s Hegel’s Social Ethics is a welcomed arrival, because it offers guidance on how to think through exactly the kinds of challenges that confront us now and promise to confront us going forward. These are situations broadly defined by the breakdown of common norms, such as the disagreement over climate science, and the drawing of intensely partisan lines which have made the cooperation and agreement required for democracy (understood in the most basic sense, as the people’s capacity to do things together) increasingly fraught. As Farneth notes, “Without relationships and practices of the right kind, communities and societies can only be held together by violence, manipulation, and deceit” (4). Her work promises to save us from those outcomes.
Farneth’s goal is to mine Hegel’s insights into social practices to identify grounds for normative critique, repair, and reconciliation from among existing social practices. Pushing through layers of abstractness that cover Hegel’s writing, Farneth gets at his most important belief, which is that the accounts humans give of what they believe they should do and what they are actually doing presents the basis for repairing the conflicts and relationships that inevitably separate them (10). By showing readers they are already engaged in this reparative process, Hegel reminds them they have the authority and ability to change existing social and political conditions. That reminder feels more timely than ever during an era characterized by impasse that has its sources in a complex government bureaucracy and is reflected in mired political processes across liberal democratic regimes. It is also felt in responses to citizen-led efforts that produced moving spectacles of human action, but produced little positive change in daily life. Events like the Egyptian Revolution, Occupy Wall Street and, more recently in the United States, the 2016 Women’s March, may have even deepened pessimism about the value of direct action and participation.
Hegel’s Social Ethics arrives amidst these challenging on-the-ground conditions. Ambitiously, Farneth extends Hegel beyond the narrow confines of closed communities like Rousseau’s Geneva, where agreement might be easier given a narrower, shared culture. She places his work instead in societies that have grown more religiously and culturally diverse. Ascertaining the General Will in such diverse societies involves more than conflict between Faith and Enlightenment commitments to science and reason, it involves conflict among individuals who disagree over what constitutes the norms and beliefs that should inform what people ought to be doing across multiple faiths in addition to the conflict with Reason.
It is with this purpose that Farneth turns to Hegel’s writing on recognition and the possibilities for reconciliation. Her discussion of practices of confession and forgiveness, for instance, are meant to demonstrate how they can be adopted widely, even by those who are not rooted in the Christian liturgical traditions from which they originate. Her discussion leaves unsaid how non-Christians might access the same practices in the same ways, however. This example illustrates the consequence of Farneth’s decision to separate Hegel’s social ethics from an analysis of power.
Farneth’s introduction situates Hegel and his intellectual work in a specific historical moment: Napoleon’s army defeated the Prussian Army outside the city of Jena, just as Hegel was completing his manuscript for the Phenomenology of Spirit. It is ironic then that history largely disappears from the remainder of Farneth’s text. Yet, the very history Farneth argues shaped Hegel’s thinking also has consequences for the social ethics that interest Farneth. Hegel’s Philosophy of History has a strong progressive narrative, which, when read alongside the social ethics cast them in a much different role.
As Michel Foucault points out, neither Faith or Enlightenment ideals were neutral. They were equally instruments of domination in the projects of modern state formation and imperialism as they were enlarged freedoms. It is this complicated, ambivalent historical legacy that I worry renders Farneth’s effort to make some of these practices of recognition and reconciliation less universal than she would like. Put differently, I think the civic republican framework which she borrows from Philip Petit leads her to view questions of difference from the center because it begins with the idea of a community to which “we” already belong or identify with. As scholars writing from the perspective of racial minorities, indigenous, and queer communities have argued, recognition and reconciliation have often been offered in terms set by the dominant group, where subjects must be judged “respectable” in order to be worthy of legal recognition.
These scholars identify a blind spot across theories of recognition that imagine recognition and reconciliation to be free of power, rather than the discourse at the center of these practices to be, as Foucault argued, themselves instruments of power. When Farneth writes that she reads Hegel as a thinker committed to “mediation without closure” (10), she renders reciprocal recognition less tethered to interpretations that stress the subject’s prior knowledge of absolute spirit. While this means reconciliation is both temporary and revisable in Farneth’s account (9), it is also reached in a power vacuum. This is clear from Farneth’s description of the crisis of authority that interests her. After the fall of authority, she writes, “we are left with power and persuasion” (116). Farneth sidesteps the first in order to think through the second.
Yet to think of the afterlife of agreements that bear the imprint of asymmetric power relations is to recall the powerful emotions, such as anger, humiliation, and ressentiment, that their memory can (still) elicit. These emotions might feed desires for more insurgent and less cooperative forms of engagement than Farneth admits. In other words, there may not be a reserve of trust that can be renewed or repaired. Reflecting upon slavery and the American racial state, Fred Moten expresses exactly this sentiment when he claims, “I also know that what it is that is supposed to be repaired is irreparable. It can’t be repaired. The only thing we can do is tear this shit down completely and build something new.”1 Moten’s rejection and refusal are based upon a record of state recognition that has not yielded the claimed progress, but at best only incremental improvements in the conditions of everyday life for Black Americans.
Additionally, her focus on persuasion and discourse assumes a level of self-knowledge and intelligibility about the self and her motives that post-structural critiques of language, which examine the structures that support discourse or the variance between signifier and signified, cast doubt upon. That is, Farneth believes we can find the words to explain ourselves, our actions, and motivations to others and this makes possible the rituals of confession and forgiveness that she sees as pathways to reconciliation. But the rioting (for lack of a better word) that followed the killing of Freddie Gray in Baltimore at the hands of the police, might have been just as much about not being heard by and not mattering to those in power, as it was not being able to find the words for expressing anguish, frustration, and fears. I wonder what place these kinds of disruptive acts of citizenship have in Farneth’s account, in part because they reflect a history of residential and economic segregation that isolated Gray and the members of his community, cutting them off from participating in the “constitutive conditions” that generate mutual intelligibility.
Of course, I am overdetermining the cleavages and their significance for mutual understanding. My point is not to rule out reconciliation and recognition, but to argue that the history of oppression may leave some subjects more wary of the practices that Farneth endorses than her account admits. Putting power back into the analysis creates rougher ground for the work social ethics can and must do to repair trust and cooperation among citizens. We urgently need and are helped by Farneth’s book and need more work like it.
Stefano Harney and Fred Moten, The Undercommons: Fugitive Planning and Black Study (New York: Minorcompositions, 2013), 152.↩
7.15.19 |
Response
A Latent Conservatism?
The Challenge of Marxian Revolution to Hegelian Social Ethics
Molly Farneth’s Hegel’s Social Ethics deftly traces the contours of what Farneth terms a “post-Kantian” reading of Hegel, and of what such a reading implies for Hegel’s usefulness in navigating the possibility of democratic disagreement and reconciliation. Does fruitful ethical discourse require a bedrock of shared foundational ethical commitments amongst those who participate in the discussion? If it does, then a dilemma may arise. The first horn of this dilemma is that such fruitful discourse might be impossible in practice, given the fact of great diversity among the ethical commitments held by members of society, and of the dizzying array of conflicts among those commitments. The second horn, is that such discourse might in fact be possible, but only by achieving deep theoretical unanimity through a purging of difference—a purge that itself could not be justified through any practice of inclusive democratic deliberation, for its proponents cannot coherently make themselves accountable to those who are to be excluded.
This second horn is the one Farneth has in mind when she warns that while the dialectic of master and slave serves as a “paradigm case of domination” in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit, “Hegel shows how the specter of domination hovers over every shape of consciousness or shape of spirit that does not achieve relationships of reciprocal recognition” (Farneth, 4). This “specter of domination” figures largely throughout Hegel’s Social Ethics as a warning of the steep price to be paid where disagreement and discussion occur in the absence of recognition and reconciliation.
A chief aim of Farneth’s book is to demonstrate how Hegel can be read as offering a way out of what she criticizes as this false choice between deep pessimism for the possibility of inclusive, democratic discourse, on the one hand, and the embrace of a sheer unaccountable exercise of power aimed at producing ethical unanimity through exclusion of difference, on the other. It is her reading of Hegel as “post-Kantian” that provides an interpretive foundation for this aim. On Farneth’s view, absolute spirit does not entail “closure”—the “end of difference, conflict, or contestation”—for it does not involve “the subject’s a priori knowledge of the absolute” (11). Rather, “Absolute spirit is that collection of norms and practices through which a community creates and re-creates itself. It constitutes the standard of knowledge and the ground of authority” (76). For Farneth, then, absolute spirit is realized in our conscious commitments to practices of mutual accountability to one another, and in our willingness to regard our ethical commitments not as fixed and given, but rather as mutable, open to contestation, and produced by that very practice of shared deliberation occurring in and through the dynamic flow of history. To engage in ethical discourse as members of a community and in ways that are intelligible to one another, we need not arrive at some settled body of final conclusions; indeed, the more we treat our ethical commitments as “given” and settled, the further we are from the reconciliation and recognition typified by absolute spirit, for we are more likely to regard others as opponents, rather than as co-participants in a shared project of human self-making.
This “post-Kantian” reading of Hegel elegantly evades the dilemma that deep and seemingly intractable ethical disagreements pose for the possibility of mutual recognition. Yet, another question lingers, one about the ethical exercise of power, and of the practical means by which we as human beings might bring about the reconciliation Farneth advocates. This is so, even if we understand reconciliation not as the absence of ethical disagreement but rather as a willingness to be open and collaborative in our shared ethical discourse in which disagreement persists. Having articulated the implications of Hegel’s theory for how individual human beings ought to engage one another as fellow knowers and as co-authors of values, in Chapter Five, “Religion, Philosophy, and the Absolute,” Farneth asks, “What can we learn from Hegel’s social ethics that might inform democratic thought and practice in a religiously diverse society” (100)? It is this question, and themes related to it, to which I will now turn, with special attention to Farneth’s discussions of the history of women’s liberation in the United States, and of revolutionary politics, one of several forms assumed by the present-day struggle for justice.
Farneth writes that “commitments and norms regarding women’s social, legal, and political standing changed, gradually, through processes of dialectical reasoning” (104). The kinds of actions Farneth identifies as having brought about progress in women’s liberation are all forms of thought and assertion: “assessing,” “writing articles,” “making declarations,” “judging commitments,” and similar. One notable feature of this account is that it tends to downplay the role of the exercise of political power in bringing about change. Farneth describes marches and demonstrations in their function as “public theater,” while activists often believe that a central aim of such exercises is to demonstrate and/or enact the power that masses of people have to directly transform society to better suit their interests, and regardless of what those opposed have to say about it. (To take another case of political activism—the antiwar movement aimed at bringing about an end to the Vietnam war—much of the success of that movement seems to have been a result of having built a movement strong enough to alter the relations of power such that ruling elites began to worry about the continued “governability” of the United States.)
Later in the same chapter, Farneth writes that “Traditions change as the people who participate in them go about the everyday business of life. […] In some cases, these experiences and encounters reveal inadequacies and inconsistencies among people’s previously held commitments” (108). This observation provides an indication of how one might elaborate upon the dialectic between lived experience and theorization of that experience. Perhaps it is an encounter with striking workers who make it no longer possible for armaments to leave a particular shipyard, that influences the shape of dialectical reasoning to develop in one way rather than another. Or put another way: in what ways do human beings, as part of a community, render themselves not only fellow subjects engaged in shared deliberation, but also objective forces that themselves constitute and co-create the encounters and experiences that must be theorized and reckoned with? Can exercises of power be assimilated into democratic deliberation in this way? In what way may practical, extra-rhetorical, extra-theoretical interventions, ones not readily reducible to forms of thought or assertion, permissibly be leveraged to influence the shape of spirit?
Farneth concludes by usefully applying the lessons drawn from her articulation of a Hegelian social ethics, to an assessment of various forms assumed by the present-day struggle for justice. She specifically discusses “liberal elitism” which, she writes, retains Hegel’s “faith in the rational state and the bureaucratic class,” as well as the early 2000s “Occupy Movement,” which she—I think quite rightly—argues was weakened by “its rejection of leadership,” which “made it difficult to know on what basis participants could hold one another or members of society accountable” (122). I will close by discussing Farneth’s critique of Slavoj Zizek, and the connection between this and the broader question of what role power can or should play in a Hegelian social ethics.
In Hegel’s Social Ethics, where Farneth discusses the exercise of power as such, her primary target is often unaccountable power—power as sheer domination. The estrangement characterized by the pre-reconciliation relationship between lord and bondsman inheres in its “asymmetrical distribution of power and accountability” (4). I read Farneth as committed to the view that power is justly exercised only when it is accountable to those in relation to whom it is wielded.
Farneth observes that Zizek argues for a vanguardist revolutionary movement that is itself unaccountable and chosen on an arbitrary, unjustified basis. Such a movement would clearly be found quite wanting as a party to the kind of democratic deliberation based on mutual recognition and accountability that Farneth carefully and convincingly argues for. However, I think the choice of Zizek as a representative foil here makes the critique of revolutionary politics less compelling than it might otherwise be. A better foil might perhaps be Karl Marx himself, who argues that the transition to socialism “cannot be effected except by means of despotic inroads on the rights of property.”1 Why despotic? It is because the kinds of changes necessary to bring about human emancipation are in principle unjustifiable on the basis of bourgeois property relations. This is different from Zizek’s approach, because Marx’s point is not that such alterations are unjustifiable altogether or unjustifiable as such. They are justifiable on the basis of the interests of the vast mass of society, which is poised, politically, epistemically, and historically, to represent the interests of all humanity.
Marx’s case for revolution is in large part premised on the claim that in order for mutual recognition to be made possible, the world must first be transformed so that there is no capitalism and thus, with the social role of “capitalist” as little live and salient in that future society as “czar” is in ours, no capitalists. It would seem, then, that Marx’s proposed form of majoritarian democratic authority is ruled out by the Hegelian social ethics that Farneth puts forward. For it defines itself, essentially, in part by its utter rejection of any accountability to capitalists, and a deep rejection of, a hostility and a lack of openness to, capitalist ethics and norms. Farneth’s critique of revolutionary politics can be put even more sharply then, in relation to Marx’s particular approach to accountability and its limits. (Insofar as Marx’s approach is nuanced, principled, and democratic in a way that Zizek’s is not, and yet Farneth offers a critique that, if true, would rule out even that stronger view as unacceptably authoritarian and closed to reconciliation.)
But if this is so, then one is lured back to one familiar charge against Hegel that Farneth seems concerned to dispel—namely, that there is a latent conservatism built into even more critical and progressive interpretations of his philosophical project. This, I take it, is centrally at stake in the question of whether or not Hegel is to be read as a “philosopher of ‘mediation without closure’” (11), as Farneth advocates. How do we navigate seemingly irreconcilable ethical commitments, where the existing arrangement of power benefits those who have the least to gain from participating in the forms of democratic deliberation that Farneth describes? It would seem terribly simple, then, for the oppressed to be made hostage to the good consciences of their oppressors.
Frederick Douglass wrote, “Power concedes nothing without a demand. It never has, and it never will.”2 History seems to have proven him quite right about this. Farneth presents the grassroots democracy of community organizers and of the Civil Rights Movement of the 1960s, as models of mutual recognition, which is very helpful for illuminating the picture of human cooperation and solidarity that she has in mind as an aim. But given the ethical constraints Farneth seems to place on the just exercise of power, and given the presence and, indeed, the dominance, of forces opposed to democratic social transformation, by what practical means do we make actual the clearly desirable forms of mutual recognition and accountability so compellingly outlined in Hegel’s Social Ethics?
Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, Communist Manifesto, trans. Samuel Moore, 1888, https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1848/communist-manifesto/index.htm.↩
Frederick Douglass, “West India Emancipation,” in Frederick Douglass: Selected Speeches and Writings, ed. Philip S. Foner and Yuval Taylor (Chicago, IL: Chicago Review Press, 2000), 367.↩
Joseph Winters
Response
Hegel’s Social Ethics and the Liberal Democratic Capitalism
For some time, the nineteenth-century German philosopher G. W. F. Hegel has received a bad rap, or at least a one-sided interpretation. Devoted readers of Kierkegaard, for instance, accuse Hegel of being the philosopher of totality, the thinker who sides with the universal over the singular, abstract reason against passion and faith. Hegel’s rational ethical system, according to Kierkegaard, cannot make sense of the existential angst that Abraham experienced when ordered by YHWH to sacrifice his son, Isaac. Although Theodor Adorno’s work draws heavily from Hegel’s dialectical approach to identity and difference, the former underscores the “negative” quality of the dialectic as a protest against Hegel’s emphasis on wholeness, reconciliation, and so forth. For Adorno, not unlike Kierkegaard, Hegel’s insistence on the “whole” being the form of truth devalues that which is divergent, dissonant, and fragmented. In the last two decades, a group of new Hegel scholars has contested the image of Hegel as the totalizing metaphysician, contending that the German philosopher has been mis-recognized. Commentators like Robert Pippen, Robert Brandom, and Terry Pinkard argue that Hegel successfully extends Kant’s critique of metaphysics and develops Kant’s concern about the limits of reason. In addition, these authors show that Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit does not have to be read as an ethereal, otherworldly text. Rather than being a sweeping, forward marching idea, Spirit is simply the name for the formation of social practices, practices defined by authoritative norms, mutual recognition, and reason exchange across difference and disagreement. Hegel, according to these authors, offers a conception of freedom that is socially constituted and constrained by norms, a conception that resonates with the best of liberal democracy.
Molly Farneth’s Hegel’s Social Ethics: Religion, Conflict, and Rituals of Reconciliation is the most recent attempt to offer a more nuanced and generative reading of Hegel’s Phenomenology in light of contemporary problems and in the spirit of agonistic democracy. As the author describes, “This book holds . . . two aspects of Hegel’s project together—epistemology and ethics, knowing and living well. In so doing, it gives an account of the relationships and practices that a community ought to cultivate, and of what happens when those relationships and practices are absent or deformed. In the Phenomenology of Spirit, Hegel shows what domination looks like and suggests that there is an alternative to it, a way of coping with conflict and forging solidarity. And while Hegel was no democrat, he describes how conflicts can be confronted and hope for reconciliation sustained through just means in diverse communities” (2). For Farneth, Hegel “has much to teach” contemporary society about the cultivation of practices that enable citizens to work through conflicts, practices of reconciliation that make room for tension and contestation. As she puts it: “A modern Sittlichkeit [ethical community] involves contestation as well as rituals of reconciliation” (ix). Consequently, Farneth wants to disabuse the reader of unfair readings of Hegel that accuse him of resolving difference and conflict. Farneth’s Hegel acknowledges that these qualities are essential to the health and integrity of a political community.
According to the author, conflicts within and between communities can be dealt with under the condition that participants realize that identities and commitments are normative, constructed, and mutable. In other words, a conflict becomes manageable when those involved in the conflict allow their commitments and attachments to undergo contestation and revision. According to Farneth, Hegel’s reading of Sophocles’ Antigone shows us how a society breaks down in the face of an irreconcilable conflict. Recall that Antigone is placed in a tragic predicament when the ruler Creon forbids her from burying her brother, Polynices, because the latter committed treason against the state. Antigone is placed between two incompatible obligations—the duty to her family and the duty to the state, the obligation to divine law and to human law. For Farneth, Hegel describes how a tragic conflict, or a situation in which “two goods or rights stand in [inevitable] opposition to one another” (32), is the result of individuals (like Antigone and Creon) who take their identities to be natural. The characters in Sophocles’ play uncritically accept their social roles and obligations, thereby avoiding “the responsibility to create, maintain, and transform them” (33). The characters in Antigone become emblematic of the problems with the Greek polis, with a society that does not fully realize how subjects are involved in the creation and transformation of norms. For Hegel, freedom involves self-consciousness; it requires a social world that teaches subjects to take responsibility for their commitments and actions—rather than blaming an undesirable situation exclusively on fate, nature, or superhuman powers.
In addition to the conflict between Antigone and Creon, Farneth draws attention to Hegel’s discussion in Phenomenology of the ostensible impasse between enlightenment and faith. This discussion provides resources for working through the interminable debates between religious groups and secularists, evangelicals and atheists. According to Hegel, enlightened reason and the perspective of religious faith share similar shortcomings and don’t realize that each position depends on the other. Whereas enlightened reason locates epistemic authority in the self-legislating subject, the person of faith locates this authority in the self’s immediate relationship with the divine. In both cases, the inner self that becomes the site of authority is imagined as detached from the actual social world. At the same time, both stances have something to offer. Enlightened reason can teach faith that one’s relationship to the Other is always mediated and constituted by concepts. And the faith perspective, when properly understood, can teach reason that thought and reflection happen within the context of community; reason is a product of norms, language, and shared practices. As Farneth points out, Hegel’s ability to mediate between Enlightenment and Faith suggests that religion has its own rationality and that conciliatory practices within communities will rely on rituals, virtues, and sacraments usually associated with religious faith.
This détente between reason and faith is important for Farneth’s understanding of the rituals of reconciliation that prevent conflicts from becoming static, reified, and tragic. When most people think of Hegel and conflict, they turn to the section in Phenomenology on the master/slave relationship. In this allegory, Hegel shows the reader that domination is the result of subjects who cannot see themselves reflected in the other without subordinating that other; objectification derives from a situation in which selves do not recognize certain others as co-participants in a common life. At the inchoate stage of the drama between lord and bondsman, one self-consciousness can only see another as a hostile adversary or as an occasion to project and extend the self’s desires. Within this initial struggle, the slave is in a position that results from the fear of death, from remaining in a state of nature and capitulating to the basic drive to remain alive. The master’s domination over the slave is unsatisfying as the former ultimately desires another free, responsible subject to be a member of his or her community. And the slave’s ability to work and produce, to make and create things, gives the slave a sense of independence and power, preparing the slave for participation in Spirit. As we see in the case of Greek tragedy and in the enlightenment/faith standoff, Hegel’s master/slave narrative demonstrates a movement from a hostile, adversarial relationship to one that moves, changes, and transforms into a practice of mutual recognition.
While Farneth acknowledges the importance of the master/slave dialectic, she draws the reader’s attention to an under-examined aspect of Hegel’s thought that has decisive implications for practices of reconciliation. For Farneth, Hegel’s discussion of confession and forgiveness toward the end of Phenomenology supplements the earlier struggle for recognition. The relationship between confessor and forgiver develops out of the hostile interaction between the wicked consciousness—the self that acts according to conscience and subjective convictions—and the judging consciousness—the self that evaluates and criticizes the wicked consciousness from a sense of objective duty. While the judging consciousness gets something right about the overly subjective pursuits of the wicked consciousness, the latter recognizes that the judging consciousness is also acting from a particular location. The interplay between judge and the wicked subject becomes a mobile, tension-filled relationship between two selves that acknowledge their mutual culpability, responsibility, and fallibility. They are called into a set of practices that involve both judging and acting, both confessing wrongs and forgiving evils (since the forgiver is implicated, to some degree, in the evils that need to be redressed). As Farneth puts it: “Through their confession and forgiveness, the wicked consciousness and the judging consciousness are reconciled. Their reconciliation, moreover, marks the emergence of full-fledged reciprocal recognition and absolute spirit” (72). And this possibility of ongoing recognition requires something like Lutheran sacraments, rituals through which individuals are treated as judges and wrongdoers, confessors and forgivers.
For Farneth, reading Hegel on the interplay between reconciliation and conflict has practical implications for democratic practices. While Hegel “was not a democrat . . . and supported a Prussian state with a limited monarchy and a large bureaucratic class” (120), Farneth contends that Hegel’s thought contributes to galvanizing an agonistic form of democracy. Democratic authority, following Hegel, cannot emerge from someplace outside of “disagreement, conflict, and the contest for power” (116). At the same time, democratic authority cannot be reduced to these conditions; it must encompass the “negative” while developing practices that aim for reconciliation, shared norms, cooperation, and so forth. Democratic life involves the extension of reciprocal recognition, a commitment to opposing the domination of others, and “the acceptance of human fallibility, the perpetuity of difference and contestation, and an implicit challenge to the notion of sovereign agency” (118). It involves a society in which both leaders and everyday people are accountable to norms that are revisable and contestable. A Hegelian-inspired democracy does not fetishize the revolutionary vanguard ruler nor does it celebrate leaderless populism; it underscores how elected leaders must be held accountable for their actions and decisions by organizations and constituencies. Finally, democratic life must involve practices of forgiveness and confession, a recognition that we are the subjects and objects of evil and injustice.
Farneth’s Hegel is hopeful that conflicts and disagreements can be worked through and modified. In her brilliantly written text, there is a tacit distinction between mutable conflict and static antagonism. Hegel teaches us that modern subjects are not bound to tragic conflicts because we do not have to uncritically accept the positions, roles, and predicaments we have been thrown into. Or more precisely, Hegel’s notion of self-consciousness indicates that subjects are responsible for (and take themselves as committed or uncommitted to) various modern practices and arrangements. We need to think more about the contrast between conflict and antagonism, a thought experiment that involves a series of questions and queries. What would modernity be without war, nation-state sovereignty, settler projects, coloniality and its afterlife, and the violent pursuit of property (sanctioned by law)? These are not just wrongs that need to be redressed and reconciled but inveterate conditions for liberal democracy. Isn’t there a relatively stable antagonism that exists between nation-state sovereignty and indigenous practices and relationships to the earth? In addition, as a host of black studies and queer theory scholars have argued, don’t conflict and antagonism, freedom and domination, and recognizability and abjection, go together? Even as the sphere of recognition historically expands to include formerly excluded groups, this expansion does not remove the general line between the livable and unlivable, between those deemed worthy of life and those associated with death. In other words, spheres of recognition can exist through and because of (not despite) patterns of violence and domination disproportionately directed toward certain populations. Disagreements and conflicts can be ostensibly resolved or managed because the less manageable conflicts have been projected outward and elsewhere. (In Hegel’s Elements of the Philosophy of Right, he discusses, without much reservation, how the antagonisms and surpluses of production get directed outward toward Europe’s colonies.) Ultimately what I am posing is the following: Is the new Hegel tethered to liberal democratic capitalism and if so, does he help us think through the traumatic kernel, the monstrous underside of this formation? Does Hegel’s faith in the elasticity of norms and commitments downplay the ways in which change and novelty happen within constitutive constraints and relatively stable arrangements of power, violence, and anguish?
These questions and concerns might be taking Farneth in directions that the book is not intended to go. Her main aim in this project is to show that Hegel offers rich insights to think about the interaction between reconciliation and conflict in a social world riddled with disagreements that have become static and congealed, and a world where these conflicts are often responded to with simplistic appeals to unity and forgiveness. In such a predicament, Farneth’s reinterpretation of Hegel is a welcome and challenging read.
7.1.19 | Molly Farneth
Reply
Response to Winters
Professor Winters and I have been talking about Hegel and Adorno for many years now, his reminders to tarry with the negative tempering my Hegelian enthusiasms. I have long been grateful for these conversations, and no less so today. In his response to my book, Winters asks if perhaps my enthusiasms are not tempered enough, if even an agonistic Hegel remains “tethered to liberal democratic capitalism” and to a set of arrangements that are not incidentally but integrally connected to violence and domination.
I’ve argued that the Phenomenology of Spirit offers insights into the conceptualization and analysis of the norms and power relations implicit in our relationships, practices, and institutions. I’ve also argued that Hegel’s book suggests that there are social practices available to us that are likely to foster relationships, practices, and institutions that are less dominating and alienating than many of those we currently have. That Hegel sometimes fails to apply these insights to his own social and political context is undeniable. In the Philosophy of Right, for instance, Hegel puts his faith in bureaucracy and monarchy, acts as an apologist for colonialism, and endorses the patriarchal family (in part, he writes, because women are like plants). But I don’t think that Hegel’s failures entirely undercut his insights elsewhere. With respect to his sexism, for instance, it is possible to read Hegel against himself. As I argue in my reading of Hegel’s discussion of Antigone in the Phenomenology, he shows how treating any particular set of gender norms and roles as natural or fixed leads to tragic and mournful consequences. Dissatisfaction with our social norms, including those related to gender, ought to lead us to scrutinize, critique, and change them. The same is true for social structures and institutions.
Some readers, Winters included, have found the last chapter of Hegel’s Social Ethics to be “hopeful,” with the implication that this is not a virtuous hope but a vicious and unwarranted presumption. In that last chapter, I consider how a Hegelian account of reciprocal recognition might inform democratic politics, and I write things like this: “Democratic authority emerges where relationships and practices of reciprocal recognition are strong and widespread. The norms of a community are authoritative for its members insofar as concrete, democratically structured relationships and social practices are in place” (130). I offer a handful of examples in which authority and accountability are being generated and practiced, including the work of relational organizers and restorative justice practitioners. Winters concludes that “Farneth’s Hegel is hopeful that conflicts and disagreements can be worked through and modified.” To be clear, I hope that conflicts can be worked through in ways that neither dominate nor alienate, but by no means do I presume that this will be the case.
The dominant offices and institutions in our liberal “democratic” capitalist state are neither just nor democratic. The people in power, the laws they write and enforce, and the institutions they lead are more often working against democracy in the sense I define than for it. I do not believe that these current arrangements of power will long hold. None of us yet knows what will replace them. At present, concrete, democratically structured practices and relationships are few and far between. With no one sufficiently organized to oppose the authoritarians and oligarchs, they seize ever more power for themselves. If we are not resigned to the prospect of a future of full-fledged authoritarianism and oligarchy, what kinds of relationships, practices, institutions, and social movements do we need to build? What alternatives might be more just and democratic? And what examples, few and humble though they may be, might people look to for generating non-dominating authority and mutual accountability?
The relationships, practices, and institutions that characterize much of our social and political life are dominating and alienating. We cannot be at home in such a world. But it is from this world that we build the next, even as we scrutinize, critique, and transform what we carry forward with us—Hegel included.