Decreation
By
11.26.15 |
Symposium Introduction
This book is about the last things, the novissima, of creatures and the cosmos. It is not a book about the future. It is not a work of eschatology in the sense of an account of the penultimate events which presage the world’s passing away or the affective responses appropriate to this passing away. It is, instead, a book about the possible ‘inglorious’ and “glorious” final ends of creatures and the cosmos. Griffiths returns to a tradition of calling the final ends of creatures novissima (the newest or latest things) inasmuch as he argues that the last things, or the final ends, of creatures are indeed last and final, there being no new thing or novel event beyond them.
The book consists of seven parts, with each part comprised of several “paragraphs.” The parts run from the grammar (I) and doctrine (II) concerning final things; to eternity and timespace (III); to the final ends of angels (IV), humans (V), and other creatures (VI); and finally to an imagining of what life before the Lord in heaven is like and what this means for life in the world’s current “devastation” (VII). Structurally, then, what Griffiths offers is indeed an account of the final or last ends of creatures and the cosmos. Materially, however, Griffiths covers a tremendous swathe of theological and philosophical ground in order to elucidate these ends, often doing so in ways highly attentive to tradition and dogma and highly creative in its conclusions. For instance, readers are given a primer in theological method; an account of eternity, the temporality of creatures (with a defense of a species of four dimensionalism), and the relation between them; reflections on atonement, the liturgy, and the Trinity; a phenomenology of being fleshly, epistemological judgments upon “the inner theatre,” and a theological account of lament through Augustine’s reflections on tears in the Confessions; and even a brief defense of political quietism. This list of examples does not do justice to the sweeping range of interwoven doctrines and issues covered in Decreation.
In one sense Decreation is a stunning example of systematic theology, and yet its systematic nature is also present in the patient and focused way in which Griffiths outlines and explores different possibilities for the glorious and inglorious ends of creatures. He is clear that what he is offering is speculative and so his positions, while grounded in dogma and informed by doctrine, are simply meant to be reasoned and attractive proposals handed over for further consideration and scrutiny. Briefly put, Griffiths argues that there are three types of last things possible for creatures: annihilation, simple stasis, and repetitive stasis. Annihilation is the creature’s complete unmaking of itself through sin, which leads to the creature’s irreversible and total extinction. Simple stasis, which could be either salvation or damnation, and so either glorious or inglorious, means that post-mortem creatures undergo no narrative, no change, no further novelty. Repetitive stasis, again in either salvation or damnation, describes a cyclical state of affairs which recurs once and again without any change or development. Griffiths lays out his speculative positions clearly and early on in the book: the glorious last thing of animate creatures is a repetitive stasis, the foretaste of which is the liturgy, and the inglorious last thing of animate creatures is annihilation.
Given the scope of Decreation, the timeliness of its attention to annihilationism and universalism (topics which have entered broader and more popular theological and ecclesial contexts), the clarity and originality of its arguments, and its genuinely moving and kergymatic prose and vision, Griffiths has given the church—and our symposium’s panelists—much to ponder and discuss. Holly Taylor Coolman questions Griffiths’ commitments to heavenly life as repetitive stasis over against epektasis and to the dimming of one’s inner theater before the liturgy, a claim also addressed and interrogated in Theodora Hawksley’s contribution. Joe Lenow raises questions regarding the speculative character of Griffiths’ arguments, whether there is a hierarchy of the blessed in heaven, and to what extent the positions in Decreation could serve as an argument for universalism. Robert Saler’s piece examines Griffiths’ presuppositions and claims regarding theological method and speculation from a Protestant perspective. James Wetzel brings up the issue of the book’s title (not addressed in the book itself but hinted at in an epigram from Simone Weil) and offers further riffs on heaven, mutability, and forgiveness. That these contributions are in turn charitable, speculative, interrogative, and moving is a testament not only to their quality but also the quality of the work Griffiths has given us and the numerous proposals and questions it contains and raises.
Panelists
Holly Taylor Coolman
Theodora Hawksley
Joe Lenow
Robert Saler
James Wetzel
About the Author
Paul J. Griffiths is Warren Chair of Catholic Theology at Duke Divinity School.
10.28.15 |
Response
Experience and Prayer
I CAN THINK OF no higher compliment to pay a work of theology than that it returned me to prayer. Without being too bold, I think that one of the reasons Decreation is so rich, unusual and moving is that it owes much to Paul’s own prayer: the confessional mode is never very far below the surface. It is prayer, and specifically the issue of liturgical prayer and its purpose, that I want to address in this essay.
In discussing the heavenly last end of human beings, Paul argues that it is characteristic of human beings to categorially and possessively layer our qualia, such that we develop an “inner theatre”—it seems like something for us to be us and, at least in some of our experiences, we are one of the things in our own field of view (222–24). In the crosshairs here are not just experiences in which one consciously feels oneself “playing a part,” but experience more generally—anything that seems like something to me, anything I remark as it passes. Negatively, Paul argues that such self-presence is an artefact of the fall, and that cultivating it may be necrophiliac (236). Positively, he argues that heaven and the joy of seeing the Lord face to face exclude this kind of presence-to-self. In heaven, there is no corner of me left to observe myself; I am completely turned towards God in joy (104, 236). Participation in liturgy, and the formation of liturgical habits over time, is one way in which we can attenuate experience, and foreshadow the ecstatic heavenly state (230–35).
Liturgy is, among other things, prayer, and Catholic spirituality evinces two broad approaches to the question of experience in prayer. One, of which John of the Cross is representative, is at best disinterested in experience, and often keen to suppress it.
For John, this is because all we imagine depends on creaturely images and tropes and is therefore “most unlike and disproportioned to God”: if we desire the unmediated presence of God we must negate all images.1 It also springs from John’s fierce distinction between God and the creature, which introduces a radical agnosticism about the significance of our felt experience—quite simply, we cannot tell what God is doing from what it feels like to us. For John the journey into God “does not consist in recreations, experiences, and spiritual feelings, but in the living, sensory and spiritual, exterior and interior death of the cross.”2 In the first approach to experience in prayer, then, we deliberately switch off the lights of the inner theatre and wait for God in unfeeling, unseeing darkness.
In the second approach to spiritual experience, of which Ignatius of Loyola is representative, we deliberately turn the theatre lights up. Ignatius is not only interested in the quality of our experience in prayer, but also in scrutinising it, and indeed in cultivating particular kinds of experience. His Spiritual Exercises seek to bring to conscious awareness oneself-as-prayer, oneself-as-creature and oneself-as-responder-to-God.3 Experience is central: one annotation at the start of the Exercises advises the director, if he perceives that the exercitant is not affected by “any spiritual experiences,” to carefully inquire whether she is making the exercises properly.4 This kind of attention to experience is meant to be sustained, and in the practice of the daily examen, the categorial and possessive sorting of qualia is pursued retrospectively as the individual closely inspects her day’s experience for the presence and action of God.5
John and Ignatius have more in common than this brief caricature allows, but some questions nevertheless emerge here, which I shall put sharply: where does Paul’s vision of heaven leave us in relation to spiritual experience? Is any attention to such experience at best second-rate, and at worst misguided? Is the Ignatian emphasis on experience, on attention to it and cultivation of it, necrophiliac? Paul’s answer, at least to the second question, would seem to be “yes”: “Experience, the categorial and possessive layering of our qualia, is at best epiphenomenal to the liturgical life, which is also the Christian life, and at worst inimical to it” (236).
It is worth making an obliquely critical point here about gratitude and acceptance. John’s writings about the dark night take the form of commentary on poetry written during the experience of literal and spiritual darkness, and the seeming absence of God during his imprisonment in Toledo. It was through this unsought-for experience of darkness—or, better, lack of any experience or sense of God—that John came to recognise it as a gift, and the nada, nada, nada as something worth pursuing.6 As he writes on the sketch of Mount Carmel made for the nuns at Beas,
In this nakedness the spirit
finds its rest, for when it
covets nothing, nothing
raises it up, and nothing
weighs it down, because it is
in the center of its humility.7
Ignatius’ scrutiny of experience also starts from acceptance of what is given us by God in the way of experience: one of the objects of the daily examen, alongside discernment, is gratitude to God for favours received.8 In a different way, too, the Exercises set out to place the soul “in the center of its humility,” indifferent and free in relation to our experience, and oriented wholly to the praise and service of God.9
I should say at this point that I share Paul’s instinctively suspicious attitude towards experience and self-presence, and I like very much his Möbius-strip sense that liturgy “is a matter simply of doing and saying these things, and, over time, of becoming the kind of person who does and says these things” (233). B XT pride in borrowed clothing. ut I am learning—and here I too am drifting into confessional mode—that it is ultimately what one does with experience that counts. The point is neither to cultivate and burnish particular kinds of experience, nor to reject or squash them, because both responses ultimately keep us enthroned, where we like to be, as masters of our interior lives.10 Accepting what is given us by way of experience and, with it, ourselves as given, with all our silly self-regard and ludicrous crankiness, may be the way in which we find the centre of our humility, and thereby grow into a deeper passivity, an ordinary humility, a greater simplicity, all of which may in the end stand as good preparation for a life of eternal gratitude.11 Something like this underpins this comment from Dom Philip Jebb, OSB, on spiritual experiences and the last things, which I give the last word:
I know the pundits on prayer tend to discount such experiences and say that we should not pray in order to get them, and I suppose there is a truth in that. But I only know that God loves me because of his gifts to me. And it is a poor sort of response to a gift not to rejoice in it. And if joy is not the object of life, I do not know what is. And if you are always looking for the dangers and pitfalls you will never see the view, and your life will be the poorer for it, and if you try to skate without falling over you will never know what skating really means. But for myself I believe that God loves me, and is constantly thinking up new ways to bring me joy, as is the way of all true lovers. So if this is the way to hell then it has been a pretty glorious one.12
John of the Cross, The Ascent of Mount Carmel II.8.5, in The Collected Works of St John of the Cross, trans. Kieran Kavanaugh, OCD, and Otilio Rodriguez, OCD, (Washington, DC: Institute of Carmelite Studes, 1964).↩
Ascent II.7.12.↩
Though Ignatius would probably agree with Paul’s statement that “what matters is response; and that response is given in action, not in attention to the inner theater’s spectacle” (Decreation, 235).↩
Louis J. Puhl, SJ, The Spiritual Exercises of St Ignatius (Chicago: Loyola University Press, 1951), §6. Hereafter Exx §.↩
Exx §43.↩
As Denys Turner points out, the point is not seeking out an experience of darkness, but negating experience altogether. See Turner, The Darkness of God: Negativity and Christian Mysticism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), 231.↩
Kavanaugh and Rodriguez, The Collected Works of St John of the Cross, 66–67.↩
Exx §43.↩
“Consequently, as far as we are concerned, we should not prefer health to sickness, riches to poverty, honor to dishonor, a long life to a short life.” Exx §23.↩
Contrition and disgust at one’s inner theatricals are not quite the same thing: the former is humility, the second may be pride in borrowed clothing.↩
See Letters XXVI and XXVII in Roger Hudleston OSB (ed.) The Spiritual Letters of Dom John Chapman OSB (London: Sheed and Ward, 1954) pp.83–94.↩
Philip Jebb OSB, “Wonder Is So Sudden a Gift,” in Maria Boulding, OSB (ed.), A Touch of God: Eight Monastic Journeys (London: SPCK, 1982) 1–26 (12).↩
10.30.15 |
Response
Crowns of Prayer and Praise
Final Questions about Last Things
PAUL GRIFFITHS IS A patient theologian. I don’t intend to make any special claim about his character with this statement, though in point of fact I’ve always known him to be very generous as a teacher, happy to follow a student’s line of questioning through to the end no matter how unpromising it may seem. Rather, I mean to say that in his writing Griffiths is exemplary of the patience needed to carry out at least one conception of the theological task, that of ordered discourse about the LORD.1 With unflagging precision, he lays out the presuppositions and entailments of the theological claims he is making, and presents their systematic interlacing; he is careful to note where the church has spoken on various theological matters, and the degree of authority with which it has done so; and he presents the endpoints of his arguments not as conclusions that ought to be accepted by all rationally or morally well-formed readers, but as offerings to be debated and very possibly rejected in coming years or generations. There are very few threads left unpulled in Decreation, leading to extended treatments of timespace, angels, and inanimate material beings.
All these features indicate the work of a theologian in no hurry, not rushing under the weight of a felt need to solve some pressing issue in contemporary Christian thought or practice, not compelled by the need to make a difference. I very much want theologians who feel these pressing tasks, who give the church resources for confronting the problems now facing it; but I also wish there were many more theologians like Griffiths, theologians liberated to follow seemingly marginal questions in theology by the recognition that none of us can predict or secure the effects that our words may have—and that, in fact, it is not the job of the theologian to be concerned with these effects. It’s only a short distance from here to one more sense of what it might mean to be a patient theologian: following the etymology of patiens in the verb patior—to suffer or endure—we should note that Griffiths is alive to the error and self-deception that enters in whenever we try to seek the LORD with intellects wounded by sin. The patient theologian, then, is one who laments the fragmentary quality of our knowledge of the LORD, who seeks out guidance and correction by others, and who tries always to keep one’s attention focused on where reason gives out in our attempts to know. Here again, Griffiths has much to teach.
In this response, I would like to focus on three questions raised for me by Decreation: first, the status of the interpretive task within Griffiths’ project, and especially the question of whether Griffiths’ own account of interpretation should be considered a speculation;2 second, a thread that it seems to me Griffiths has not pulled in this book, the question of whether there is a hierarchy of beatitude among the saints in heaven; and finally, a question about whether Griffiths’ arguments in favor of the resurrection of nonhuman animals may double as an argument for universalism. There are, no doubt, a slew of interesting quarrels to pick with Decreation. Because of the consistency of Griffiths’ thought, many of the most interesting of these will be challenges to his system as a whole—attempts to argue against his thought from different presuppositions than the ones he holds, which thus attempt to construct an alternative picture of the last things, and to convince the reader that the alternative picture is more beautiful on the whole than the one Griffiths presents. Because I share most of Griffiths’ theological starting-points,3 I will argue on grounds largely internal to the project, accepting his general methodology and views on the LORD and creation presented within Decreation.
Decreation is notable in part for the dramatic speculative claims Griffiths makes—centrally, of course, his account of annihilation as a possible novissimum of human and angelic creatures. I would like to focus, however, on a slightly less showy moment of Griffiths’ thought, the work of theological interpretation. In the section on “Doctrine and Last Things,” Griffiths writes,
Speculative theological work can proceed in many ways. Three among them are usually present, and are certainly so in this work. The first is the offering of interpretations of doctrinal statements. Determining that some claim is doctrinal—for example, that ingredient to the last thing of human creatures is carnis resurrectio, the resurrection of the flesh—does not by itself yield conclusions about what the claim means. What, the theologians may reasonably ask, is the meaning of caro in the phrase carnis resurrectio? No claim, doctrinal or otherwise, exhaustively specifies the means of its own interpretation or the conclusions of interpretive acts, and it is part of the theologian’s task to make proposals about these things.4
As Griffiths goes about the work of interpretation throughout Decreation, a clear pattern emerges that further specifies how he envisions this task: interpretation does not primarily involve an attempt to recover the intentions of those who crafted a doctrinal definition, but rather aims to mark out the minimal set of claims to which the theologian is necessarily committed by any particular doctrinal definition when it is situated within the broader context of magisterial teaching. So, in the example Griffiths gives above, the theologian is committed to there being something that the word caro picks out as capable of resurrection, but in itself, does not specify what that might be. Some options will be closed off by other magisterial teachings that mention caro, but we can expect that a fairly wide range of options will remain open.
An especially clear instance of this approach funding Griffiths’ speculative thought in Decreation can be found in his treatment of the general resurrection. The vast majority of Catholic interpreters of the magisterial text Benedictus Deus have read its statement that “on the day of judgment all humans (omnes homines) appear with their bodies before Christ’s tribunal to give an account of what they have done so that everyone might receive what is appropriate according to whether they have acted well or badly in the body”5 as an affirmation that all those who have ever been human persons will be reconstituted in the flesh and will appear before the judgment seat of Christ. This is, at first blush, a claim about the general resurrection, and tells us that all those who have ever lived, bound for heaven and hell alike, appear before Christ to be judged in the flesh. Yet Griffiths pushes interpretation in another direction: “The key interpretive question here is what the opening phrase omnes homines may reasonably be taken to mean. I have already argued (§22) that according to Christian doctrine, there are no homines, no humans, in the intermediate state; discarnate souls are not that. And so the phrase cannot refer to them.”6 This is perhaps a surprising conclusion, but on Griffiths’ understanding of the interpretative task, a perfectly reasonable one. I do not mean to suggest that there is anything illegitimate about Griffiths’ interpretative method; he seems to stand clearly within a long tradition of Catholic thought about magisterial authority, associated paradigmatically with John Henry Newman and his Letter to the Duke of Norfolk.7
The question I wish to pose, however, is this: should we consider this interpretative method undergirding so much of Griffiths’ speculation the disposition that all faithful Catholic theologians should hold toward magisterial teaching, or is this way of reading magisterial texts itself a speculative proposal? To be clear, I am not asking whether theology should begin with the tasks of investigation of magisterial teaching, but whether Griffiths thinks that his approach to interpreting magisterial teaching—restricting assent only to what can be required by the “legitimate sense of the words”—is the only fully Catholic one. Griffiths presents no magisterial texts telling us that we should treat doctrinal definitions in this way, though such texts may indeed exist (I am far from an expert on these matters). Another possibility is that there are compelling philosophical grounds, perhaps in the philosophy of language, for restricting the binding force of magisterial teaching to the texts of doctrinal definitions. Or perhaps there are properly theological reasons for thinking this, rooted in an account of the nature of the LORD’s revelation to the church. The significance of this line of questioning can be brought out, I hope, by contrasting Griffiths’ position to the one presented by Lewis Ayres in the final chapter of Nicaea and Its Legacy. Ayres faults much contemporary theology precisely for its location of authority in the words of conciliar statements and definitions, without accompanying attention to the theological cultures (in this case, pro-Nicene) that generated these definitions. So Ayres: “I will be understanding pro-Nicene theology to be functioning as an authority when its basic principles are treated as a foundation for subsequent theological reflection and its theologians as a constant point of departure in the articulation of Trinitarian belief in subsequent periods and cultural contexts.”8 It is perhaps ironic that Griffiths and Ayres, both deeply rooted in Augustine’s thought, would agree (I suspect) on most matters directly related to Trinitarian theology, and the necessity of maintaining many aspects of the pro-Nicene culture of the fourth and fifth centuries that produced the Niceno-Constantinopolitan Creed (deep engagement with the text of Scripture, contemplative epistemic reserve, etc.). Nevertheless, Ayres’ argument about what is authoritative in past generations of Christian doctrine seems to push against some aspects of Griffiths’ argument, and could be pushed into periods beyond those in which Ayres is most interested. What, for example, are the thought-forms or features of theological culture that produced Benedictus Deus? My sense is that attention to the theological culture of Late Medieval France and its representation of the general resurrection would push against the indeterminacy Griffiths finds in the phrase omnes homines.9 If Griffiths’ approach to interpreting magisterial texts is regarded as a speculation on Catholic theological methodology, an approach like Ayres’ that attends to theological culture in interpreting authoritative doctrinal definitions remains possible. Is such an account possible? And if it is, why should we regard Griffiths’ speculative methodology, the presumption of linguistic indeterminacy, as superior to other approaches?
Second, let me raise a question about a theological tradition concerning last things that Griffiths does not deal with in an extended way in Decreation, the question of a hierarchy or gradation even among those in a state of beatitude. These considerations are not totally absent from Griffiths’ book: it is clear both that all difference is not obliterated in paradise, and that such difference is rooted in the earthly histories that have brought heaven’s occupants to this degree of intimacy with the LORD. Griffiths writes of our retaining “a style signature that is the habit of being by which we can be recognized”;10 and his depiction of heaven as a time in which “the resurrected saints and angels are congregated around the assumed flesh of Mary and the ascended flesh of Christ”11 at least indicates a distinction between the manner in which Mary inhabits heaven and the manner in which the rest of the saints do. Beyond this, however, we receive little explicit discussion of differentiation among the saints.
There is, however, a long theological (though on Griffiths’ terms, probably speculative as opposed to doctrinal) tradition of marking different gradations of beatitude among the saints. St. Ambrose’s Epistola 42 writes, communicating the condemnation of Jovinian by the Council of Milan of AD 389 to Pope Siricius, that “it is a savage barking to shew no reverence to virginity, observe no rule of chastity, to seek to place every thing on a level, to abolish the different degrees of merit, and to introduce a certain meagreness in heavenly rewards, as if Christ had only one palm to bestow, and there was no copious diversity in His rewards.”12 St. Augustine, interpreting the words of Christ in John 14:2, writes in his sixty-seventh tractate on the Gospel of John that
the many mansions point to the different grades of merit in that one eternal life. For there is one glory of the sun, another glory of the moon, and another glory of the stars: for one star differs from another star in glory; and so also the resurrection of the dead. The saints, like the stars in the sky, obtain in the kingdom different mansions of diverse degrees of brightness; but on account of that one penny no one is cut off from the kingdom; and God will be all in all in such a way, that, as God is love, love will bring it about that what is possessed by each will be common to all. For in this way every one really possesses it, when he loves to see in another what he has not himself. There will not, therefore, be any envying amid this diversity of brightness, since in all of them will be reigning the unity of love.13
In the same vein, the supplement to part 3 of the Summa Theologiae has St. Thomas Aquinas saying that the mansions referred to by Christ are “degrees of beatitude”14; and in Question 96 of the supplement to part 3, Thomas determines that additional rewards (aureolae or “crowns”) are given to virgins, martyrs, and those who preach or teach. Similarly, while it is important to note that Dante’s Commedia does not properly speak of novissima inasmuch as it represents states of affairs prior to the Last Judgment, the eschatological picture he presents there suggests a significant amount of stratification in the blessed life.
These texts raise a number of questions seemingly not answered in Decreation, among which: is it coherent to think that the beatific life of the saints might be ordered by different grades of merit? How might such differences be represented within Griffiths’ view of heaven—will the metaphors of proximity or orientation that he tends to favor serve for this purpose? Are there particular features of one’s earthly life that we should identify as meriting these crowns? Do virginity, martyrdom, and teaching or preaching mark out particular features of earthly lives that bring with them such rewards, and if so, why are these distinguished from (all?) other features of one’s pre-eschatological career? Are these the only such features of life that merit crowns, as Thomas believes? Are the eschatological lives of angels and nonhuman animals similarly distinguishable in degrees of beatitude? Can Griffiths’ account of the attenuation of self-experience be harmonized with Augustine’s words above, in which it is precisely experiencing the reward of another as “not mine” that allows one to rejoice in it properly? Even were Griffiths to wish to reject this sort of differentiated beatitude, something that would be theologically licit if this tradition is to be understood as speculative rather than properly doctrinal, it is worth noting that other parallel points in Decreation see him taking great care to argue for the strengths of his own position against others rooted deeply in the theological tradition (e.g., hell as everlasting punishment, the general resurrection including the bodies of those to be damned, etc.).
Third and finally, universalism. One of the many delights of reading Decreation is the extended section on plants and animals, precisely because so few texts of systematic theology treat the subject. I found Griffiths’ arguments in favor of the resurrection of nonhuman animals quite interesting, especially the argument found on pages 288–89. Very briefly, Griffiths suggests—following the anthropocentric tendency in theology he outlines at the beginning of this section—that perhaps it is necessary that animals be resurrected in order to “permit the transfiguration of human blood-soaked relations with them, and thus to bring those relations to their proper perfection, a perfection that contributes essentially to the constitution of human creatures as the kind of animal we are.”15 One of the intriguing features of this argument for me was a resonance I detected with an argument F. D. E. Schleiermacher offers in the Glaubenslehre in favor of universalism. In an appendix to his division on “The Consummation of the Church” (his own treatment of last things), Schleiermacher writes,
If we now consider eternal damnation as it is related to eternal bliss, it is easy to see that once the former exists, the latter can exist no longer . . . Now if we attribute to the blessed a knowledge of the state of the damned, it cannot be a knowledge unmixed with sympathy. If the perfecting of our nature is not to move backwards, sympathy must be such as to embrace the whole human race, and when extended to the damned must of necessity be a disturbing element in bliss, all the more that, unlike similar feelings in this life, it is untouched by hope.16
Schleiermacher, of course, argues along very different lines than Griffiths here, suggesting that it is the presence (or even memory) of the damned that would disrupt the beatitude of the blessed, and thus indicating to us that the bonds of affection obtaining between the damned and the blessed will eventually be bring the former to the state of the latter. With only a little tweaking, though, the following (more Griffithsian) picture emerges: our relations with one another are, throughout our lives, characterized by the attempt of each to dominate the other. Each one of our interactions is compromised by our wickedness, and so we find ourselves implicated in a long history of trespasses committed and suffered. Purgation and the resurrection to life, in turn, properly order our loves to God and our neighbor, and bring our relations with one another to their proper perfection. Yet if those we have wronged and who have wronged us have come to nothing, such perfected relations are impossible; it is thus constituent to our beatitude that we enjoy perfect relations with all those we have wronged or who have wronged us throughout our lives. It is a particularly interesting feature of this argument that, just as for nonhuman animals, an individual human’s having reached her desired end of annihilation does nothing to remove the possibility of her resurrection to life—she may be recalled to life even after having come to nothing. And here we see also one of the quirks of our mode of generation (in contradistinction from the angels) come to new significance: because human creatures cannot exist apart from relations of procreation and birth with other human creatures, and because none of them may survive at all without some good or ill being done to them by another human, every human creature that has ever existed has either wronged or been wronged by some other person. The transfiguring of our broken relationships with one another seems to require that all human persons be resurrected to life, thus rendering “the kind of animal we are” an inherently and capaciously social one (or at least, so the argument goes; I follow Griffiths in finding an argument of this form suggestive, while desiring to retain a strong eschatological reserve). If one lesson of the garden of Eden is that we do not sin alone, but with and against one another, perhaps we will be surprised to find that this same fact saves us.
I will follow Griffiths’ convention in naming the God known as Father, Son, and Holy Spirit.↩
For an expanded presentation of Griffiths’ thoughts on theological method, see his recent lecture at the Catholic Theological Society of America, available at http://catholicmoraltheology.com/paul-griffiths-ctsa-plenary-address.↩
Or at least, as many as an Anglican can in good conscience.↩
Decreation, 42–43. We may note that this account is in some tension with Griffiths’ CTSA lecture, where—rather than being identified as one way of doing speculative theological work—interpretation is presented as one of three more-or-less discrete “tasks” of the Catholic theologian, a task separate from and mostly prior to the work of speculation.↩
I follow Griffiths’ translation on p. 208.↩
Decreation, 208.↩
See Letter to the Duke of Norfolk 9.11 (337–38): “These instances out of many similar are sufficient to show what caution is to be observed, on the part of private and unauthorized persons, in imposing upon the consciences of others any interpretation of dogmatic enunciations which is beyond the legitimate sense of the words, inconsistent with the principle that all general rules have exceptions, and unrecognized by the Theological Schola” (http:/C:/dev/home/163979.cloudwaysapps.com/esbfrbwtsm/public_html/syndicatenetwork.com4.newmanreader.org/Works/anglicans/volume2/gladstone/index.html).↩
Nicaea and Its Legacy, 386.↩
Cf. Paul Binski, Medieval Death, and Jacques Le Goff, The Birth of Purgatory.↩
Decreation, 230.↩
Decreation, 217.↩
Ambrose, Epistola 42.2 (unknown translator from the Oxford Movement Library of the Fathers, ed. Roger Pearse, accessed at http:/C:/dev/home/163979.cloudwaysapps.com/esbfrbwtsm/public_html/syndicatenetwork.com4.tertullian.org/fathers/ambrose_letters_05_letters41_50.htm#Letter42); Pope Siricius’ condemnation of Jovinian’s beliefs is recorded in his Epistola 7.↩
Translated by John Gibb (accessed at http:/C:/dev/home/163979.cloudwaysapps.com/esbfrbwtsm/public_html/syndicatenetwork.com4.newadvent.org/fathers/1701067.htm).↩
Summa Theologiae suppl. 3.93.2. See Griffiths’ comments on the supplement to part 3 of the Summa at 276.↩
Decreation, 289.↩
The Christian Faith, 721.↩
11.2.15 |
Response
The Spaces That Stamp Our Souls
A Protestant Appreciation of Paul Griffiths’ Decreation
What I display is one theologian’s attempt to understand and re-present Christian doctrine about the last things, and to speculate on the various things that doctrine might reasonably be taken to mean. This interplay between doctrine and speculation is what makes theology what it is: theologians accept with gratitude and delight what is given, which is doctrine; and then, as a means of returning the gift to its giver, who is Christ the LORD in the person of his beloved spouse, they think and write about what they have been given, freed for the delights of speculation by the acknowledgment of the gift given and received. —Paul Griffiths, Decreation, ix
IN A BOOK PUBLISHED last year, I argued that Paul Griffiths’ theology epitomizes the principle of “ecclesiology preceding epistemology,” that is, the understanding that the principle of “thinking with the church” (sentire cum ecclesia) impacts not only the content of one’s theology but also what Griffiths has repeatedly called the “style” of how theologians think about the topics proper to their task.1 There I had in mind chiefly his major 2009 “grammatical” work Intellectual Appetite: A Theological Grammar, a book which established a dialogue with key passages from Augustine in order to support arguments about the nature of curiosity, intellectual delight, and the pursuit of knowledge that was virtuosic in demonstrating how thinking within the bounds of different modes of Roman Catholic magisterial teaching (including the differing levels of assent to which given teachings might compel the faithful) can be both lyrical and iconoclastic—for instance, in Griffiths’ playful but serious defenses of plagiarism as a mode of Christian authorship.2
Now, with his stunningly beautiful new text Decreation: The Last Things of All Creatures, Griffiths’ virtuosity in parsing the spaces within established Catholic doctrine that invite speculation on the part of the church’s theologians reaches new heights. Leaving aside for the moment the text’s explicit subject matter (a theological proposal concerning the nature of Christian hope for the “last things” of all that exists, from angels to humans to inanimate objects), Griffiths’ book can first be appreciated as a master class in how “ecclesiology preceding epistemology” impacts style of thinking through and through—from engagement with sources to explicit acknowledgment of when a matter falls under speculation rather than settled doctrine. As in past books, Griffiths’ key texts with which to think are magisterial documents (encyclicals, conciliar writings, etc.) as well as interventions from Augustine, Thomas Aquinas, and Pascal. I know of no other Catholic theologian who displays the level of sensitivity towards what is and is not defined within plain readings of magisterial texts as Griffiths, and his exegesis of Augustine and Thomas in particular is most compelling when he demurs from them in significant respects even while respecting their intended fidelity to orthodox teaching.
Also significant about Griffiths’ method in the text is the rigor and elegance of his “lexical” approach. Now, to be sure, there’s nothing particularly unique about a theologian defining one’s terms early on and then remaining consistent in their deployment throughout the remainder of the text; indeed, any good theologian should do just that. Where Griffiths’ technique distinguishes itself is in the author’s sense of how the terms under consideration—e.g., “cosmos,” “devastation,” “flesh,” etc.—take their bearing not from logic first and foremost but rather from narrative: the church offers an account of the world that is more or less consistent in its essentials across period and context, and it is on the basis of that narrative that the speculative theologian can establish a kind of grammar for a given proposal that then governs the logic by which that proposal is unfolded. This approach avoids the periodic conceptual sloppiness which (to be frank) haunts much of what has gone under the banner of “narrative theology” precisely because of the analytic discipline Griffiths is able to bring to bear on the task of unfolding the inner logic (or better, “syntax”) of how the terms intersect.
The book’s signature proposal—that annihilationism is not only an orthodox option for thinking about the nature of hell but is in fact superior to the more common depiction of hell as eternal punishment of enfleshed souls—is a case in point. In order for Griffiths to propose that his speculative proposal of hell as annihilation is ultimately “more beautiful and more fully articulated within the tradition’s deep grammar” (247) than, say, Augustine’s account of hell as eternal torment, he brings to a crescendo themes nascent in the unfolding of his lexicographic from the beginning: that pain is proper to the devastation and not God’s healed cosmos, that depictions of hell as unending enfleshed torment ascribe metronomic time to a sphere where it does not belong, that plain readings of magisterial texts on hell compel assent but not to the account of hell most commonly attributed to them, that rival accounts are equally speculative (if also faithful), etc. It is here, in what might be the text’s most controversial proposal (even though Griffiths is far from alone in his endorsement of annihilationism—indeed, perhaps more noteworthy in the contemporary theological scene is his demurral from unqualified universalism!) that Griffiths’ assertion that carrying out one’s theology within the bounds of established magisterial teaching actually frees the theologian for more daring speculation than might otherwise be the case.
Indeed, at an intriguing moment in the text, Griffiths conceptualizes this freedom in ecclesiological terms that are of particular interest to non-Catholics such as myself who find themselves compelled by Griffiths’ vision:
This picture of the theologian’s work is, or ought to be, productive of speculative work of a daring and radical kind. If it is incumbent upon theologians to get as clear as they can about the difference between church doctrine, on the one hand, and speculative proposals about and elaborations upon that doctrine, on the other hand, then theologians are freed from anxiety about whether their speculative proposals are right. It is not up to them to decide this; whether any element of a particular theologians’ speculative proposal is incorporated into church doctrine is a decision made by the teaching church over time, with the college of bishops playing an essential role in arriving at that decision. In this way, the theologian is relieved of anxiety about her own rightness and her own influence, at least if she is Catholic; the picture is very different for Protestant theologians, on whose shoulders a heavy weight is placed. (42)
I highlight this moment of perceived contrast on Griffiths’ part between Catholic and Protestant theological method because it frames the question with which I would like to conclude this essay: if, as Griffiths suggest, theological proposals regarding last things are important at least in part because they teach us in this life what it might mean for us to order our loves so that we are receiving God’s gift of being shaped for citizenship in the company of saints and not achieving via the “long slog, done alone, by yourself and for yourself” (319) of our own damnation, then the question of the context by which such grace is received and such lives are formed becomes a crucial one not only for speculative theology but also for self-formation (or perhaps the “being formed” of selves).
To elaborate: in the absence of a magisterium of the sort that Griffiths describes and to which Catholic theologians such as himself have recourse, then it is not exactly true that Protestant speculative (or “constructive,” to use the term more native to Protestant theological dialects) theologians have a heavy weight on their shoulders, if the implication is that they somehow are responsible for creating and upholding “paper churches,” to use Newman’s typology. Rather, the agon of the constructive theologian (certainly Protestant, but are Roman Catholics and Orthodox truly exempt?) is the marketplace, the intersection of church, academy, independent publishing outlets, cyberspace, and so on where theological ideas—as much as any—compete with each other for airtime and influence.
Griffiths has written incisively about the marketplace as an agonistic realm for self-formation/de-formation in multiple works;3 and in the manner suggested above and recapitulated in Decreation, it is the space of the church as liturgical and teaching community that serves (not without enfleshed ambiguity within what Griffiths’ terms the “devastation” of fallen existence) as the bulwark against the most pernicious elements of the marketplace’s effect upon body and soul. The church as a space to which our bodies and actions might be “apprenticed” (to use a term from his book Lying) is the place where our bodies are habituated to/by the liturgy such that our souls are moved from preoccupation with the “inner theater” of our experience (which presumably includes the default setting of envisioning ourselves as the perpetual protagonists of our own unique narratives) to gradual acclimation of vision to focus on God. This sort of space, undergirded theologically by magisterial teaching as the authority by which the church opens up space for speculative delight that (at its best) furthers the church’s formation of saints, is what Protestants qua Protestants do not have available to them, at least not in as explicit and robust a configuration.
As a Protestant myself, I find myself wholly uninclined to push back against the outlines of this problematic. I think that the more fruitful route for Protestants appreciative of the call of Griffiths’ vision to consider speculation about the last things to be an aid to the task of ordering our lives and loves in such a way that we allow God’s grace to form us for heaven is rather to take on the challenge on two fronts.
The first would be to follow the ecumenical impulses present in the most ecclesially coherent Protestant bodies (as well as the Roman Catholic Church, outlined especially in John Paul II’s Ut Unum Sint) and recognize, employing Decreation’s terminology, that surely the division of the churches in our time is its own kind of capitulation to the devastation. That is not to say that division itself is sinful or even deleterious without remainder; it may be (and I have argued elsewhere that it is) the most honest and contextually faithful response to the fragmentation of teaching authority characteristic of this present age. But contentment or triumphalism that eschews ecumenism for ecclesial insularity is surely a mistake if the eschatological implications of the church’s role in forming us are as weighty as Griffiths’ text portrays.
The second would be for Protestants to take on the challenge of continuing to identify and limn the spaces of redemptive shaping that the gospel creates within the devastation, and to theologize as well as we can (and indeed inspired by and in collaboration with our Roman Catholic and Orthodox brethren) about how the embodied truth of these spaces shapes us for our novissima in God. I have no way of knowing whether the following tale is true or apocryphal, but I well remember a literature professor of mine, upon the conclusion of our class’ discussion of the William Carlos Williams short story The Use of Force, recounting the story of how admirers would come to visit Williams at his farm towards the end of his life. Occasionally, visitors would find Williams roaming the property with his hands making a series of gestures in the air, seemingly unbeknownst to Williams himself (who was a stroke victim). It was only after his visitors called to mind the fact that, in his lengthy career as a doctor who made house calls near Rutherford, he had reputedly delivered some two thousand babies that they realized that his hands were repeating the gestures of a doctor carrying out a delivery. As his inner theater began to quiet and fail, his flesh bore the vocational formation that had (we might speculate) stamped his soul. No Christian of any stripe should shrink from the task of finding and placing our bodies in the spaces within God’s creation that will so mark our flesh and souls in preparation for the day when the time that kills our bodies is overcome.
Robert C. Saler, Between Magisterium and Marketplace: A Constructive Account of Theology and the Church (Minneapolis: Fortress, 2014).↩
Griffiths, Intellectual Appetite: A Theological Grammar (Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press, 2009).↩
Cf. inter alia, Lying: An Augustinian Theory of Duplicity (Grand Rapids: Brazos, 2004) 226–28; “Reading as a Spiritual Discipline,” in The Scope of Our Art: The Vocation of the Theological Teacher, ed. Gregory L. Jones and Stephanie Paulsell (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 2002), esp. 34ff.; and Griffiths’ review of Charles Taylor’s “A Secular Age,” Thomist 72, no. 4 (October 2008) 668–69.↩
11.4.15 |
Response
Death and Decreation
Tiptoeing (with Paul J. Griffiths) at the Limits of Speculative Theology
La croyance à l’immortalité est nuisible parce qu’il n’est pas en notre pouvoir de nous représenter l’âme comme vraiment incorporelle. Ainsi cette croyance est en fait croyance au prolongement de la vie, et elle ôte l’usage de la mort. —Simone Weil, from the section on “Décréation” in La pesanteur et la grâce (translation to follow)
I AGREED TO RESPOND to Paul’s book, Decreation: The Last Things of All Creatures, before having read a word of it. Although I am far from regretting this decision, now that I have more than just an anticipation of the book’s finely wrought distinctions and exhilarating flights of speculation, I am reminded, somewhat uncomfortably, of the conceit that lies at the heart of this kind of reviewing. I have been paying visits to Decreation, on and off, for maybe a couple of months; Paul has been thinking and refining the thoughts of Decreation for years, likely decades. I feel like someone who has been invited to head directly to a lavish and exquisitely prepared banquet, but the day is Sunday and all the food-markets along the way are closed, except for the Quickie Mart at the filling station, where food and fuel live in unsettling proximity, and so all I have to bring, as a guest offering, is a hastily bought bag of potato chips—and not even the low-in-sodium “guiltless” kind.
I don’t intend to lean heavily on this simile. My aim is not, after all, to relinquish my responsibility for bringing a considered and collegial response to the table and not just a bag of salty chips (or its verbal equivalent). But let’s at least be clear about what the conceit is here. It is not that I have spent the last ten years or so poring over the pages of Decreation (I haven’t, but, in my defense, the book did come out in 2014); no, the real conceit has to do with the utility of my presumptive background knowledge in philosophy and theology. Given all the years, the decades, that I have worked to understand Augustine’s theological vision and its invitation to my sometimes spiritless philosophy, surely I must have deep thoughts about last things. For if Augustine is not a profoundly eschatological thinker, who is? But I can assure you (if assurance is the appropriate notion here) that I do not have deep thoughts to share about last things, that I barely know how to think about them at all, even superficially, and that this is due neither to a lapse on Augustine’s part nor to my lamentable inattention to his insights. It is not for trivial or accidental reasons that I find myself so inarticulate here. The inarticulacy comes with the territory.
When Paul wants to refer most generally to a last thing, he prefers the Latin, novissimum, to the Greek term it normally translates, eschaton. As the superlative form of novum, “a new thing,” a novissimum is a thing in its newest condition. While newness often connotes flourishing, as in a renewal or a rebirth, here the meaning is more restricted and exact: a novissimum is a being that is in its last or final state, a condition, whether good or bad, that admits of no further novelty. In its properly restricted sense, a novissimum is indeed an eschaton, “a last or final thing.” Paul avoids using that term, not because eschaton fails to denote a last thing, but because of its placement within the history of eschatological thinking, where the concern has been as much with signs of last things, the omens that portend a final reckoning, as with the things themselves. (Given that take on the history, Augustine isn’t a very committed eschatologist.) Paul’s steady focus throughout Decreation is on what the last things are, differentiated according to kind: angels, humans, plants, animals, and inanimate creatures. For the sake of a manageable engagement with his efforts, I will restrict my attention for the most part to the human case. Human beings, made in the image and likeness of God, admit of two possible ends: the inglorious end of utter separation from the Creator, irreversible and without hope of amelioration (hell), and the glorious end of unending and perfected loving communion, free of the faintest specter of sin (heaven).
Neither of these ends lies in plain view. And so what are we to imagine? Paul rejects the notion that hell, as a last thing, is a condition of torment and torture, of excruciation without the withering away of flesh. Rather than being a place of punishment, where sinners forever elicit divine anger, hell, he speculates, is merely the resolution of sin’s project of loving nothing and being rid of the affections that make for a creaturely identity. The last thing here, that of annihilation, is not a condition to be suffered. There is no one to suffer it, and nothing to picture. So leave your Dante at home. The inferno isn’t even a ghost yard. Meanwhile, matters are no more imaginable at the other extreme of the spectrum of being, where reincarnate souls join unfallen angels in an endlessly repetitive, but necessarily never boring, liturgy of praise and thanksgiving. “Immortal flesh,” Paul cautions (164–65), “is strictly unimaginable for us: we have and can have no imaginative grasp of what immortal flesh might be like, for all our experience of flesh, ours and that of others, is deeply inflected with movement towards death.”
The speculative daring of Decreation, which invites its readers to venture conceptually into the timespace of discarnate and alternatively fleshed beings, depends surprisingly little on leaps of the imagination. Its driving force is that of a judiciously articulated theological grammar, one that ideally extends the form of theological thinking well beyond the limits of material content. So while we may not be able to say, content-wise, what it is like to have immortal flesh (we simply have no feel for it), we can say, form-wise, that immortal flesh does not age, sicken, or come with the need to consume food and eliminate waste. The grammar that allows us a formal extension to our thinking, even into the exotica of last things, consists most basically, Paul reminds us (1), of a set of clearly defined concepts (a lexicon) and principled ways to arrange these concepts to form greater units of intelligibility (a syntax). In practice, the lexical and syntactical features of a living grammar tend to bleed into one another. The grammar that Paul uses to elaborate Christian doctrine about the last things is living, and, as such, it cannot without violence be wholly abstracted from the dialectical practices of those who use the grammar, mostly implicitly, to share a form of life. Even if I had all the time in the world, I could not put Paul’s theological grammar on full display; it is not the plaything of argument, and it is not, by any stretch of the imagination, just Paul’s. On the other hand, there is nothing wrong and, one hopes, something even a bit salutary about a grammatical self-consciousness that remains open to the unscripted possibilities of the Word.
In the spirit of that hope, here are a few of the lexical stars in Decreation’s firmament, along with a nod toward their syntactical complexity. Begin with God. Paul prefers the name LORD (caps are important here), to the quasi-name, quasi-kind “God,” rightly decapitalized. The LORD is the triune name of the god of Abraham, Isaac, Jacob, Mary, and Jesus, but with this syntactical stipulation: the LORD is not the god of gods, not the surpassingly best member of a class of divine beings, all of whom, it turns out, are merely creatures. The LORD, not being a creature, is not a kind of anything, not a kind of god, not even a kind of being who is not a kind of being. (The grammatical acrobatics called for here are just dizzying; cf. Aquinas.)
Then there is the ensemble of all the creatures, whose adorned totality Paul refers to as “cosmos,” a thing of beauty. This ensemble, taken together with its Creator, is all there is to what there is. And yet there is also the “world” or, more descriptively, the “devastation”; Paul uses either of these terms to designate the sin-devastated cosmos, still harboring traces of its original beauty, but for the most part being what it appears to be (4): “a charnel house, saturated in blood violently shed; an ensemble of inanimate creatures decaying toward extinction; a theater of vice and cruelty.” If the conjunction of Creator and cosmos is already exhaustive of what is, then the world adds nothing further to the picture; evil is emphatically not a new form of being. But it surely looks as if something has been removed from the picture, once sin, the double artifact of angelic and human perversity, has done its devastating work.
Paul, I don’t think, would put it this way, but I will. The world, when set in cosmic context, where it seems so diminished, exposes the imperfection in the original creation, or better, our conception of it. I refer, of course, to the awful vulnerability of the cosmos to the irrational preference of some penultimate beings (bad angels, delinquent adams) for nothingness. It’s as if creation ex nihilo doesn’t quite take in the whole of creation, at least not at first. And so while “heaven” in the lexicon of last things is certainly, as Paul defines it, a permanent restoration, in that something diseased gets definitively healed, it is also, and more fundamentally, as Paul would not be inclined to define it, the original perfection itself, thanks to a final novelty. There are now only last things. In the timespace of heaven, the penultimate agents who once rendered time into such a dicey proposition will have either perfected their sin and absented themselves from the scene, or they will have been given the grace to see through nothingness and become one with their love of God.
That is enough of a gesture, I trust, toward the richness and complexity of Paul’s lexical choices. I now want to focus on one of his lexical omissions, for it will prove to be the hole into which my hopes for thinking clearly about last things are finally sunk. Paul entitles his speculation about last things Decreation, and so I am inclined to assume that the concept of decreation is important in some way to his efforts. But on no page of Decreation will you find a working definition of what decreation means. Its omission from the book’s lexicon is, in one respect, quite understandable. Paul writes self-consciously as a Catholic theologian, and the term “decreation” is hardly a common Catholic term of art. When I first came upon it, in Simone Weil’s Gravity and Grace, I had to suppress an internal cringe (ugly term!) before I could get much out of Weil’s distinction, central to her style of theological speculation, between decreation and destruction, “a culpable substitute.” Although the OED informs me that decreation has a fourteenth-century French provenance and basically means annihilation, I assumed that Paul was drawing his title from the depths of Weil’s inspiration and not from late medieval anxieties about death and damnation. In a short email exchange between the two of us, he reminded me that he had used a quotation from Weil, left in the original French, to adorn the frontispiece of his book. It is a passage that describes two ways of construing the presence of God: there is the unimpeded ingress of divine presence into the entire being of each and every created thing, and there is the mysteriously cooperative venture between creative spirit and human will, undertaken for the sake of redemption. “The first presence,” writes Weil, “is the presence of creation; the second is that of decreation.” She rounds off that arresting thought with a citation, more or less a quote, from Augustine (s. 169.13): “The one who has created us without us will not save us without us.”
In the pocket edition that I have of La pesanteur et la grâce, the passage that Paul quotes appears as the second paragraph of a single aphorism. The opening paragraph is what I have quoted in full at the beginning of my response. Here it is again, in Emma Craufurd’s sturdy English translation:
Belief in immorality is harmful because it is not in our power to conceive of the soul as really incorporeal. So this belief is in fact a belief in the prolongation of life, and it robs death of its purpose.
My only hesitation about Craufurd’s translation is her decision to translate ôte l’usage de la mort as “robs death of its purpose,” a choice that effectively veils the presence of usage in the original. For Weil, “use” has a life as a theological term of art. If the thing to be used is sin—or in this case, a death that is inextricably bound to sin—then no good will come of a solo human usage, but only further corruption; it is God alone, the LORD, who can make good use of evil and, in so doing, fold creaturely perversity wholly within the nothingness that it seeks.
If we put the two parts of Weil’s aphorism together, it seems to me that she is suggesting something like this: we cling desperately to the selves that we imagine ourselves to be and thus hate death, the great solvent; when we indulge the thought, in the teeth of this hate, that some part of us never dies, some ghostly but still corporeal self-image, we omit ourselves from the usage of death that God offers us: a means of release from a faithless imagination. The ego that sin cobbles together from the wastelands of fear and disaffection is less an illusion, or something wholly imagined, than matter for sacrifice. Such a sacrifice, when rendered acceptable to God, is the decreation to which Weil refers, and it never takes place other than in the divine presence and so deep within the connective tissue of being. Another word for decreation is forgiveness.
In book 12 of the Confessions—a book I have only recently really begun to appreciate—Augustine struggles to extend his imagination into the conceptual space that a well-formed theological grammar has been opening for him. I mean in particular the grammar of creation itself, keyed to the doctrine of God as creator ex nihilo. The surface grammar of this doctrine invites us to think of nothingness, the nihilum, as having a quasi-material content; it is the pseudo-stuff out of which God shapes a form of being that is not-God and not-nothing, but something inconceivably in-between. The depth grammar encourages us to resist this tempting reduction of matter to nothingness and to retain form and content as equally essential elements of a timelessly creative act. When Augustine struggles not to subsume matter under form and finds himself clinging precariously to halfway-house notions, like that of a “nothing something” (nihil aliquid) or a “not-being kind of be” (est non est), he has, in effect, begun to breach the depths (conf. 12.6.6). The purest form of matter, forever uninformed, Augustine will come to think of as mutability itself (mutabilitas)—a fundamental capacity for change, to be sure, but more tellingly, a receptivity to what is different. Augustine is prepared to find mutabilitas in the caelum caeli itself, the heaven of heaven, or what Paul simply calls heaven, but that magnificent last thing, Augustine insists, “will at no time or place live out its mutability” (conf. 12.11.12). Or, in Paul’s language, life in heaven is repetitively static.
I confess that for many years this picture of perpetual peace, the peace of heaven, has seemed grossly unappealing to me. For what is a capacity for change that is forever contained if not evidence of a profoundly tyrannical will, locking essentially mutable beings into an alien perfection? The problem here, of course, is not that God is actually a tyrant, but that I have trouble thinking of power other than as an imposition of some sort. That makes for a debased mutability. Matters don’t improve for me until I start to notice that mutabilitas, in its pure offering, appears elsewhere in the Confessions, and in a less speculative context.
In book 7 of the Confessions, we meet up with a dispirited Augustine. It has been about a year since he sent his partner, the mother of their son, back to Africa. His own mother, Monnica, is living with him in Milan, and she has helped him make arrangements for a socially advantageous marriage. But the girl is too young to marry right away, and he is not terribly sure, in any case, whether he still cares all that much about social advantage. In the meantime he takes another woman to his bed, left nameless in his confession, and wonders how it can be that a world under divine lordship is such an evil and dispirited place. His spiritual mentors, Bishop Ambrose and the old priest, Simplician, have been telling him that evil has its source in free will (liberum arbitrium), but he can do nothing with that admonition; if God’s will is truly sovereign, why would any creature have the freedom to defy it? Dear God, please explain yourself. It is with an imagination for power drearily similar to my own—an eye for imposition, for forced conformity—that Augustine enters his inner depths, feels the light of love claim him there, and then is abruptly taken up by God into an unlikely place (conf. 7.10.16): “You took me up that I might see that what I was seeing was real, and that I, who was doing the seeing, was real not yet.”
What Augustine sees, from his unlikely place of being “not yet” (nondum), is something akin to the caelum caeli, that of a perfectly ordered world, exquisitely lovely, but, more importantly, impervious to all the ugly impositions that would set it on a path toward becoming “a charnel house.” It would seem that the mutability of this world is well constrained to fit a preordained pattern of perfection, except for one detail: Augustine is one of the unrealized possibilities of this world, and he has been invited, through a strange folding of temporal perspective, to become real and make a difference. When Ambrose and Simplician tell him that evil is sin, a willful turning away from God, he cannot take in the love of that admonition because he is already, at the core of his self-awareness, the person who sins. When he has this view of evil confirmed for him, but from a perspective that is divinely disjointed, he is not yet the person he imagines himself to be, but a lover of God (conf. 7.17.23):
It was a marvel to me that I loved you already and not some phantom in your stead. But I was not stable in my enjoyment; I was caught up by your beauty and just as soon torn away from you by my weight. I crashed with a groan into lesser things. That weight: it was my habit for flesh.
Forgiveness may first announce itself as the ecstatic release from a burdensome persona, but it requires, for its unfolding, a reeducation of habit: “Put on Jesus Christ, the LORD, and don’t look to lusts to care for your flesh” (conf. 8.12.29; Rom 13:14). The path here is as much a reckoning with losses as it is a labor of new life.
As a gesture toward the timespace of last things, Paul, taking his cue from St. Paul (1 Cor 7:29), speaks of systolic time, or time that regularly contracts, like a heart, to release life-giving love. The antithesis of systolic time is what Paul calls the time of the metronome: the regularity here, dismally measurable, punctuates the movement of a broken-hearted cosmos toward decay, dissolution, and death. But as I have been trying to say, in so many words, I cannot wrap my head—or my heart—around this kind of contrast (perhaps my imagination is just too corrupt). I need the reminder from metronomic time, not so much that time is measurable (ultimately it is not), but that time, being mortgaged to the no longer and the not yet, is a tendency, my tendency, everything’s tendency, not to exist. And in as much as I have a sense of the time that folds back upon itself and contracts, like a crouched heart, I am moved, like Augustine before me, to abandon my bad-faith perfectionism about last things and return to the rough ground of forgiveness, where a tendency not to exist is not always such a bad thing.
10.26.15 | Holly Taylor Coolman
Response
To Love God with One’s Mind
OF THE SEVERAL EXCELLENCES displayed in Paul Griffith’s Decreation, none is more salutary than his unapologetic, thoroughly unfashionable embrace of speculative theology. Given the emphases of the present moment—on praxis, on “practices,” on theology’s concrete contexts and its indispensably political implications, on its fundamental rootedness in liturgy and its relationship to the care of souls—some have unfortunately concluded that speculation is entirely unnecessary or even vicious. But this is not so. Griffiths’ work in this volume reminds readers that, although theological reflection arises out of and returns to a world of action, and although it ultimately relates us as whole persons both to God and to one another, it also remains indispensably a work of the intellect. At the same time, this book demonstrates the patience and care that work of this kind requires. Ideas can be tricky, and they require a steady hand. Speculation done well does not hurry to its conclusion, but works carefully and well, and relishes ironing out the small wrinkles tucked away in the corners.
Decreation does all this in a way that is unmistakably characteristic of Griffiths. The argument proceeds on the basis of careful definitions, it displays careful logic and, at the same time, it hints at enormous swaths of logical deduction that precede and stand behind the writing. It is idiosyncratic in its concerns, moving in directions that are neither easy to predict nor simple to engage. Time is “pleated,” Griffiths argues. Angels, he insists, although they are not composed of matter, do have mass. This tendency, too, though, is a strength of the work. Precisely in its display of Giffithsian quiddity, Decreation makes its contribution. Claims such as those mentioned can, after all, prevent theological reflection growing stale, as it does when theologians simply rehash familiar positions in familiar arguments. It can serve especially well to spark that venerable and valuable form of theologizing, disputation.
The topic Griffiths considers here—the “last things” of various creatures—is also welcome. There is much to consider, in part because this topic depends so heavily on speculation, and thus is likewise unfashionable. Although eschatology has come to play an important role as a sort of limit concept in theology over the last several decades, this sort of direct consideration of the final states of various creatures is virtually unknown in the present theological scene.
To do this sort of speculative work on the last things is, of course, no easy task. It involves not only the challenges inherent in speculation itself, but also particular limitations related to the topic. Griffiths himself invokes briefly the term “apocalypse” in connection with last things, and that term captures the difficulty well. The transition from this world to the next, as it is described in the Christian tradition, can be imagined as the lifting of a veil. There is also a real form of hiddenness at work. Theological work in this present age is separated from those final realities by more than time.
Given this reality, Griffiths makes the choice to root his eschatological speculation, above all, in the phenomena the church has long understood to be a true foretaste of heaven: the eucharistic liturgy and the liturgical life that it fosters. On this basis, in fact, he arrives at his largest claim concerning the final end of human beings. Having considered three possible ends for creatures—annihilation, stasis, and repetitive stasis—he argues that the third of these is the form of liturgical time, and so it is the best characterization of the ideal state in which human creatures will come to rest.
I take this rooting in the liturgy to be a wise and fruitful choice. It is, however, in the extrapolation from liturgy in this age to the life of the world to come that additional questions arise. Griffiths himself notes that speculating on a reality beyond the veil is tricky, and that it involves “ticklish decisions.” Two of the claims of Decreation, in particular, strike me as ones requiring further investigation.
The first has to do with the treatment of the ancient doctrine of epektasis. A relatively simple argument is deployed here. The whole of Decreation is based on a central decision to treat last things under the conventional category of novissimis, which means both the “very last” and hence the “most recent” or the “newest.” If an entity arrives at its novissima, then, it has come to the end of novelty; nothing further and thus newer is possible.” To be a creature, Griffiths says, is necessarily to have an end of this kind. Epektasis, on the other hand, elaborated especially in the thought of Gregory of Nyssa, describes humanity’s heavenly state as constituted precisely by eternal progress in godliness. As Griffiths argues it, the category of novissimis allows no room, by definition, for this possibility. Several questions could be raised in response to this argument, but I focus here on just one: does liturgy in this life not suggest otherwise?
Repetitive stasis describes well the nature of the liturgy if liturgy is considered apart from any human subjects who are actually performing it. If we are to ask, though, how liturgy reveals the end of human creatures, it is not clear that considering it in this way is helpful. In fact, as we reflect on the participation of human subjects in liturgy in this life, we see that growth in holiness is integral to liturgy’s ideal. In the structure of the liturgy’s repetition, both individual Christians and Christian communities are ideally moved forward, to greater love of God and one another. Drawing near to God in worship shapes the subjects who do so. Perhaps this subjective reality integral to liturgy teaches us something indispensable. Perhaps progress of this kind is actually an intrinsic feature of the dynamic that takes place whenever human creatures draw near to God. Perhaps progress of this kind only intensifies as they draw nearer.
A second point deserves some comment, and perhaps only makes clearer what is at stake in this first point. Griffiths proposes that we consider human experience under the philosophical category of qualia, or mental impressions. A sense of one’s own experiences or one’s own “layered qualia,” which Griffiths calls the “inner theater,” is, he argues, slowly erased by the habit of liturgical practice. In fact, he says “the proper end of the liturgical life . . . is the radical attenuation of experience.” Our multiple experiences, he argues, are not only “not us”; they are, in fact, “an artifact of the fall.” In the end, Griffiths argues that, while our true selves certainly do persist in heaven, nevertheless, “the sense we have of who we are . . . is no part of what we will be” (italics added).
It is not hard to see how participation in the regular rhythms of liturgy involves precisely being taken up into something larger than oneself. In relation to the “inner theater,” it can indeed prompt a salutary form of self-forgetfulness. If we are to make liturgy our touchstone, though, there are also ways in which we might best describe personal experience not as erased, but as remade.
In light of claims such as St. Paul’s in Colossians 1:24—“I rejoice in my sufferings for your sake, and in my flesh I am filling up what is lacking in the afflictions of Christ on behalf of his body, which is the church”—Catholic theology teaches that our sufferings are actually joined to Christ’s sufferings. The Catechism describes concisely the possibility that “suffering . . . becomes a participation in the saving work of Jesus.” The Eucharistic liturgy, the Holy Sacrifice of the Mass, in particular invites participants to unite their own individual sufferings to the one sacrifice of Christ. But what are these individual sufferings if not qualia? And in this union with Christ, are they not being drawn into the great drama of the liturgy in just such a way that they do not thereby simply cease to be our own?
We might also think of the litanies of the saints so central to liturgy. Surely we ask the intercession of these saints in such a way that we recall the specific qualia of their lives. The intercession of St. Peter is not undifferentiated, but is the intercession of the one who knew Jesus and betrayed him and went to Rome to die. The intercession of holy father Francis is the intercession of one who kissed the wounds of lepers. But why would the liturgy foster our awareness of particular saints in this way? Perhaps Griffiths will grant that in heaven we will have awareness of others’ experiences as connected to them, although he denies that we will have awareness of our own experiences as connected to ourselves. But again, why should this be? Would we not rather say that to be holy would allow just the same sort of joyful awareness of our own sainthood, in all its particularity, as we have of others?
It seems that me that what the liturgy instead teaches is that, in patria, layered qualia and the way they contribute to “the sense we have of who we are” are not simply erased. Rather, like physical wounds, qualia are healed. The martyrs, we could say, do “possess” their scars for all eternity, in a new way, as “possessions” remade and grafted into the eternal worship of God. They are golden crowns that “belong” to their owners precisely as, and so that, they can be continually cast before the throne.
Griffiths is rightly concerned to set aside a poverty-stricken notion of the self as “inner theater,” an account of the self as founded on—perhaps consisting entirely of—the gradual accumulation of layered qualia. The logic of liturgy, however, would encourage not a setting aside of any subjective element, not a “decreation” of the self, but rather would suggest a process by which those who lose their lives in fact find them.
All this, I would argue, has implications for the method of speculation, which can foreshadow for us just this reality. Speculative theology, as it leads theologians in contemplation of that which exceeds them, fosters a beautiful form of self-forgetfulness. On the other hand, the theologian loves God with his own mind. When all things are made new, why should the theologian not find himself rejoicing in the quiddity of his own particular doxological contribution as much as anyone else?
10.26.15 | Paul Griffiths
Reply
Requiescam in pace
Introduction
I’m grateful to Syndicate for putting this symposium together, and of course especially grateful to those who took the time and trouble to comment on Decreation. I’ve not done justice to what they’ve written, but perhaps my responses can serve as stimulus for further discussion.
It’s interesting to me that my discussion in Decreation of the attenuation of experience by way of the liturgy has prompted the most response, and that more than one of my commentators has perceived and (critically) noted the connection of that thesis with my rejection of an epektatic view of heaven (and hell). I’m not convinced that I’m wrong about either of these matters, but rightness or wrongness is hardly what matters in these discussions. What does matter is the efficacy of the verbal exchange in prompting patterns of thought and writing that otherwise wouldn’t be engaged in. That’s happened for me here, and I’m pleased that it has.
Response to Coolman
Holly Taylor Coolman has some kind things to say about Decreation, and I’m grateful for them. The issues she singles out for critical engagement are important, and she describes both them and my position on them accurately, so I’m grateful to her for that, as well. I’ll make a few comments in response, about one of the issues only—the question of epektasy—in the hope that we can have further exchange about it. The question of experience, the other topic Coolman raises, is intimate with this one, but I won’t address it in these comments.
Coolman and I are at one, I think, on the definitional question. If the epektatic view of heaven (and perhaps also of hell) is right—the view, that is, that heaven, for those fortunate enough to get there, is best understood as forward movement without terminus—then this just means that there is no last thing for any inhabitant of heaven. That’s because there’s always something new, heaven-without-end, and, therefore, no end (terminus, last thing) to any of it. To defend epektasy in this sense is to deny the position taken by the vast majority of Christian theologians who’ve thought about eschatology, which is exactly that creatures do have last things.
We differ, then, about whether epektasy should be affirmed, not about what it means. Coolman likes novelty, and thinks there’ll always be more of it for the saved. I find novelty exhausting, and the prospect of endlessly more of it a crushing weight. What I’d like from and in heaven is rest and peace, the delight of seeing the LORD in company with the assembly of the saved. There’s a difference in intuition here which might repay further thought. Is it just a matter of temperament? Is it that some people are so ordered that the prospect of novelty delights them, while for others it feels like a curse? And must the matter be left there? If it must, I’m with Augustine: what I want is to rest in the LORD.
But perhaps there’s more to say. Coolman suggests that the liturgy as we practice it here below in the devastation isn’t simply a matter of repetitive stasis; rather, it brings about movement and progress, an increase in the holiness of those who engage in it. Or at least it may. That’s right, I think. But I don’t see that much follows from this. The need for growth in holiness is surely itself an artifact of the fall—what else could it be? All lacks are such artifacts, and the lack of holiness is paradigmatically so. If heaven provides the remedy for what has been wrought by the fall, then among the things it remedies must be any need for increase in holiness. I’m more impressed than Coolman is by the deep structure of the liturgy, which, as it seems to me, signals again and again its repetitively static nature. She agrees about this “if liturgy is considered apart from any human subjects who are actually performing it.” But if the liturgy is the best anticipation we have here in the devastation of what heaven is and is like, then perhaps we ought to take these signals more seriously than Coolman does—and not only about the liturgy as such, but also about our nature as liturgical agents, even here in the devastation.