Repetition and Identity
By
2.2.15 |
Symposium Introduction
To be is to be repeated. This is Catherine Pickstock’s central assertion in Repetition and Identity. Paradoxically, identity, individuality, distinctiveness, and so on are secured not through absolute singularity but through “non-identical repetition.” In Pickstock’s words, “A thing or res . . . is constituted through non-identical repetition through time” (29). For anything to be recognizable to us, it requires continuity with other things, with past and future instantiations of a similar sort. The whole process of identification—that is, the whole enterprise of getting by in the world on a daily basis—depends upon familiarity, but also upon variation.
In exploring this common philosophical theme, Pickstock intentionally takes up Kierkegaard’s challenge, in his novella Repetition, “to develop simultaneously an ontology and theology of repetition” (xi). She concludes that “repetition” is an “equally ontologically primordial category” as res, that it is in “the basic ontological or reological category” (11). Claiming that “reology”—or “the study of things”—“is more fundamental than ontology” (14), Pickstock’s understanding of the thingness of things is extended not only to concrete, inanimate objects but also to language, time, human subjectivity (“the human thing”), and God (“the supreme thing”) (86, 12).
Pickstock implicitly situates her account of repetition over against two primary alternatives. On the one hand, she wishes to rule out the “mass identical repetition” or “mechanical reproduction” that seems to mark the modern condition (41). As so many dystopic novelists portray it, “modern life” has become “comprehensively bureaucratic, technologized, and capitalized,” such that humans are “docketed, tracked, timedtabled” and finally “substitutable for everyone else in the manner of capitalist wage slaves or communist cadres” (88). Henri Bergson refers to this sort of “merely identical repetition” as “the enemy of things”—and, indeed, of humanity (41). It is here that Pickstock’s account is particularly compelling, in her insightful phenomenological counterexamples of the “repetition-with-variation” of houses, waves, skeletons, people, and so on (23). While these descriptions are all offered on the way to a certain Christian-Platonist metaphysics, it is clear that Pickstock has no interest in the sort of spirit-matter binary that would render us inattentive to the beauty and manifold variegations of material reality.
On the other hand, Pickstock is persistently dissatisfied with postmodern versions of non-identical repetition. In contrast to an “immanentist” alternative—which she associates with Jacques Derrida, Gilles Deleuze, and certain strains of phenomenology—Pickstock insists that transcendence is essential to material integrity and distinctiveness (61-62). She maintains that the intelligibility of every res depends upon a stable “exemplar” that is “transcendent” (33). Referring of course to Plato’s doctrine of Forms as well as a Christian doctrine of divine ideas, she says, “the secure identity of a thing is curiously transcendent to itself, an identity in which the material thing itself only participates” (63). Thus regarding things as “signs” (47), Pickstock circles toward an analogical—and finally: incarnational—account of sense and reference that grounds the identity and distinctiveness of everything in the fullness of God.
This arc will not be surprising to Pickstock’s readers or to anyone familiar with the metaphysical vision of “Radical Orthodoxy,” a contemporary movement in philosophy and theology with which she is associated. Reiterating many themes prominent in her other writings, throughout the book Pickstock synthesizes Plato and Aquinas while taking aim at a host of “secular” and “modern” philosophical positions including, among others, nominalism, realism, Saussurean semiotics, and poststructuralism. But what makes Repetition and Identity interesting is that it is offered as a challenge not simply to theology and philosophy “without metaphysics,” but also to daily life without metaphysics. As Pickstock says, “To live is to construct an ontology” (2). Even the most mundane tasks depend upon the recognizability of things, and this is the basic experience for which she attempts to account in this work.
As the four scholars who engage Pickstock in this symposium each note in different ways, Repetition and Identity is a profoundly recursive text. The prose enacts the “serpentine line” of every res that Pickstock describes (32). Engaging an impressively expansive range of interlocutors, her thought winds across the canons of Western philosophy, theology, and literature—sometimes in a single paragraph. The reader may deem this dense circuitousness a “line of beauty,” to use William Hogarth’s phrase (30). Or perhaps it will be judged a “difficult stylistic performance,” as it is by one contributor, the “opacity” of which finally obscures the point. Either way, it is clear that its content has incited strong responses all around.
Aaron Simmons, writing from the field of postmodern philosophy of religion, explores the ontological and epistemological implications of Kierkegaard’s account of repetition through the ordinary example of the kiss. In so doing, he invites Pickstock to respond to a number of pressing questions related to both the style and the argument of the book. Silas Morgan’s primary research interests include critical theory and continental philosophy. His contribution inquires into the political implications of understanding subjectivity in terms of repetition. He wants to be sure any understanding of time and subjectivity (and therefore history and society) as repetition does not foreclose on “the New,” the genuine “political Act.” Margret Adam’s response is more theologically focused. She highlights the centrality of the incarnation for Pickstock’s theory of the existing thing. But detecting a tone of triumphalism, Adam expresses concern that the absolute assurance of continuity in the Christological patterning of being and time does not do justice to experiences of complete rupture, for example horrific violence and death. Jeffery Hanson’s main areas of expertise include philosophy of religion, contemporary continental philosophy, French phenomenology, and Kierkegaard. Hanson lauds a number of Pickstock’s comments on Kierkegaard as “perspicacious” and “expert.” However, at other points he offers a somewhat different reading of Kierkegaard, particularly when it comes to identity and contradiction as well as the relationship between “nature” and “spirit.” Together, these responses mirror the surprising breadth of subjects traversed in this short book.
About the Author
Catherine Pickstock is the author of After Writing: on the liturgical consummation of philosophy, and several other books and articles in philosophical theology. She is a University Reader in Philosophy and Theology at the University of Cambridge, and is a Fellow of Emmanuel College, Cambridge.
2.4.15 |
Response
Shattered and Continually Reborn Anew
My response to Catherine Pickstock’s stimulating Repetition and Identity will trace the following trajectory: I wish to ask whether, and if so in what sense, the Kierkegaardian repeated self of which she speaks so powerfully in her fifth chapter is a question of identity at all; whether the emergence of the self or spirit from nature in Kierkegaard’s way of thinking is a matter of smooth transition or transcendent leap that establishes a complex discontinuity with non-human things; whether more ought to be said about the possibility of a negative, spectral, and spectatorial shadowing of the self that represents the worst of the aesthetic person and his (and I use the male pronoun advisedly) persistence even within ethical selfhood; and finally whether more ought to be said about the unique power of the religious to redemptively repeat the aesthetic within the ethical and thus banish the spectral and spectatorial shadow-side of the aesthetic while reconciling the ideal and real, fiction and history, in a consummate realization of Pickstock’s aims. Much of what I have to say I believe furthers rather than hinders those aims.
I begin with a remarkable quote from Johannes Climacus in his Concluding Unscientific Postscript: “That the law of identity is in a certain sense superior in that the law of contradiction presupposes it is not difficult to see. But the law of identity is only the boundary; it is like the blue mountains, or the line which the artist calls the base line, the drawing being the important thing. Identity is therefore a lower view than contradiction, which is more concrete. Identity is the terminus a quo for existence but not ad quem. An existing person can maxime arrive at identity, and keep on arriving at it by abstracting from existence. . . . Instead of saying the law of identity annuls the law of contradiction, it is contradiction that annuls identity.”1
Climacus thus concedes that the law of identity is in an obvious sense presupposed by the law of contradiction; there can be no contradiction without identity, that is, there can be no consciousness without the selfsameness of the self that is conscious.2 But Climacus argues further that while identity is presupposed by contradiction, it is nevertheless not the main issue for an actually existing person; it is only the base line for the drawing. So in a more important sense, identity is a “lower view,” an abstraction compared to the concretion of contradiction. This is why Climacus says identity is a terminus a quo for existence but not a terminus a quem, that is, identity is a departure point, not a destination. For the actually existing person then, as consciousness develops it departs from at least a trivial self-coincident sense of identity, not toward it.
Now this conception may be very close to what Pickstock means by identity, a sort of identity in differentiation or identity composed on the back of repetition. But Climacus seems to argue that identity is at best presupposed by selfhood, which moves away from its trivial sense, toward contradiction, which the text Johannes Climacus3 argues is definitive of consciousness as such.4 Lurking behind these observations is Claude Romano’s argument that “selfhood is not a form of identity.”5 As Romano has further argued, there persists in the French tradition from Descartes through Levinas to Ricoeur an unwarranted assumption that identity is tantamount to immutability6; in my view this unwarranted assumption has in turn provoked a number of unnecessary “workarounds” the Cartesian problem of the self. Pickstock does not fall victim to this mischaracterization fortunately, but the question remains why in view of Kierkegaard’s discussions of the self in Concluding Unscientific Postscript, The Sickness unto Death, Johannes Climacus, The Concept of Anxiety, and yes, Repetition, none of which seem to depend heavily on the category of identity (nor require a forced “workaround” the Cartesian pitfall) but instead on contradiction, relation, and repetition, she remains loyal to the language of identity at all.
Part of the explanation is presumably her vision of the kinship between the self “thing” and all other things, but the question is still more urgent in view of the issue of how the human spirit emerges from its likeness to other things. Pickstock implies at various points that this happens in a continuum with the whole world of things. She approvingly cites for instance Hans Jonas (19, 82), and she claims forthrightly in chapter 2 that “The mark of the strength of a thing as an engrained habitude would be its spontaneity and adaptability, since a strong disposition is not merely fixed and stubborn but capable of originality and improvisation. This observed truth concerning human beings can be extended to ontology or reology because it has been concluded that the perdurance of a thing consists in its non-identical repeatability, and so in a certain style that can persist through different and unpredictable variations.”
I note in passing that the first sentence bespeaks a fascinating observation about human disposition that is thoroughly Kierkegaardian. This capacity for originality within stability is what Kierkegaard calls earnestness. From The Concept of Anxiety: “When the originality in earnestness is acquired and preserved, then there is succession and repetition . . . The earnest person is earnest precisely through the originality with which he returns in repetition.”7 Earnestness in Kierkegaard’s account is neither routine habit nor stale pedantry nor waxing and waning enthusiasm; it is the disposition that allows the self to take up again and again its tasks day after day with freshness and originality each time.
This point, I think, strengthens much of what Pickstock wants to say about the anchoring of the fictive upon the historical (with which The Concept of Anxiety is also deeply concerned, though readers rarely notice this). It is also worth observing that Kierkegaard’s example of earnestness is drawn from the liturgy: “To make everything as concrete as possible, I shall use an example. Every Sunday, a clergyman must recite the prescribed common prayer, and every Sunday he baptizes several children. Now let him be enthusiastic etc. The fire burns out, he will stir and move people etc., but at one time more and at another time less. Earnestness alone is capable of returning regularly every Sunday with the same originality to the same thing.”8 Pickstock of course has had much to say about liturgy, but here it would be useful to return to the subject, especially if as I suspect the liturgical is for Kierkegaard the necessary synchronic complement to the diachrony of history, whether we are speaking of the individual or of the race (which, after all, are both contained in every individual according to The Concept of Anxiety).9
The second sentence I quoted from Pickstock however seems more problematic, as it poses an isomorphism between the self and non-human things. Part of my concern here stems directly from Kierkegaard’s own words in response to the ill-conceived review of Repetition penned by J. L. Heiberg. Kierkegaard’s unpublished reply to Heiberg attacks him precisely on the grounds that he assigns repetition to the course of the natural world.10 As Pickstock concedes, Kierkegaard himself rarely speaks of the relation of the world of spirit to nature (though there is a brief discussion of “objective anxiety” in The Concept of Anxiety)11, but I think we can reconstruct a view of how spirit emerges from nature along the lines that Ronald Hall has suggested.12 He argues that the hallmark of Kierkegaardian transcendence is the spiritual exclusion of the sensual, an exclusion that nevertheless simultaneously dignifies the excluded as excluded.13 This dynamic I would argue is everywhere in evidence in Kierkegaard’s writings, but it implies a stronger and more complex discontinuity between nature and spirit than Pickstock acknowledges.
Such a discontinuity by leap in turn implies the possibility of a negative, spectral shadowing that would haunt the self, not just the neutral possibility of alternate selves. Pickstock cites Constantin’s observation that “this shadow-existence also demands satisfaction” as support for her contention that “for Kierkegaard, one cannot become a real person unless one plays through all the people whom one might be and might become” (81). However, given Constantin’s relentless irony and aestheticism, we might question the sincerity of this remark.14 He himself is easily entranced by the spectral, as when he spies on a beautiful young girl at the Konigstadter Theater, where he attends the show “not as a tourist, not as an esthete and critic, but if possible, as a nobody.”15 Constantin’s aspiration to nobody-existence that derives vampiric satisfaction from spectatorship, that in the darkened theater indulges the male gaze on the unaware feminine beauty, is surely not a trustworthy guide on how to become a real person.
Later in the text Pickstock is much more clear that there is a real danger to this shadow-play, that the variable possibilities for the self can undermine rather than contribute to the self’s full development (88–89).16 That I think is an important clarification, but even here the role of the religious might be more fully accounted for in recuperating aesthetic experimentation with the self. Pickstock’s analysis of the ethical in Kierkegaard makes a number of expert comments, and in her chapter 7 she revisits the potential concern that for Kierkegaard nevertheless the ethical needs to be completed by the religious. Her identification of the limits of the ethical, even in its paradigmatic consummation as marriage, is just as perspicacious as her discussion of the ethical’s importance in chapter 5, as is her analysis of Kierkegaard’s edifying discourses on the epistle of St. James. Her conclusion, that “The religious, one might say, integrates the aesthetic sublime with the aesthetic-ethical beautiful,” is spot on (134).
I think it’s worth developing the thought though that the aesthetic has to be fully recuperated by the religious on the far side of the ethical. This is true of the argumentation of Fear and Trembling, for instance, but the point is missed entirely by commentators who do not take Problema III into their consideration, a far too frequent oversight. By underscoring the recovery of the aesthetic within the religious (which, seeing as how it was already surpassed and contained within the ethical must perforce be surpassed and contained yet again within the religious), I take it that I only strengthen Pickstock’s analysis of the way in which the fictive and historical, the ideal and real, consolidate themselves in the fully realized self.
The religious life cannot be just a question of actuality but must be made possible by the collision of actuality and ideality that is determinative of consciousness itself. As we read near the unfinished end of the Johannes Climacus, “If that fallacy discussed above could remain, that ideality and reality in all naiveté communicated with one another, consciousness would never emerge, for consciousness emerges precisely through the collision, just as it presupposes the collision.”17 This collision is tantamount to the arising of repetition. Like consciousness, repetition does not occur merely in reality or in ideality alone. “When ideality and reality touch each other, then repetition occurs.”18 Repetition does not occur in reality alone because even the variety of difference is insufficient to produce it. In reality everything is different, but this does not make anything repeated. As Pickstock makes clear, repetition is always contrasted by Kierkegaard with merely mechanical reiteration. One of my passages to this effect occurs in Johannes Climacus: “If the world, instead of being beauty, were nothing but equally large unvariegated boulders, there would still be no repetition. Throughout all eternity, in every moment, I would see a boulder, but there would be no question as to whether it was the same one I had seen before.”19
It is telling that the contrast is drawn here between endlessly-distinct-but-nevertheless-the-same sensible phenomena and “beauty.” Can we surmise that beauty is precisely the non-identically repeated in its actuality rather than ideal distance?20 For the merely aesthetic, there is no actual beauty because there is only the static, timeless ideal. It is this paralyzing ideal that freezes the vamipiric gaze of Constantin, that defines the resignation of de Silentio, that represents the darkest hinter-side the shadow play that haunts the self. “In ideality alone there is no repetition, for the idea is and remains the same, and as such it cannot be repeated.”21 Pickstock and I agree I think that for the religious life alone there is goodness and beauty, where the ideal construals of these are continually shattered against the rocks of actuality and continually reborn anew.
Kierkegaard, Concluding Unscientific Postscript to the Philosophical Crumbs,” ed. and trans. Alastair Hannay (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009), 353–54. Translation modified.↩
According to Johannes Climacus, consciousness just is contradiction between the ideal and the real.↩
The point holds even if the author of Concluding Unscientific Postscript is not the same as the author of Johannes Climacus or De Omnibus Dubitandum.↩
An excellent discussion of this issue and its vital link to “interest” (which Pickstock mentions in her Preface) can be found in Patrick Stokes, Kierkegaard’s Mirrors: Interest, Self, and Moral Vision (London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2010), 29–60.↩
“Identity and Selfhood: Paul Ricoeur’s Contribution and Its Continuations” (unpublished paper).↩
Romano, “Identity and Selfhood.”↩
The Concept of Anxiety, ed. and trans. Reidar Thomte (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1980), 149.↩
Ibid. Pickstock notices a parallel passage from the Journals and Papers (128).↩
Ibid., 28–30.↩
Fear and Trembling and Repetition, ed. and tran. Howard V. Hong and Edna H. Hong (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1983), 283–319.↩
The Concept of Anxiety, 56–60.↩
Ronald L. Hall, “The Origin of Alienation: Some Kierkegaardian Reflections on Merleau-Ponty’s Phenomenology of the Body,” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 12 (1981) 111–22.↩
Ibid., 114–15.↩
Pickstock also seems to give an optimistic view of the fate of the young man (139).↩
Fear and Trembling and Repetition, 165.↩
I especially appreciate her caution against the prospect of “violence against real women, who can never coincide with ideal ones.” The friction of the ideal and real is a theme close to my heart and I believe crucial to Kierkegaard.↩
Johannes Climacus, 171.↩
Ibid.↩
Ibid.↩
Pickstock I take it would agree, and perhaps she here follows her teacher John Milbank in “The Sublime in Kierkegaard,” Heythrop Journal XXXVII (1996) 298–321, p. 319 n. 25: Milbank’s suggestion that “while ‘the religious’ for Kierkegaard exceeds the scope of the three philosophic transcendentals [the true, the good, and the beautiful], it is also the true condition for their integration: the religious alone completes the ethical, and does so by ‘bringing back’ the poetic/aesthetic in a higher guise” is one that this book aspires to develop.↩
Johannes Climacus, 171.↩
2.9.15 |
Response
Kisses Sweeter than . . . Something
Kierkegaard and Pickstock on Repetition and Revision
FIRST KISSES ARE PHENOMENOLOGICALLY ODD. What makes them so strange is that, while occurring, they are indeterminate both in signification and in experience. This indeterminacy arises from the fact that the first kiss only is what it is in light of what follows from it: a relationship that includes more kisses.
A first kiss phenomenologically contains more than a simple encounter of new lips. Rather, it necessarily includes the expectation of future kisses, of the relationship that will follow from the kiss, of the eventual last kiss that will occur at some point yet to come, etc. None of these dimensions of the first kiss need to be explicitly intended by the people kissing, but, nonetheless, these aspects are still “there,” so to speak “in” the kiss itself. To engage in a first kiss is, thus, to find oneself confronted with expectation and yet also with aporia. The first kiss signals an unexpected future into which one is (usually) excited to move in order to discover what lies only embryonically contained in the kiss itself. David Wood nicely encapsulates the phenomenology of the first kiss as “the experience of the opening of a possibility, as a trembling on the brink of something inchoate but momentous, the experience of the realignment of boundaries. Space and time, self and other, activity and passivity, certainty and uncertainty are all thrown into the air, and caught again, differently.”1 Accordingly, he continues, “the first kiss solicits the tenderness of a response, a visceral recognition of the desire of the other. But it also asks a mute question a question every bit as important as “What is the meaning of Being?”2
Expectation, anticipation, trepidation, and even perplexity are all part of the experience of a first kiss. It would seem that a lot happens when pressing one’s lips against the lips of another. Perhaps this is why so many people close their eyes while kissing—they need to focus; there is a bunch going on!
Compare this phenomenology of the first kiss with a phenomenology of the last kiss. Rather than expectation and anticipation, one finds culmination and closure. Instead of trepidation about the emerging relationship, one might find trepidation about the isolation and loneliness that lies ahead, or excitement about finally being free of a toxic relationship, say. While the first kiss “inaugurates a relationship,”3 the last kiss usually ends it. The first kiss seems necessarily to bring eagerness while the last kiss is more hermeneutically complex in that it might be full of regret, longing, disappointment, or freedom and release. Indeed, the last kiss might be a “kiss goodbye,” or simply a “kiss off.” To complicate things even more, some last kisses might arise due to subsequent and unexpected injuries or even the death of one’s lover, which would yield a whole different reality in which there is a termination of the relationship and yet not of the love, etc. Yet, in that case, surely the experience of the “last kiss” would be quite different from the “last kiss” that occurs before breaking up or getting a divorce, for example.
Although such distinctions between these different things, these different events, can be articulated in much more detail, what is important about these initial descriptions is that they are not strictly true at the moment when the first kiss or last kiss occur. Instead, they are made true in light of other events and other things. The first kiss only is a first kiss if followed by a second kiss, and a third kiss, and so on. In other words, it only is what it is when it occurs again, but not for the first time. Moreover, first kisses are importantly located in the context of expectation/trepidation, but many times one can kiss someone for the first time without such a context. In this sense, the first kiss might be best explained as “just kissing” as part of a “make-out session.” We might say, thus, following Kierkegaard, that the first kiss never is, but only ever becomes. If a first kiss inaugurates a relationship, only the relationship itself constitutes the kiss (after the fact) as a “first kiss.” Without the relationship occurring, what we thought was a first kiss, was merely a matter of “making out,” say. Similarly, what we may have understood to be a last kiss might turn out to be the kiss that reignites the relationship and so could actually be properly understood as a first kiss (even if not the initial time that those two individuals touched their lips together). Or, it may have just been one more kiss that, then, turns out to be the last kiss, again potentially due to a variety of eventualities: distance, divorce, death, and so on.
The phenomenological oddity of the first kiss (and the last kiss) confronts us when we realize that there is no way to experience the kiss as what it is without having a variety of subsequent other experiences, according to which the first kiss becomes what it is, or will turn out to have been. We might say that only by being repeated (but now transformed into the “second kiss”) can the “first kiss” occur in the first place. How then are we to make sense of the first kiss, while kissing? Is there ever really an experience of the first kiss or only of there having been a first kiss? What makes these questions difficult is the fact of our existing, our “living forward,” as Kierkegaard would say.
Continuing to live forward makes the task of understanding backward (that is, making sense of things that occur because of the repetition that gives rise to their status) difficult for us at determinate instants. When we think we understand, we continue to live and so our understanding continues to progress as both we and also the thing we are attempting to understand continue to become what they will have been. What we face here is an existential interruption of epistemic certainty. As I read Kierkegaard, the upshot of this basic idea is that epistemic certainty is probably not, then, the goal for lived existence, but instead confident trust and expectancy are.4
Kierkegaard expresses the existential challenge for understanding as follows:
It is quite true what philosophy says, that life must be understood backwards. But that makes one forget the other saying, that it must be lived—forwards. The more one ponders this, the more it comes to mean that life in time is never properly intelligible, for the very reason that at no point can I find complete repose in which to take up the position—backwards.5
Notice here that Kierkegaard does not disagree with the retrospective requirement for understanding, but he does take issue with the idea that one could ever be existentially stable enough to obtain complete understanding in this way. Additionally, it is important that the topic that Kierkegaard finds so difficult to know is life itself.6 The knowing that occurs when I say that there are two cups on my desk, or that if I add two more that there will be four, is not his primary focus. This is important because when Johannes Climacus discusses subjective truth in the Postscript, he is not rejecting objective truth altogether, but simply pointing out its limits when inappropriately applied to matters of existence—and specifically Christian existence.7
There are epistemic and ontological consequences of this Kierkegaardian insight. Ontologically, we might say that things are what they are only as a result of what they will become. So, as we saw above, the first kiss is a first kiss if the relationship the kiss inaugurates happens. In other words, there must be a second kiss in order that the first kiss is constituted as “first.” Similarly, the last kiss is only a last kiss if the relationship the kiss ended does actually end for some reason. In other words, there cannot be a reconciliation that leads to more kissing. Yet, none of these eventualities are known while kissing. It is here that the epistemic consequences emerge. Epistemically, we might say that knowledge is only possible insofar as one continues to realize the impossibility of the “complete repose” required for retrospective understanding. As we continue to live forward, the best we can do is try to understand backward given where it is that we find ourselves. Akin to Aristotle’s claim that one could only be said to be happy after death (because the course of one’s life could now be assessed as a whole), Kierkegaard’s existential epistemology is one that depends on the dynamics of temporal location, perspectival orientation, and eschatological expectation.8 This is not to say that Kierkegaard rejects knowledge, whether objective or subjective. Instead, he simply reminds us that human knowing is something that we do while still in the situation of existing, while still in process, and, thus, while always inhabiting a perspective that is not final. You can’t get outside existence to think about existing. Life is the situation in which knowledge is possible, but it is a situation that makes knowing always a bit more complicated than the logical expression of “S knows that p.” “S” is always an existing individual and that makes a difference in how we make sense of “knows that p.” Similarly, “p” is never simply a static property, but also becomes itself by being known by “S” as what it is in relation to its own repetition in a context.
Importantly, the epistemic and ontological are interwoven such that one attempts to know that which only occurs/exists/happens in light of other known/experienced events. The tension between living forward and understanding backward, and never being able fully to achieve the latter because of the continued requirement of the former, is what animates Constantin Constantius’s account of “repetition.”9 For Constantius, repetition is distinguished from the extreme alternatives of what he terms “hope” and “recollection.” “Hope,” Constantius explains,
Is a new garment, stiff and starched and lustrous, but it has never been tried on, and therefore one does not know how becoming it will be or how it will fit. Recollection is a discarded garment that does not fit, however beautiful it is, for one has outgrown it. Repetition is an indestructible garment that fits closely and tenderly, neither binds nor sags.10
For Constantius, and Kierkegaard too, hope (when taken in isolation as a way of life) is simply a need for the new and a rejection of the continuity of existence. Alternatively, recollection is the bland monotony of the same over and over. Repetition, in contrast, is the willed engagement with the stability of meaning in light of the newness of every moment. “The person,” Constantius writes, “who has not circumnavigated life before beginning to live will never live; the person who circumnavigated it but became satiated had a poor constitution; the person who chose repetition—he lives.”11 It takes courage, then, to will repetition—to affirm the sameness amidst new encounters. Repetition, like the first kiss, entails both expectation and also aporia.
The first kiss is something that should not be sought merely because it is “first,” but instead because of the joy of the relationship that it inaugurates which opens the space for kissing, again, and again. Only in the context of that repetition can the first kiss continue to occur (with every subsequent kiss, the first kiss is kept active in the lived relationship). Similarly, but a bit more strangely, the last kiss is something that continues to happen insofar as one does not fall back into the relationship whereby it turns out that the “last kiss” was not so final. Again, it is the repetition of willing to continue to exist (to live forward) in the space opened by the repetition of the last kiss as final that one’s existence and the event of the kiss itself are co-constituted. In this way, repetition requires of each “single individual” that one demonstrate the courage to go beyond mere aesthetic hope, beyond mere ethical remembrance, and ultimately embrace the possibilities that recur in the repetition of religious trust, with the risk that always attends such trust. Constantius anticipates this Kierkegaardian trilogy of life stages when he offers God as the maximal example of repetition:
If God himself had not willed repetition, the world would not have come into existence. Either he would have followed the superficial plans of hope or he would have retracted everything and preserved it in recollection. This he did not do. Therefore, the world continues, and it continues because it is a repetition.12
Accordingly, repetition is central to all of life’s stages: “Repetition is the interest of metaphysics, and also the interest upon which metaphysics comes to grief; repetition is the watchword in every ethical view; repetition is conditio sine qua non for every issue of dogmatics.”13
We can see, then, that Kierkegaard (through the works of Climacus and Constantius, as well as a variety of other texts by other pseudonyms) provides a possible vision of existence itself as maximally fulfilled by willful repetition. In this way, Kierkegaard nicely invites a future book considering his thought that takes up the intersection of repetition and identity. In such a book the epistemic and the ontological dimensions of lived existence would come together such that only by occurring again does something exist as what it is, and only by willing this repetition would one become who one is. Repetition, thus, inaugurates identity. And yet, identity is what emerges by willing repetition. Importantly, though, repetition is never merely a process of identical occurrences. Repetition needs to be non-identical insofar as the first kiss and the second kiss are not the same kiss, and yet only in the kissing-again does the first kiss happen.
In her book, Repetition and Identity, Catherine Pickstock attempts to write the book that Constantius’s text invites. As Pickstock notes in the Preface, when Constantius claims that repetition is “the indispensable condition for every issue of (Christian) dogmatics,” he “implied that the task for future thought was to develop simultaneously an ontology and a theology of repetition” (xi). In response to this invitation, Pickstock claims that she will “assum[e] Kierkegaard’s challenge” and offer an essay that “hazards an articulation of the real as repetition, and will metamorphose into a sideways articulation of Creation, redemption, apocalypse, and God as repetition” (xi). These are noble goals and the book that Pickstock has attempted is an important one. However, I am not sure that the book she has written successfully achieves what Constantius calls for and what Pickstock herself announces.
If I am on target regarding what Kierkegaard is up to with repetition and the possible ways in which such repetition might be understood regarding an everyday phenomena such as kissing, then it would seem that Pickstock’s text, which explicitly claims to be occurring in light of Kierkegaard’s authorship, would offer something similar regarding repetition and the subjective identity that is implicated in it. In other words, part of what I take to be key to Kierkegaard’s/Constantius’s account of repetition and identity is the mundane level at which repetition occurs. For Constantius, his engagement focuses on the simple question of whether one can return to Berlin. While the stakes of such a return trip, and of repetition more broadly, are significant indeed, the phenomenological level at which those stakes present themselves are matters of what Heidegger would call “average everydayness.” In this way, Constantius successfully expresses “the sublime in the pedestrian,” to borrow a phrase from Johannes de Silentio.14
My point here is that there is something about repetition that must be pedestrian, that must be ordinary, that must be everyday—hence the non-identical repetition of what David Foster Wallace would describe as the “day-to-day trenches of adult existence” in which “banal platitudes can have a life-or-death importance.”15 Indeed, for Silentio, faith is never something that can be recognized from the outside because it is not a matter of external expression. In this way, it is invisible. When it comes to repetition, a similar sort of invisibility confronts us because of the constancy of repetition itself—it keeps happening, we might say.16
This quality of expressing the sublime in the pedestrian, however, is not something that characterizes Pickstock’s text. Instead, Pickstock’s book might better be understood as a manifestation of sublimity itself insofar as the sublime challenges the cognitive faculties of the viewer (or in this case, the reader). Like the mountain range in Caspar David Friedrich’s Wanderer above the Midst, which overwhelms the Wanderer’s faculties and thereby challenges comprehension, Pickstock’s writing style and mode of expression similarly overwhelm the reader and thereby make comprehension difficult. There are a variety of reasons that one would find significant value in writing a performative text that assumes a deep facility with not only contemporary French philosophy, but also with speculative realism, apophatic theology, and a variety of genres of literature. Indeed, if the point is to offer something of a hypothetical vision of what a particular metaphysics of repetition might involve, then perhaps Pickstock’s book is successful. However, if the task is what she seems to claim it is, namely, to think through the Kierkegaardian invitation regarding repetition as the key to existence and especially Christian life, then I find the very style of the book to interfere with the achievement of such a task.
I realize that Pickstock’s influential authorship impressively plays at the border between philosophy and theology on the one hand, and between philosophy/theology and literature on the other hand. This book surely inhabits such border-lands. This is either what makes it remarkable and importantly challenging, or what makes it confusing and simply a challenge that may or may not be worth the effort. I genuinely don’t know which it is. I think that this may be its strength, and I am entirely willing to be persuaded in the direction of the former interpretation. Indeed, I hope that Professor Pickstock’s reply to this review will facilitate such persuasion.
In order to motivate such a response, then, I will offer three concerns that lead me to conclude that this book ends up undercutting itself. Let me be clear about my own frustration at not being able to follow much of the book. I am still not sure I track with all of Pickstock’s account, but I consider the general topic Pickstock engages (as I have suggested with my own account of the phenomenology of the first kiss) to be important and timely. As such, I offer the following criticisms as invitations to further relationship and not as a declaration of divorce.
First, literature is not known for being thesis-driven and supported with argument as the primary means of justification. Perhaps, then, the literary aspects of this book are successful in that Pickstock’s thesis and, subsequently, argument in support of that thesis, are never entirely clear. Maybe such opacity is Pickstock’s intention. In the Preface, Pickstock does admit, perhaps rightly, that “the construal of reality as repetition can be seen as inseparable . . . from the shadowy haunting of reality by sign and allegory” (xiii). “In consequence,” she continues, “the bringing together of metaphysics and theology in what follows itself offers a theory of literature, in the sense that the bringing together can only be fashioned as work of literary artefaction” (xiii). That the book begins with a poem entitled “The snowdrop sequence” seems to support the idea that the book itself is a “work of literary artefaction.” However, how ought we to make sense of such a “work” when it is explicitly presented as offering a “theory of the existing thing” (according to the back cover) and a full-fledged “theory of literature” as claimed in the Preface? Additionally, what are we to make of the claim that it will offer “a sideways articulation of Creation, redemption, apocalypse, and God as repetition”? It seems that the book explicitly aims to stand as a contribution to ontology, contemporary metaphysics, philosophy of literature, and philosophy of religion. If such contributions are to occur, a bit more straightforward articulations would be helpful, instead of such “sideways” movements.
In the first full chapter, Pickstock suggests that we should move away from ontology and, instead, embrace a “reology” where by things are not necessarily “entirely coincident with ‘a being’ or ‘an existence’” (3). Indeed, she goes on to claim that “there is a valid sense in which a reology is more fundamental than an ontology” and that such a “reology is the fundamental scope of that science of identification which we must informally engage with if we are to exist as human beings on this middle earth” (14–15). If this book does offer the “theories” that it claims to offer, this is where those theories would seem to be articulated (such that the rest of the book could stand as the argument for their truth). However, Pickstock does not do enough to clarify exactly what “reology” even means or would entail such that one could weigh and consider the rest of the book as an argument for it. Although I am quite sympathetic to what I take to be the general relational metaphysics that underlies her suggested transition from ontology to reology, there is no real discussion of the difference provided by such a metaphysical option as opposed to relevant alternatives. Instead, what one finds is a weaving together of Kierkegaard, Aquinas, and Augustine without situating their thought in terms of the recent philosophical debates regarding identity and temporal endurance, say. As such, Pickstock seems to assume that her readers are already generally disposed toward reology, yet this assumption is a difficult one to make since it is not clear what reology involves, whether it requires a very specific account of relational (or, more specifically, process) metaphysics, and, if so, why such a metaphysics would be required if one takes repetition seriously in relation to self-identity.
Ostensibly a contribution to ontology, metaphysics, and the philosophy of religion, this book rarely includes direct engagement with the debates occurring in those areas. As just one example of where the engagement with the philosophical issues accompanying her account is lacking, consider that although Gottlob Frege and Saul Kripke are mentioned in footnotes later in the book (83n20, 83n22), neither are discussed in any detail even though their views would be very helpful in situating reology as a distinctive option among the other relevant alternatives. Moreover, instead of engaging contemporary debates in mainstream process metaphysics (as offered by Nicholas Rescher, Roland Faber, Catherine Keller, or Donald Sherburne, say), Pickstock’s discussion is presented primarily as either an interpretation of historical figures or as a contemporary (literary?) performance of some threads occurring in continental philosophy that revolves around such thinkers as Alain Badiou, Gilles Deleuze, and Quentin Meillassoux. As a continental philosopher myself, I am not at all opposed to engaging such thinkers, but without an equally rich engagement with analytic philosophy of mind, philosophy of language, and contemporary metaphysics, it is difficult to see how the account of reology that Pickstock offers could be supported with the requisite warrant to make it stand as a proposal worth serious consideration. Indeed, without such engagement, it is difficult even to understand what the account involves or expects of one who would affirm it. Instead, it seems only to be intelligible if one already grants a variety of very contestable premises assumed by these French thinkers. Perhaps such premises should be affirmed, but argument is needed to justify such affirmation and this is where the literary dimensions of Pickstock’s book seem to occlude what is philosophically necessary rather than fill the necessary gap in the philosophical literature.
Second, and in line with my comment above regarding the metaphysical analyses without considering contemporary work in analytic metaphysics, although Pickstock’s source material demonstrates the important possibilities of understanding philosophy as trans-disciplinary, this often comes at the cost of missing careful analysis of the relevant literature on the specific thinkers upon whom she draws. As perhaps the most striking example of this, the discussion of Kierkegaard that occurs sporadically throughout the book is rarely presented in relation to the enormous amount of Kierkegaard scholarship that currently exists. In chapter 7, as just one instance, Pickstock addresses Kierkegaard’s account of the religious as it might bear on the crucial limits of ethical repetition. Yet, in this chapter, the only cited secondary source on Kierkegaard is John Milbank’s (1998) “The Sublime in Kierkegaard,” which is notoriously difficult and itself oddly disconnected from the main trajectories in the contemporary philosophical literature on Kierkegaard. Now, my concern here is not that Pickstock doesn’t cite more people, but that her engagement with Kierkegaard is nearly unrecognizable as a contribution to the debates regarding those key aspects of Kierkegaard’s thought upon which she draws so heavily.
What results is more of a performative retelling of a possible reading of Kierkegaard than an argument regarding how one ought to read his authorship in relation to process metaphysics and reological accounts of personal identity. As a “work of literary artefaction,” perhaps this is acceptable, and maybe even commendable, but as such it is difficult, then, to see it also as a work of philosophy. Hence, the status of the truth claims that Pickstock offers are, thus, thrown into something of an ambiguous state. Is her account meant to be a possible vision of reality—an expression of a literary imagination, say? Or is it meant to be an account of reality that should warrant our assent—an expression of a philosophical argument? If it is the former, then exploring the phenomenologically “pedestrian” dimensions of repetition and the ways that these dimensions play out in existence (rather than in the pages of Deleuze) is required. If it is the latter, then involving the philosophically “pedestrian” aspects of clear argumentation and scholarly engagement is required. As it is, it is difficult to understand this book as either a contribution to constructive metaphysics or to Kierkegaardian scholarship. Perhaps neither of these alternatives is the aim of Pickstock’s text, but if not then it would be very helpful to get some clarification as to what the aim actually is.
Finally, Pickstock faces the extremely difficult theological task of attempting to speak positively of what might only be reasonably expressed negatively. In other words, such theologians as Meister Eckhart, Nicholas of Cusa, and Origin, upon whom she draws variously throughout the book, are not exactly easy to appropriate into a mode of expression that favors clarity and lucidity. Instead, such work (in a variety of ways) stands resistant to such appropriation because of their attempt to attend to the unsayable, the inexpressible, and the radically transcendent. Such topics are notoriously difficult to engage with the frequently all too blunt tools of philosophical analysis. That said, I commend Professor Pickstock for her facility with such thinkers and her noble attempt to bring them into conversation with thinkers working in alternative traditions that offer their own rhetorical and conceptual challenges: Irenaeus, Kierkegaard, and Deleuze, in particular. Accordingly, a significant amount of charity should be shown as a reader of this book given the sheer degree of difficulty of the endeavor it attempts. However, there is an emerging discussion in contemporary phenomenology that directly considers what Heidegger terms a “phenomenology of the inapparent” (Phänomenologie des Unscheinbaren).17 Even well discussed moments in recent French philosophy as Jacques Derrida’s (1982) consideration of negative theology in “Différance,” Emmanuel Levinas’s (2000) account of a God “transcendent to the point of absence,” and Jean-Luc Marion’s (1991) difficult attempt to discuss a “God without being,” are all faced with similar challenges as those that now face Pickstock. Yet, there are ways of thinking about that which resists expression without, necessarily, effacing expression in the process. Indeed, one might even argue that the best engagement with apophatic theology would be one that attends to the tension of the engagement itself as threatening self-refutation.18
Regardless, apophatic theology and the phenomenology of the inapparent both invite an appreciation of the fine line that exists between, on the one hand, performative rhetorical devices that serve to remind us of the epistemic arrogance that can so easily emerge when we assume the confident repose that Kierkegaard finds ultimately incompatible with existence itself, and on the other hand, giving in to a rhetorical performance that sidesteps the risk of attempting clearly to articulate that which resists clear articulation. In the first option, there is a risk of misunderstanding, but one attends to that risk itself in the attempt to avoid misunderstanding. In the second option, alternatively, there is no risk of misunderstanding because understanding was never really the goal. There are different sort of expectations when one sits down to read philosophy and when one goes to the theater. Neither is more important than the other, but it is crucial that one not go to the theater expecting to hear a refutation of Kant. Just as with the first kiss, context is crucial. Because I am so deeply interested in the possibilities for relational metaphysics and the promising idea that there might be reasons to prefer a reology in the effort of attending to the difficulties that existence presents to understanding, I wish I had a better sense of what Pickstock’s book is attempting to do and how, then, to make sense of it. Unfortunately, though, I so rarely have a sense of the argument being presented in the book that it is extremely difficult to tell if the difficult stylistic performance is necessary to what is being claimed or not.
I initially approached this book with the excitement and trepidation of something like a first kiss. I wasn’t sure of what the relationship with the ideas was going to be and whether it would be a relationship that motivated further kisses/readings or not. Even though I ended up reading the book several times, at this point the repetition has not yielded intimacy, but instead mere longing for an explanation. I sincerely hope that the last time I read the book will not turn out to have been a metaphorical last kiss. I hope that Professor Pickstock can express the sublime in the pedestrian and make a bit clearer for philosophers like me who love literature, but are suspicious of the idea that continental philosophy has to been written in a poetic mode in order for it to be true to the original inspirations that motivated it as a distinct philosophical tradition (or, better, traditions). Even as a continental philosopher, I think that we must be very careful to distinguish between the importance of considering the intricate detail of the Emperor’s new clothes, which resist being understood according to the existing fashions of the day, and the importance of admitting that there may not much there to consider in the first place.
Let me conclude by suggesting that repetition and revision go together. When we will repetition we don’t simply embrace sameness, but instead we cultivate an attitude of expectation that occurs only in beginning again for the first time. We keep trying to get better at the task of existence, which means that striving and risk are perpetual (as entailed by the aporia of repetition itself), but so is the renewal that such becoming offers (hence the trust that defines religious existence). Such revision needs not be understood merely as a metaphor, however. Perhaps attending to Kierkegaardian repetition will call all continental philosophers to realize how important it is to write and re-write texts that invite readers into relationships rather than convince them that they are either not smart enough to understand, or that there is nothing there worth reading in the first place.
“Kisses sweeter than wine” are largely compelling because we are able to make sense of exactly what is being compared and, thus, it can be concluded that, as good as wine is, kisses are even better. “Kisses sweeter than, well . . . something,” are not compelling because the comparison is not clear. Are they sweeter than lemons? Or rice? Or chocolate? The point here is that clarity is required in order to be able to make reasonable choices about how to act and what to believe. Metaphors that gain traction in our life-world depend on such clarity and the philosophical texts we write should display such clarity as well. Only then could cognitive assent and existential action be rightly motivated.
Although I hoped, and continue to hope, that Repetition and Identity would be a text that offers a relationship to readers that will motivate willed repetition of the reading itself, ultimately I find it to be one that may, unfortunately, reinforce the belief that continental philosophy is simply not worth a second date. For my own part, I think I will just keep dating Kierkegaard.
David Wood, “The First Kiss: Tales of Innocence and Experience.” In The New Kierkegaard, edited by Elsebet Jegstrup (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 2004), 131.↩
Ibid.↩
Ibid., 130.↩
See Kierkegaard, “The Expectancy of Faith” in Eighteen Upbuilding Discourses. Edited and translated by Howard V. Hong and Edna H. Hong (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1990); See also John J. Davenport, “What Kierkegaardian Faith Adds to Alterity Ethics: How Levinas and Derrida Miss the Eschatological Dimension.” In Kierkegaard and Levinas: Ethics, Politics, and Religion. Edited by J. Aaron Simmons and David Wood (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 2008), 169–96.↩
Michael Strawser, Both/And: Reading Kierkegaard from Irony to Edification (New York, NY: Fordham University Press, 1997), 17.↩
Here I take him to anticipate the new phenomenology of Michel Henry—see Michel Henry, The Essence of Manifestation. Translated by Girard Etzkorn (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973); I am the Truth: Toward a Philosophy of Christianity. Translated by Susan Emanuel (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2003); Words of Christ. Translated by Christina M. Gschwandtner (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2012). For considerations of Kierkegaard as a phenomenologist, see Jeffrey Hanson, ed. Kierkegaard as Phenomenologist: An Experiment (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 2010); J. Aaron Simmons, and David Wood, eds. Kierkegaard and Levinas: Ethics, Politics, and Religion (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 2008).↩
Kierkegaard, Concluding Unscientific Postscript to Philosophical Fragments.↩
For more on Kierkegaard’s epistemology, see M. G. Piety, Ways of Knowing: Kierkegaard’s Pluralist Epistemology (Waco, TX: Baylor University Press, 2010).↩
Kierkegaard, Fear and Trembling.↩
Ibid., 132.↩
Kierkegaard, Fear and Trembling, 132.↩
Ibid., 133.↩
Ibid., 149.↩
Ibid., 41.↩
David Foster Wallace, This is Water (New York, NY: Little, Brown, and Company, 2009), 9.↩
For a sustained consideration of Kierkegaard’s notion of faith, see Merold Westphal, Kierkegaard’s Concept of Faith (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2014).↩
See Martin Heidegger, Four Seminars. Translated by Andrew Mitchell and François Raffoul (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 2003), 80; for more on this notion as it relates to new phenomenology, see J. Aaron Simmons, and Bruce Ellis Benson, The New Phenomenology: A Philosophical Introduction (London: Bloomsbury, 2013), 27–41.↩
Scott F. Aikin, and J. Aaron Simmons, “Levinasian Otherism, Skepticism, and the Problem of Self-Refutation.” Philosophical Forum 40, no.1 (Spring 2009): 29–54.↩
2.11.15 |
Response
The Politics of Repetition and Identity
It is not so easy to reach the last resort. To get there, one must indeed try everything (which is a lot of things)-and not just once, as if a political party or movement might organize a single demonstration, fail to win immediate victory, and claim that it is now justified in moving on to murder. Politics is an art of repetition.
—Michael Walzer, “Excusing Terror”The difference is that philosophy is no longer knowledge, or knowledge of knowledge. It is an action. One could say that what identifies philosophy is not the rules of a discourse, but the singularity of an act.
—Alain Badiou, “Philosophy as Creative Repetition”
REPETITION IS HAVING ITS OWN little moment these days. It is the ultimate cross-over act: from Plato to Hegel, Kierkegaard to Deleuze, and Derrida to Adorno, the philosophical attention to the subject has generated considerable theological and ethical treatments as well. In her latest book, Repetition and Identity,1 Catherine Pickstock affords us an opportunity to rethink repetition as a properly theological category, that is, a notion that coalesces ontology with physics in a genuinely Thomistic spirit. My specific interest in this essay is to surface the political aspects of her proposal, to raise some questions about what her account of “non-identical” repetition might mean for contemporary politics. By my reading, politics is the absent specter in this book, haunting its every move, and so I hope that my comments here can perhaps spark a conversation that brings it out of the shadows a bit more.
Any attempt to respond comprehensively or account adequately for all of the various arguments and their permutations in this book is far beyond the scale of this article, not to mention my own intellectual bandwidth. So, in lieu of that, in what follows my objective will be to surface what I think are the more politically salient aspects of her reological position on repetition. This short essay is not so much a critique as it is a query, namely out of a humbling recognition that I am still learning from Pickstock’s work, and that there much in this book, most of it actually, that I still do not fully understand. I fully expect that I will get it wrong along the way, and so I hope that Pickstock will rectify any errors or mistakes. I trust that Pickstock’s corrections will be valuable, not only for myself, but for other readers as well, as we collectively engage her work over the next few weeks at Syndicate. I also hope that, in her response, Pickstock will comment more specifically on the political import of her proposed reading of repetition, beyond the trace comments that appear in the argument’s marginalia. The impact that repetition can have on selfhood, or to be more specific, on the formation of a political subjectivity, capable of executing the collective, large scale interventions required for social emancipation, is of great interest to me, and yet I found little by way of explicit help in Repetition and Identity, and so I am hopeful that Pickstock might humor me here.
Second, it is unavoidable that I approach Professor Pickstock’s work from my own rather uncharitable reading of the Radical Orthodoxy movement, a theological and political sensibility for which she is a primary contributor and spokesperson. The exact political leanings of this program is highly debated, and there is no doubt that there are indeed differences between those who work in and through the Radical Orthodoxy framework. But when reading this book, while not scratching my head and re-reading any number of paragraphs for the eighth (or thirteenth) time, I found myself interested in what Pickstock might say about the relation of repetition to the inaugurate effect of political creativity—namely the creativity of Action that generates the genuinely politically New—that impolite and disruptive Event that inaugurates “Really Existing Difference.” The political valiance of the New is deeply linked to a materialist theology of creativity, which de-centers optimistic views on “productivity” and genealogic patterns of “generativity,” opting instead for a politics of negativity and failure. It is, nevertheless, revolutionary in its willingness to redouble itself in repetition, which incessantly calls for that which is not yet here: the irruptive event of New that shifts the coordinates of possibility for the authentic political Act. To what extent does Pickstock’s theory of the Thing as existing in/as “non-identical repetition” contribute or resist these ideas about how to convert politics from being about nothing, to being about repetition of failure. I want to ask whether the key to repetition is not its ability to generate res, but rather in its stubborn failure to produce at all. This urges us to return to the starting point, where it all began, to repeat the beginning. This negative dialectical pattern is the legacy of Hegel’s theory of repetition, and is the vanishing mediator in Adorno that shows up again and again in Žizek and Badiou. There is little doubt that Pickstock will object to the intellectual trajectory just sketched out, but it nevertheless affords us a political perspective on repetition not directly engaged in Repetition and Identity.
Repetition and Reology
After a long “postmodern” hiatus, it certainly appears that metaphysics is back. Much like the “return” of the theological in contemporary philosophy, it has not so much returned as it has recurred, and so has acquired both a new visibility as it once again tries to claim purchase on the state of the contemporary present. The importance of this development, not only for the relation of philosophy and theology, but also for that of theology and politics, is as difficult to overstate, as it is to fully understand. For this reason, we are all indebted to Pickstock for her Repetition and Identity in which she lays out a characteristically erudite theological account of repetition that is dripping with aesthetic sensitivity and literary acuity. Her commitments are as straightforward as the details are obscure: Pickstock puts her Platonism to work to synthesize epistemology with an ontology (a move that she identifies as also being Kierkegaardian) that is, at the same time, also a theology of repetition, through which we are able to maintain and live in an integrity of thought and experience. It is through reology that human persons are able to grasp the world, to live and act in it “as it is” with legibility and coherence, properly identifying the complex, but accessible interplay of Things with its selfsame non-identical repetition. To identify res is to position ourselves and others in a consistent, organized, and reliable fashion, one that accounts for paradoxically moving and closed character of signification. The goal of her reology, then, appears to be a thoroughly political one: to aid the subject in being and acting with consistency and intelligibility—which is made possible only in light of God’s own repeating. Repetition and Identity’s political moment is not incidentally its theological one as well: all identities—which are inaugurated by their repeating—are situated in Christ, whose repeating discloses divine aseity to be that perfect One of the many that binds its internal multiplicity and difference, its variety and iteration in an eternal relation of being “wholly ‘alone’”(195).
And so, I take the main objective of Pickstock’s Repetition and Identity to be nothing less than a radical intervention into key philosophical debates about difference and identity by proposing a metaphysical reology that integrates thought and being, but does by way of the theological. The stakes are significant: it is nothing less than the ability to be able to identify Things as they are: the conditions of survival (15). For this task, she argues that a reological turn is required, because prehending res as repetition helps us realize the requisite conditions of meaningful and substantive existence. We need a reology because in order to live as human beings and do so well (that is orderly, meaningfully, and cogently), we must being able to consider, identify, and organize a thing as it is and situate it in a weighed relation to other things. To know the real is know the essence of res. The requisite category for this inquiry is repetition. Not just any understanding of repetition will do, however. What we call repetition must be able to account for the life and emergence of a thing “in such a way that the mark of thingness appears to be consistency and continuity despite variation” (11). Certainly, repetition introduces difference, and so however repetition operates, it cannot be auto-generative; there must be change at the same moment that a thing becomes a thing by being other than selfsame. All of this hangs, of course, on Pickstock’s description of repetition as “non-identical” and her defense of it against alternative forms/understandings of repetition. It turns out that the stakes here are steep and sweeping, in that her account of repetition cashes out in a theological way, and is not restricted to metaphysics or selfhood.
Insofar as Pickstock’s register is thoroughly synthetic, she is interested in putting forth a thick theory of the Thing as “non-identical repetition” whereby things are things as both and/or either sense-objects or thoughts that must double themselves via as self-same iteration in order to be manifested by the human subject as Real. There must be, she insists, variation in the Thing itself that short of reproducing that selfsame thing (either as a copy or clone), introducing of the novelty of difference through and as sign. Things relate to themselves in multiplicity and alterity in, through, and as sign, which is indeed faithfully and reliably expresses reality as such, rather than merely inaugurating the inchoate and aporetic aspects of difference itself.
Interpreting human experience of self, other, and world through the rubric of repetition, or non-identical repetition (“sameness only obtainable through difference” and “difference only postulated through similarity”) to be specific, is required if we hope to rescue ourselves from the confusion and incoherence of a life where we are unable to make sense of things, ourselves, and our constitutive relations to things. Her reology comes down to a theory of a thing as that which is non-identically repeated; all things acquire their original thingness (their constitutive identity) when they have been repeated—holding itself together with integrity and continuity while also transgressing its own boundaries an indiscrete number of times. So a thing as a thing must have integrity, doubling, difference, continuity, variety, and multiplicity to be its selfsame. How does she accomplish this? In a properly Thomistic spirit, she sketches an inner and outer analogy between the thing and its repetition that is thoroughly non-identical, calling upon the affect of motion to outline how it is that a thing can be internally iterated by variety, difference, and indeed, continuity despite change, without splintering, fragmenting, combusting due to seemingly endless multiplicity or contradiction. The res-as-repetition model expressed here is that of “integrated difference” that sustains the thingness of res through the presumption of closure and limitation, with respect to both its inner and external relations (24ff), which are irreducibly and necessarily double (35). This leads Pickstock to conclude “that each thing, as a non-identical repetition, is an unanalyzable compound of the same and the different, in such a way that the same has always become different, and the different forever remains the same”(51).2 The coherence of a thing depends, then, on a “kind of internal analogy between its parts, of a kind that is closer than the analogies which pertain between disparate things”(51). “Every res is a non-identical repetition held together in beauty by inner and outer analogy” (100), Pickstock maintains, and this establishes an “obscure likeness of ‘attribution’ which pertains between two unlike things, without being expressible outside the specific conjoining of their unlikeness”. The kinship between these two unlike things (presumptively, res and its indefinitely repeated selfsame other) is only accessible and apparent through this conjunctional analogy that resists hierarchy (between the same and the different as compositional elements of res) and buttresses a mutually participative interplay between the two, that nevertheless generates an irresolvable contradiction that resists explanation.3
So then if repetition, namely the non-identical sort, is that operative event wherein the Thing comes into itself, it is also that through which the Self encounters an internal difference that is analogically always a sameness, and so repetition produces an internal analogy that empowers it to be meaningful, and so to act in significant ways. But, again, why repetition? It has an ontological dynamism, a fundamentally constitutive power, that is able to traverse, or rather transcend, in a synthetic move, the supposed binaries of modern life. Pickstock addresses a few of interest to her (i.e., fiction and history, double and the moment, and that of sense and reference), but the most important is that between identification and differentiation. Repetition binds them so that difference and identity are resolved not through a dialectical “coincidence of opposites,” but as an analogically simple Whole: “every single thing is strangely doubled and then multiplied in space; also, every thing is an event in time which must occur twice and then an indefinitely number of other times”(43). Nature, self, history, and indeed God, are included in this account. Indeed, in reading Repetition and Identity, it was clear to me the initial reological chapters are little more than preludes to the later theological chapters, keen on preserving possibility of being able to know and speak of about God, human salvation, and eschatological futurity with consistency, order, and integrity. What is theologically at stake or gained in her theory of repetition, and what are the political implications of said theological formulation?
Repetition as a Theory of Political Subjectivity
It is a modern philosophical-theological axiom is that politics begins with the subject. But Pickstock uses Plato to argue against Descartes and (in an odd way) with Deleuze that the subject itself is incapable of becoming the foundation of thought itself. To secure an identity for herself, the subject positions herself in relation to “non-identically repeated events in time, which appear and present themselves in a swirl of self, history, and, important for Pickstock, a fiction that is seemingly more real than the truth.4 In a thoroughly Kierkegaardian moment, it is this last aspect of repetitive identity in which the subject encounters herself “caught” in and as a shadowy presence that speaks to and discloses the transcendent “the higher power” (81) as the constitutive term that binds them to the subject in the first place.
This feeds directly into a corresponding theory of the repeating subject, whereby again, it is through repetition that human beings are able to establish ourselves as enworlded subjects whose affective existence and relations are in fact coherent (85), harmonious (51) and reliable, despite the tossing and turning of shadowy figures (that are, at the same time, selfsame and not), the apparent slippage and bricolage that presents themselves in culture and history as obstacles to human well-being:
If the human self is to cohere as a res, and to be disclosive of all other res, it cannot only be reinscribed in circles of representation which describe the world geographically or record the past archivally. The self must be a living, dynamic symbol, fusing sense and reference, fiction and history, able to traverse, prehend, and grieve, decipher and fulfill the allegories of nature (101).
This is conditioned by “decisions” we apparently make, but are meaningful insofar as they necessarily share in God’s own powerful judgement, given coherence as they “are disclosive of that which lies absolutely beyond.”5 She is broadly anti-philosophical in that she faults the discipline for its apparent anemic inability to make sense of the most prosaic of experience, and so turns to both theological sources to give an account of why it is that things must come and come again (via the sign) if they are to be counted as real.
The integrity of the self is under clear assault from the “circle of sense and reference” which imbues subjectivity with a sense of arbitrariness and discontinuity, leading it to think of itself as something radically contingent and discontinuous with the Real, lacking any purposive coherence or legible consistency. Repetition affords us a way out of this, that is, a way into an identity whereby it is possible, says Pickstock, “to become themselves, develop a reliable character, in repeated harmony with other characters, and achieve virtue, a participation in the eternally Good?” Non-identical repetition is necessary, if we are to avoid resigning the self to an instrumentalized life whose operations are pointless, regulated, and distracted. Without repetition, human social life is sentenced to incessantly routinized bureaucratic forms, mechanized to meet particular functions, but lost to the life-giving world of affect and sense. Repetition is called upon to help us escape the new, emergent forms of alienation that masquerade as shadowy and shallow forms of fiction, whether they pass under names like Freedom, Democracy, love, or morality.
Following (in a properly “indirect” way) Kierkegaard, the non-identical repetition of the self is achieved, not by or through the ethical, but the religious grasp of the eternal, that rejects the nostalgic tyranny of the past or the on-going deferral to futurity, redemptive in itself (mostly because it is unknown, and apparently, still emergent). The goal of the repeated self is to secure identity by embracing and illuminating the eternal, which means refusing a bias towards the past or future, but rather “living in the present which constantly accepts its passage and receives and constitutes the ‘momentary’ or ecstatic unity of past, present and future”(95). The significance of the eternal for repetition (and thus, for Pickstock’s thesis here) is that it is eternal (and the participation of Things therein) that holds together the hidden level of unification and harmony made available to the thing (and so to nature, history, and also, the self) via repetition.
This idealist appeal to the Platonic eternal as the properly basic condition of repetition has potential costs, though. One of them is the radical appeal of repetition as a political Act, namely as the basis upon which any and all politics can be indeed to be recognized as Acts that are about something at all, rather than reoccurring iterations of the incessant cynical dismissal “that anything can ever change, really.” What is spectrally absent—rather than missing—from Pickstock’s account is a way to think repetition as a political moment or project, as something that happens within the historically material aspects of social relations or productive forces, and that may or may not generate or engender something akin to the New—that emancipatory Event that so radical that it completely changes the coordinates of possibility for affective relations and social attachments.
Constructively, speaking: Repetition, Difference, and the New
Purveyors of repetition are given careful and nuanced attention in this book: Kierkegaard to Peguy, Bergson to Deleuze, Agamben to Irenaeus are given careful attention here, but it is worth noting that Hegel is again only spectrally present, as is his heterodoxic postsecular reader, Slavoj Žizek.6 Let us bring him and his politics of repetition into the light a bit—and see what happens. The ‘trace’ engagement with these perspectives is understandable, given her preoccupation with reinterpreting Kierkegaard, resisting Deleuzian materialism, and her constructive use of early Greek patrology. But humor me for a moment as I wonder aloud about how an non-identical repetition might be rendered useful for thinking theologically about political materialism—using a bit of Hegel and Žizek along the way. I will try this by relating repetition to the category of the New through Pickstock’s position on the repetition of the revealed event. I am sure that Pickstock might object here—but there are times when we learn far more by disagreeing as we do otherwise. I am hoping that she can teach me a bit more about Hegel here—and also clarify her own positions a bit more.
The central question I want to raise here, to myself, to other reviewers, and to Professor Pickstock is whether or not her theory of repetition can help us prehend and enact the revolutionary process. What does it offer to a political theology eager to function in a critical and interventionary way in material aspects of human life, the nitty-gritty details of affective relations, sensual movements, and bodily attachments that characterize and shape how we as human beings live, fuck, and work? In repetition, what is the fate of the politically New, or are we left with a dialectical repetition of the Same? In what ways can repetition be counted on to generate the New? If repetition is and remains, as Pickstock claims, a transcendence, a catalyst which discloses the bankruptcy of the immanent fervor, what does this mean for a ruptrual and inaugural politics that welcomes the impossible Event that disrupts the Now of present conditions?
Hegel interprets repetition as the symbolic act: the act whereby the Symbolic order emerges as the structure of meaning for the subject upon which it shows itself to be substance. It is in this way that, like Pickstock, Hegel argues that repetition is not simply that which acts upon or to Things, but it is rather constitutive of those Things: “By repetition that which at first appeared merely a matter of chance and contingency becomes a real and ratified existence.”7 It is repetition that moves the Thing through the passage from contingency to necessity, as it is clear that “the event that occurs only once seems by definition incapable of occurring at all.” The initial iteration of the Thing presents itself and is received by its constitutive signifying network as an intervention, a contingent and ruptured failure within the legibility of the symbolic. This “recognition by passing through repetition” announces the traumatic emergence of the Thing into the symbolic order: “the Thing that repeats itself retroactively receives, through its repetition, its law.”
Repetition has long been a critical battleground in the struggle against Hegel, most notably against his theory of Absolute Knowing. In the skirmish between Hegel and Kierkegaard, Pickstock sides with the latter, and in doing so, considers herself also opposing Deleuze, despite the fact that he too resists Hegel at a fundamental level. It was Kierkegaard, after all, who led the charge against Hegel, in part, on account of his supposed affinities for Platonic “recollection,” which can be faulted for many reasons, the most pressing of which was that it demanded a movement “backwards into knowledge” so that truth is located in an abstract past into which one can only access by entering backwards. This significantly troubles the passionate decisiveness required for action. If one is obsessed with encountering and redoubling the past, how can one ever be authentically present to and so acting in the reoccurring present—the ever-recursive Now which is always dialectically then, there, and here? In repetition, Kierkegaard counts, the human subject is able to “enter eternity forward” in a “reappropriation of the past through which the past becomes transformed and recast, opening a future of possibility for choice and action.” Repetition then is always a transcendence and thus avoids the unbearable numbness of pure reoccurrence—the same-one-after-another (except that it is not so much another as it is itself under the guise of negativity) that marks the patterns of the aesthetic life. Stephen Crites describes the difference in Kierkegaard’s mind between recollection and repetition (which is essentially, again, in Kierkegaard mind, the difference between him and Hegel) well: “Not in the re-collected necessity of thought, but in the contingency of historically situated action directed towards an uncollected future, a man (sic) appropriates truth.”
If you want a politics of the New funded by repetition, Hegel at first glance appears like an odd resource for such a thing. Indeed, Kierkegaard’s legacy lives on a generation of readers of Hegel who find his conception of history, his theory of absolute knowing, his theology of the State, hazardous, vulgar, and undesirable. To these readers, Kierkegaard is convincing on the point that Hegel’s “recollection” invites, nay demands, a radical closure of history and so abandons the concrete individual for the sake of abstract thought, absolutized by synthesis and reconciliation. It is common, in talk about Hegel, to hear the accusation that he is stridently opposed to the emergence of the New, and so effectively abandoned dialectics in route to absolute knowledge, demanding along the way that history is concluded, that nothing new is possible. If history has indeed come to an end, this means that action ceases, for if there is this radically decisive completion of knowledge, that there has been a final resolution of history, any and all acts are quite unintelligible. What and when would you act—and what for? For why act if, due to the radical closure of history and thought, there will never be more anything new on earth? The cost of this totality is that we all cease to become human—that we are no longer are subjects. (To me, if there is a political impetus for Pickstock’s theology of repetition, it is indeed to help the human person think herself as subject in a social world that has lost sight of the ground of its intelligibility and coherence: “god.”)
Surely, the idea that Hegel thinks that “there will never be more anything new on earth” (an accusation blamed in large part on his alleged predilection for recollection over “pure” repetition) is incorrect. As is the aforementioned assumption (the classics locus of which is certainly Kierkegaard) that Hegelian “recollection” is in fact incongruent with Kierkegaardian repetition. Following a wave of new research on Hegel’s ontology and political philosophy, it is increasingly clear that Hegelian position on repetition is far more than mere recollection in that he interprets the former by reading the latter as a reappropriation of the past which always already transcends it—giving birth to a new world (or at least a dialectical materialism that hopes to bring it to fruition). This is the political promise of recollection, is that it repeats itself in ways that gets beyond itself (a “negation of negation”), effectively pointing thought, history, and action towards the New—all the while avoiding the forced choices established by present coordinates. Is this that much different than Kierkegaard’s repetition, which considers the past to be the creative point of departure for its (own) future—which is always the eternal Now?8
Hegel’s position on repetition is often misunderstood, I think, because the self-reflexive core of his negativity is not readily recognized. Again, a new wave of research is changing this. Following Žizek and Malabou here, the essence of Hegelian negativity is the incessant albeit unbearable and traumatic drive to repeat without “any movement of sublation or idealization.” What Žizek calls “pure repetition” is a negative and negating drive, a dark compulsion of life and thought that is sustained by an internal “impurity,” “the persistence of a pathological element to which repetition gets stuck.” The problem with Hegel is that he cannot theorize a pure repetition that is not yet caught up trying to either fragment itself or perfect itself in some pure, representative form.9 For Žizek, the task of interpreting Hegel on repetition, then, is to think beyond Hegel—to transcend Hegel by repeating him—for in order for this this radical openness to be realized with or even as pure repetition, it must not be about sublation or idealization. “The point is not so much that we should not ignore Hegel, but that we can only afford to ignore him after a long and arduous working-through-Hegel. The time has thus come to repeat Hegel.”10 Žizek, again like Pickstock, sides with Kierkegaard over Hegel, only because he sees Kierkegaard as much closer to Hegel than either Hegel or Kierkegaard would have liked to think. Again, Žizek: “Is not the excess of negativity over the reconciled social order, also the excess of repetition over sublation?”11
For Žizek, the properly Kierkegaardian “pure” repetition occurs when the negative dialectics of sublimation encounters its own core, as outside itself, as it fights against its own abyssal ground, in order to resist any phantasmic identification, a move which blatantly ignores the cut, or wound, at the core of the “Nothing, that is the subject.” Alas, the central notion of Hegelian negativity is not the utter destruction of whatever there is/may be, but rather a sudden, unannounced, and unforeseen halt or paralysis of the normal flow or smooth running of things. Negativity recognizes the immense creativity that is made possible when things get stuck, due to the unwelcome and impolite singularity that persists beyond allowed time. Deleuze and Žizek both concur that this is how the New can arise: when repetition manifests its proper negativity: this happens when “things flow, they follow their course, of constant change, and then something gets stuck, it interrupts that flow, imposing itself as New by way of this very persistence.” But again, how might this extreme negativity be seen as in any way productive, rather than strictly annihilistic in its unapologetic disregard for order or law, in its ebullient fete of failure, loss, and chaos? This kind of negativity sounds like a perverse game of dancing with the devil—and enjoying it a bit too much. But when self-reflexively applied, in the fourth moment of negation, it appears as “the blind compulsion to repeat”, it shows itself to be the productive force inherent to absolute knowledge itself. Many will accuse this of suffering from an oft-noted radical historical closure that refuses any meta-language or any way to prehend oneself from an “outside” position, but few will recognize how it is that the repetition of this self-relating negativity also admits/generates a radical openness to the future, indeed, even a pathway to the New.
This political valency of repetition is clarified when read through the Marxist axiom that historical appears twice: “first time as tragedy, the second time as farce.”12 Žizek interprets this politically: “Repetition, according to Hegel, plays a crucial role in history: when something happens just once, it may be dismissed as an accident, something that might have been avoided if the situation had been handled differently; but when the same event repeats itself, it is a sign that a deeper historical process is unfolding. . . . The same holds for the continuing financial crisis. In September 2008, it was presented by some as an anomaly that could be corrected through better regulations, etc. Now that signs of a repeated financial meltdown are gathering, it is clear that we are dealing with a structural phenomenon.”13 Repetition is far from an innocent or progressive notion; it may indeed be constitutive of human existence in history but this may not be the best of news. What is being repeated is violence, war, injustice, and indeed death—in all its sundry forms. But this is required, says Žizek. It is only by going through farce, through error and failure, that we are able to traverse fantasy of the really existing Act that changes every thing and finally get to something productive: namely, to get something right, we are compelled, forced even, to get it terribly wrong first—and to repeat this again and again.14
How, then, can repetition be counted on help us think how to “deal” with these structural pathologies in revolutionary ways—that is, in ways that generate avenues for the political New, and establishes conditions for authentic political Acts? Žizek reminds us of Rosa Luxemburg’s description of the dialectic of the revolutionary process whereby the oppressed proletariat takes power and does so prematurely, without proper planning and lacking adequate operational details, but this is not of concern. “The only way of arriving at mmaturity,’ of waiting for the ‘opportune’ moment to seize power, is to form themselves, prepare themselves for this seizure; and the only way of forming themselves is, of course, these ‘premature’ attempts . . . the ‘maturity’ of the revolutionary subject—can only occur through a series of ‘premature’ attempts. There is no right or appropriate time for revolution. It is not a polite, ordered, and organized affair. The revolutionary subject cannot be revolutionary from a measured distance; she cannot prepare herself to be revolutionary and then wait to engage the situation when her mature status is intact and tested: the ‘subjective failure’ of the agents is essential to the ‘objective’ process of the Act itself.”15 The revolutionary subject is indeed constituted through this process of insufficient action and failed planning; it is only through repetition of failure, of loss, of prematurity that the revolutionary subject comes into herself. The revolutionary act realizes itself only in its repeated failures—on getting it wrong, on making the same mistakes. We must strive to act, if only to get it wrong over and over again, if we have any hope of arriving at the properly authentic act, as it is through this very error that we are able to succeed. The failed revolution must be repeated—over and over again—despite its well-documented destiny to fail.16 The revolutionary “meaning” of those premature attempts is found in their repeated failure. Žizek will often cite Hegel here in saying that, “a political revolution is, in general, only sanctioned by popular opinion after it has been repeated.” When it comes to revolution, something New comes about only through repetition, but it is the repetition of discontinuity, rupture, failure, loss, and dissensus that ultimately creates and generates the inaugural and unanticipated moment that introduces real change.
And so, if the self-negating pattern of repetition admits and generates a radical openness to the future that creates a pathway to the politically New, this admittedly is most sensible within “the immanent frame,, which an disenchanted socio-political imaginary expresses a belief in the self-sufficiency of the natural order, wherein we experience ourselves as political subjects as standing alone without the eternal, transcendent, or supernatural. Although it is thoroughly materialist, this immanence is not a deflationary worldview, but one that readily admits to the possibility of the miracle, “a kind of punctual hole blown in the regular order of things from outside, that is, from the transcendent.”17 Indeed, something is missing if we adopt a fully closed immanence, narrowed to the point of subjecting ourselves to the peculiarly modern malaises: frailty of meaning, the inability to solemnize collective moments of passage, and the emptiness of the ordinary. Pickstock gestures to the political impact of this in her defense of the transcendent aspect of repetition, that is, the repetition of the eternal:
Ironically, the need for ontological hierarchy arises within the apparent democracy of pantheistic immanence, rather than for theistic transcendence. For if there is only one finite reality, one must seek out the dominant factor within this reality, But the admission of transcendence like the monarchy relative leveling of class and prevention of oligarchy, puts into perspective all lesser hierarchal distinctions but perhaps leaves in place an unresolved oscillation between different ontological elements, none of which may assume the upper hand” (59–60).
But, is there not some sort of remainder, some traumatic leftover, not absorbed or traversed by the inner analogical gesture of repetition that affects the unity of difference to identity, constitutive of non-identical repetition? Pickstock seems to agree with the implied Hegel’s resistance to Deleuze: any reference to pure difference is actually identity of the selfsame sort. Difference constitutes identity as such, or as Žizek says, “an entity is perceived as ‘(self-)identical’ when (and only when) its virtual support is reduced to a pure difference,”18 thereby any the politics of repetition is one “without reserve”—and whose radical reflexivity is brought in its repetitive structure. When it comes to identity, the problem of repetition is not the relation of sameness to difference, but rather the retroactive character of repetition’s effect on identity. For Žizek, it comes down to understandings of temporality, not in terms of linear casualty but as Hegelian retroactivity, which reconstitutes identity by repeating it within a parallax frame. This links the effects of repetition on identity directly to the paradox surrounding the political Act:
in our ordinary activity, we effectively just follow the (virtual-fantasmatic) coordinates of our identity, while an act proper is the paradox of an actual move which (retroactively) changes the very virtual “transcendental” coordinates of its agent’s being—or, in Freudian terms, which does not only change the actuality of our world, but also “moves its underground.”19
And so, repetition is that experience of instrinsic alterity where difference retroactively and appears to be the same only within parallactic perspective: “although nothing changes, the thing all of a sudden seemed totally different.” It is only that under the auspice or appearance of a self-negating repetition of difference “in which a thing remains the same in its actuality” that the New is created. But how is it to recognized as being genuinely New?
The self-reflexive negativity of difference, in this way, is quite formally antagonistic, and it is this characteristic that suggests that it may indeed by promising for those of who really seek change, who create, live, speak, and act in order to rupture the Same and inaugurate the rise of that something that is really, really New. But how does the repetition of difference generate “really existing” change? How does it contribute to the emergence something really New when we can easily see that “things really change not when A transforms itself into B, but when, while A remains exactly the same with regard to its actual properties, it imperceptibly “totally changes”? Repetition is indeed real insofar as it establishes the minimal difference iterated between the thing and itself. Repetition does not change actuality because it brings up again the repressed “content” of truth hidden from recollection, but because it is only through repetition that the traumatic gaps constitutive of the real are able to show themselves—or rather be shown by critical processes of negative dialectical thought. Repression of trauma then is apocalyptic, rather than messianic, in its disclosure by repetition. The truth of repetitive difference, as such, is that the inherent antagonism that demands identity, asserts non-identity and does through returning again and again to the beginning, if only to repeat the unbearable failure. And so one way of reading what Žizek calls, “the Nothing that is the subject”; is that it is the gap of repetition that divides the Thing from itself, creating the space for the New to emerge, making authentic Acts possible by shifting the currently available choices.
Conclusion
I do not disagree with Pickstock’s reological thesis on repetition, in large part because I am willing to admit to not fully understanding it, even after multiple readings. I do however wonder how it relates to specific instances—or if you will, iterations—of repetition in more strictly political terms. I have tried to draw some of those themes out in the preceding pages, and humbly look forward to Pickstock’s response, and of course, her corrections. My own sense of repetition is that it is far more political than reological, more material than ideal, and so less (but also more) theological than she suggests. Perhaps these are false choices. My lingering concern, if I may hazard this, is that there is an inherently conservative and/or nostalgic impulse to Pickstock’s distinctly reological take on repetition, to be contrasted with an immanent and/or materialist one, intimated in a broadly Hegelian-Žizek manner, which is more prone to interpret repetition as a historical phenomena wherein the self-reflexive negativity of the Real upends itself, widening the traumatic gap from which the New emerges, and the Act is made possible once again.
Catherine Pickstock, Repetition and Identity (Cambridge, UK: Oxford University Press, 2014).↩
Pickstock’s use of analogy to mediate the relation of same and difference in the repeating of the thing is meant to ensure that repeating does not favors one more than the other (52). I am uncertain if Pickstock actually responds to Deleuze’s rejoinder, that such a reading of difference (as a variation on the same) is but an “appeal to same at the expense of difference,,” other than to say that she disagrees—with good reason.↩
Pickstock’s model for resolving this, which she readily admits as an aporia, is Platonic model of methexis whereby “Eternal truth…is the weaving of the one with the two, the same with the different” which, incidentally admits to the mysterious and problematic character of the real (52–53).↩
For on this idea of “fiction” with specific reference to its impact on political-theological work today, see Simon Critchley, Faith of the Faithless: Experiments in Political Theology (London, UK: Verso, 2012), 81–92.↩
Elsewhere, Pickstock queries, “Is it possible to live a human life as an integral “non-identical repetition,,q to realize a consistent but creative habit, to realize cosmic purpose, and to disclose the divine?” One can easily see here how her theory of ‘the Repeated Self’ is really a theology. This is not remarkable, except that the repetition of God becomes constitutive of all other repetitive forms. It is the participation of the self in the repetitions of God that allows for it to repeat itself, and so gain the integrity, reliability, and cogency requisite for meaningful (and as she will argue eventually, virtuous) human existence?↩
This is not surprising given the well-documented disagreements between Pickstock, John Milbank (her partner in the Radical Orthodox project) and Slavoj Žizek. See Žizek and Milbank, ed. Monstrosity of Christ and Pickstock’s essay, “Liturgy and the Senses” in Paul’s New Moment: Continental Philosophy and the Future of Christian Theology (Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Academic, 2010), 125–45.↩
Cited in Slavoj Žizek, “The Most Sublime of Hysterics” in Interrogating the Real (London: Continuum, 2005), 42; See G.W. F. Hegel, Philosophy of History, translated by J. Sibree (New York: Dover Publications, 1956), 313.↩
More should be said here, certainly. Suffice it to say that I have in mind the line of revolutionary thought that links Johann Baptist Metz to Slavoj Žizek through Walter Benjamin’s understanding that the hopeful future of political justice—the eschatological redemption of the past—lies with the remembering of the suffering of the dead.↩
See Slavoj Žizek, Absolute Recoil (London: Verso, 2014), and Slavoj Žizek, Less than Nothing, (London: Verso, 2012).↩
Žizek, Less than Nothing, 504.↩
Žizek,, 502.↩
Marx mistakenly cites Hegel here: “Hegel remarks somewhere that all great world-historic facts and personages appear, so to speak, twice. He forgot to add: the first time as tragedy, the second time as farce.”↩
Slavoj Žizek, “Shoplifters of the World, Unite!” London Review of Books, August 18, 2011: http:/C:/dev/home/163979.cloudwaysapps.com/esbfrbwtsm/public_html/syndicatenetwork.com4.lrb.co.uk/2011/08/19/slavoj-Žizek/shoplifters-of-the-world-unite↩
“Only the wrong choice creates the conditions for the right choice.” Žizek, Less than Nothing, 290. Also, see 68–70, and 205–07.↩
Žižek, “The Most Sublime of Hysterics” in Interrogating the Real, 41.↩
Žizek, First as Tragedy, Then as Farce, 86–87.↩
Charles Taylor, The Secular Age (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University, 2007), 547.↩
Slavoj Žizek, “Deleuze’s Platonism: Ideas as Real.” http:/C:/dev/home/163979.cloudwaysapps.com/esbfrbwtsm/public_html/syndicatenetwork.com4.lacan.com/zizplato.htm↩
Žizek, Less than Nothing, 214.↩
Margaret B. Adam
Response
In Search of Death
ACCORDING TO REPETITION AND IDENTITY, to be a thing is to repeat, differently but recognizably, the same. Persons—and all other things, are persons and all other things, in continuity that incorporates and perseveres through change. Catherine Pickstock shows how the perseverance of life is sustained in God’s eternal creating and through Christ’s once and always saving. She sketches thingness, person-ness, with light strokes, to allow for ongoing changes and the limitations of human perspective. She highlights with bolder strokes the particularity of persons that marks the constancy of personal identity. And she situates all identities, individually and gathered together as one, in Christ, affirming Kierkegaard’s proposal that “human identity, and the identity of all things . . . is secured through the historical reduplicating, and so continuous representation of the atonement achieved by the God-Man” (147).
Pickstock’s emphasis on the continuation of life reflects an understanding of salvation and God’s eternal glory, which she shares with Kierkegaard and some Patristic writers, that with Christ, all things will be well: “everything returns as good in the identical repetition of time by eternity” (182). A superficial reading of the book might give the impression that Pickstock supposes the sort of universal salvation that leads with eschatological optimism and downplays both death and the resurrection victory of the dead. We sometimes see this approach when Easter is celebrated without Holy Week, Good Friday and Holy Saturday, or when (as was the case in one church I attended) confession is always omitted from worship because it dampens the positive feelings of the Eucharist. There is nothing glib or simplistic about Repetition and Identity, and it deserves more—as well as more careful—readings. And yet, multiple readings have not revealed a substantive role for death in this account of life. Does death ever threaten and challenge the repetition of things? Is it ever the case that death, in Repetition and Identity, so thoroughly breaks the non-identical repetition of a person that continuity beyond time seems impossible, and the efficacy of the seems beyond reach?
Nature, in Repetition and Identity, seems not to die at all. Pickstock describes nature’s undulation, the wave-like, serpentine character of a non-identically repeating thing which moves and regathers itself, changes and remains the same as the very nature of its being. The very character of natural life connects what might seem like the death of one organism to the life of another. “The generative self-shaping of the organism [is] still somewhat subordinate to an ongoing work of regeneration in which the ‘next’ organism repeats the internal genetic processes of the preceding one, while also repeating its external form or general habitude” (34). This rhythm of ordering and transitioning, of continuity through difference, gives the impression that what might have been death is already preempted by new generation, and therefore not really death.
If we were to extend the images of regenerating organisms to things which are persons, we might anticipate a more distinct death, at least a pause between the end of an individual’s life and whatever there might be afterwards, rather than the no-gap-at-all undulation of a flower’s fading and its re-incorporative, regenerative new life in the soil. The death of a person might be an end which clarifies the identity that was continuing in non-identical repetition. And, for those still alive, another’s death might be a sign of what it is to be alive oneself. Pickstock notes from the beginning of the book that to live is to distinguish one from another: “To inhabit our finitude and be reconciled with it, we need to identify external objects (including other subjects), and we have, in a mirroring manner, to identify ourselves. The external acts of recognition, and our internal access to a specific identity, seem to depend upon one another” (1). Accordingly, might think of death as distinguishing life from non-life, and of life as that which is framed by the edges of death.
Pickstock, however, does not make a connection between distinguishing oneself as a matter of self-identification and establishing the edges of life and death. She argues against the possibility of discovering one’s definitive moment of beginning or ending, and she points out the impossibility of finding one’s own edges. While she recognizes the desire to establish the origin of a thing and its first repetition, she explains that people, like all things, are created by God who has no beginning or end. Persons, therefore, can claim neither an identity prior to a first repetition, nor a first repetition, since the source of a person’s identity and repetition has no beginning. Similarly, she argues, we cannot identify the last, closing repetition of a thing. “The quest for the hidden place of pure original inspiration, and the elaboration of a culminating crown in the concluding future, summon a circular journey where the going out is also the return. Transcendence is invoked in the coincidence of both gestures” (156). God meets creation in that coincidence, as Jesus Christ, God Incarnate; humans meet true humanity. To fulfill true human identity, one must be a disciple of Christ, to non-identically repeat his life through the particulars of one’s own life. To regard oneself is to regard Christ, and “the only way to regard Christ is in a sense to become him, to reduplicate him as a disciple and an apostle” (146–47). It would seem then that death, in Repetition and Identity, is not at the edge of a person (even if we could discern the edge); but God is, and God has no edges.
Looking elsewhere, we might interpret Pickstock’s account of Adam and Eve in the Garden as experiencing a kind of death when they refuse to participate in God’s creation (176). Non-participation means non-repetition, on the terms of Repetition and Identity, and non-repetition means non-existence.
Because Eve and Adam have refused the procedure of continuity in time itself—namely, participation in the glory of God—they cannot themselves recoup this procedure by an individual action which would vainly seek to express it through recapture. Rather, God himself must rehearse to undo their lapse (176).
God undoes the lapse through Jesus Christ: Mary accepts, for Israel, the invitation to participate in the glory of God and receives the Incarnation, the human life that is divinity. Mary is thus the mother of the life which does not die, the life that reverses the refusal of Adam and Eve.
God here restores to us continuity through recapitulation, a restoration which itself opens us to our own innocent desire to recapitulate, or non-identically repeat. The recapitulatory action reaches its climax when a human being, Jesus Christ, “impersonated” (or “hypostasized”) by the divine Logos, is obedient to God the Father in his weakness, dangling on the tree of death, thereby undoing through backwards traverse Adam’s disobedience to God and loss of the tree of life, when he was in a position of created strength (180).
If Adam and Eve’s refusal is their death, then perhaps it is the first death, the one that Christ’s death reduplicates through his fully human and fully divine death, which reincorporates and restores human life. Christ’s Passion and death might be the non-identical, reconstituting repetition of Adam and Eve’s refusal-death; this time death would not lead to separation from God, but to eternal closeness with God. But, Pickstock would likely note that not only can humans not find their origin and originary repetition, they also cannot—need not—determine the first death and its first repetition. The origins and ends she describes are in and of the Triune God. Their repetitive motion—their existence—carries persons over and through any threat of death. Adam and Eve and the rest of us continue repeating, thanks to the undoing and redoing of Jesus Christ. Reform, rather than death, characterizes the return, restoration, and recapitulation in Repetition and Identity. Christianity itself is a “movement of endless re-forming and repairing a broken, but never completely ruined prior reality” (175). Adam and Eve’s refusal to participate in God’s creation is not a death that completely ruins reality.
Death can be understood as stopping life. When Paul Griffiths, in his 2012–13 Stanton Lectures on “The End,” explores human death, he describes it as the separation of body and soul, when the person no longer is a person, no longer is at all. This death is a complete stop. The person ceases to be a person, because neither the body alone or the soul alone is the person. Death as the cessation of a person might be, in Pickstock’s terms, when the non-identical repetition of the person comes to a complete stop, when there is no more repetition of any sort. No more undulation, no more movement and return, gathering and regathering, or continuity—whether identical or nonidentical. A dead person would be a thing that does not repeat. In this case, the resurrection of the body might reinstate the person as repeatable, as the reunion not only of body and soul but also of a consistent, continuing identity. Life after death might be life begun again, repeating again; new life in Christ eternal might be compared to jumpstarting a heart.
Pickstock does not posit death as the separation of body and soul or death as non-continuity, non-repetition; but she does address the character of repetition in eternal life, and at some points it seems that the eternal life of repeating-identity persons aligns with the eternal life of a person as reunited body and soul that Griffiths describes. His description of the end of a person at the end of time involves no more change, and we might imagine that identically-repeating person after death, beyond time, as one who no longer needs the non-identical repetition necessary for existing in time and space. Repetition and Identity death might be the transformation from this life’s non-identical repetition to eternal life’s identical repetition with God, after the death of time and change. However, Pickstock seems to lean more toward a life of non-identical repetition for persons who are embraced by God’s infinite and eternal identical repetition. Thus, there would be no stop or death of non-identical repetition, but reformed, renewed, and ongoing non-identical repetition through Jesus Christ, who allows persons to move into a fuller participation in God’s divine reality.
Surely, if there is death anywhere, it is Jesus Christ’s deadly, all-the-way dead, death on the cross, but when Pickstock refers to Christ on the cross, she does not address pain, suffering, loss, or the utter absence of life. Instead, she offers the Patristic image of Christ as the corrective to the Fall, which is a perversion of the non-identically repetitive, undulating movement that is truest to creation.
The allegorical association of Christ with the figura of the serpent, at once natural and artificial (taken up by many Church Fathers), suggests that the devil’s imitation of the serpent was a false copying of the human and cosmic Urform, the form of the res as such, which has been philosophically situated as “serpentine” in character. Christ’s crucifixion inverts this inversion through recapitulation, and allows the true created serpentine progress to be resumed, removing even the curse from the ground (or from material reality) made by God after the Fall (183).
Christ’s death is more of a pivotal serpentine turn than a definitive death; it is a divinely radical reconstitution of existence. Death is already redeemed. Life is already renewed. Any apparent break in identity is pre-mended and carried through by the Holy Spirit. Christ’s life and death seem to repeat—in a divinely intensified manner—the always-already regeneration of the natural world.
This brief search of Repetition and Identity for death in all the usual death places has not uncovered a death so devastating as to render any hope for life impossible, save for the imponderably salvific love of God. The book’s emphasis on the continuity of identity seems to soften the sharpness and lessen the loss of death. A person remains a person; continuity does not end, but continues in an ebb and flow of passage and renewal. There is little suspense about the ongoing constitution of persons and all things, before, within, and after time and space. Instead, a dead person resembles the “mostly dead” condition of Westley in “The Princess Bride.” The less savvy audience fears he will die a permanent death; the more savvy audience knows that “mostly dead” allows for the revivification that the plot requires. Repetition and Identity shows how God sustains the life of all persons and all things through Jesus Christ, through non-identical repetition ever moving toward the culmination of truest identity in the presence of God. In the main, certainty of continuity overshadows and subsumes death to the extent that death has no sting to lose, and the defeat of death is of little consequence.
There is one section of the book in which Pickstock points toward a death that exercises some dominion that only Christ could defeat. In chapter 5, in the midst of describing the repeated self, Pickstock cautions against human attempts at identical-repetition in this life, in which acquiescence to impersonal uniformity washes out the particularity of non-identical repetition.
If human life consisted in these quasi-identical repetitions, and no other, it would be comprehensively bureaucratic, technologized, and capitalized. We would be docketed, tracked, and timetabled, and would become substitutable for everyone else in the manner of capitalist wage slaves or communist cadres. We would identically repeat others, and in principle any person could repeat any other. Moreover, the inhabited life of each person would be a mechanical performance, reiterated from minute to minute, day to day, year to year, and any vaunted variations would perhaps be irrelevant and irregular or even illegal distractions. (88.)
Pickstock’s scenario is only partly speculative; it is also, chillingly, a realistic image of contemporary life. This is the backdrop for a perversion of repetition that eliminates particularity and exhibits the most deadly death I can find in the Repetition and Identity. The inhabitants of this world of substitutable identity long to escape it and the death of particularity it imposes. Those desiring to escape cannot ever reach beyond the “regulated and commodified” options for escape, the set experiences of difference that are really identical repetition in holiday wrapping. Pickstock draws on the novels of Robbe-Grillet and Bolano to illustrate the worst manifestation of escape in this context: illicitly authorized sexual violence against women (88–89). Privileged and powerful men can try to fulfill their desire for non-identically repeated individuality by destroying women, by ending what shreds of particularity the women might sustain in a world of substitutability and imposing on them the identity of abused object. She observes that “it is as if the ‘escape’ which men have sought from tedium and regret has evolved away from the creation of fictional ideals, especially of women . . . towards the negative refusal which is realized as an act of violence, and especially violence against real women, who can never coincide with ideal ones” (89). The supposed escape of sexual violence against writes over any previous identity of the women, who become exchangeable, already destroyed, objects for destruction.
The abused women do not continue or repeat as themselves; they do not continue. The end of this repetition is death.Pickstock observes that, “if an individual person could not ‘act otherwise,’ or adopt another role, she would be reduced to one role and so be substitutable, and would be no more than a human atom in an ongoing social continuum” (92). They have been erased as they were and subsumed into another, for the other’s futile attempts at escape.
The 1995 movie, “Strange Days” provides another vivid example of death-by-identity-erasure, in which the desperate desire for non-identical identity motivates a murder of sexually violent, forced identical repetition. This film follows the use and abuse of a product, Squid, that records and shares experiences. One person wears a brain-wave recording device while engaged in an appealing (marketable) activity, sunbathing on a tropical beach or riding a roller coaster. The recorder sells the recorded experience to a broker of identically-repeatable experiences, who then sells the recordings to those who want to have those experiences on demand, without traveling or otherwise setting up the circumstances. In the increasingly bleak, dangerous, anarchical near-future world of “Strange Days,” there are few possibilities for thriving, for non-identical repetition; and the market for the fulfillment of desires explodes, as does the number of Squid addicts. As one user explains: “This is not like TV only better, this is life. It’s a piece of somebody’s life. It’s pure and uncut, straight from the cerebral cortex. I mean, you’re there you’re seeing it, you’re doing it, you’re feeling it.”
Almost all the Squid users in the movie are men, and the featured experiences involve sex, violence, and murder (often all together). These users, like those in the novels above, act out their desire for escape by brutally annihilating women. The most vile character (of many) adapts the device so that he can violently rape a woman while simultaneously transmitting his experience to her. He savagely rapes her, and at the same time he forces her to see, do, and feel what he feels, as if she is raping herself. Then, he strangles her and produces a marketable Squid of his entire experience. It is a multifold murder, of her experience, her response, her body, her mind, and her identity. Pickstock wrote of the novels that, “if an individual person could not ‘act otherwise,’ or adopt another role, she would be reduced to one role and so be substitutable, and would be no more than a human atom in an ongoing social continuum” (93). In the movie, the woman’s role is reduced further. She is her own rapist and murderer. There is nothing left of her to repeat. This death defies certainty that all will be well, as there is no longer a person to repeat, no particularity to persist, nothing remaining to be regathered and recapitulated through Christ.
Outside of novels and films, myriads of people die torturous deaths that end the possibility for return, reparation, and recapitulation. There is nothing left to continue except the lament of those who remain. It is not clear that Repetition and Identity presents a Christological death and resurrection deep and broad enough to reach and restore the persons who annihilate and those they annihilate. I am grateful for this chance to receive clarification and guidance from the author herself.
2.2.15 | Catherine Pickstock
Reply
A Response to Margaret Adam
I am very grateful to Margaret Adam for her response to my book. She appreciates well my attempt to take a “light” approach to the “heavy” matter of ontology; my denial that there can be any “thing” before repetition and so any “first repetition,” alongside my linking of non-identical repetition to a metaphysics of self-renewing life. Here I have tried to learn from immanentistic vitalists such as Deleuze, yet have suggested that vitalism is better guaranteed by the affirmation of a transcendent source of life; this ensures that one does not need to absolutise either the past, the present, or the future, nor a seamless process of “undulation” itself, in abstraction from all its particular moments. Rather, things only have identity as both continuous and changing, yet all the “moments” of this process remain, in finite terms, ultimate. In the end, the “holding together” of things derives from their participation in the eternal forms or ideas in the mind of God—where, for Aquinas, things exist more absolutely and perfectly than they do in themselves.
For this reason, Adam is rightly discerning to say that, for me, “death is not the edge of a person, but God is, and God has no edge.” This is indeed exactly how I see things, though I would add that the unbounded character of God does not imply a kind of vague and tasteless soup, but rather the most distinct and yet infinite and pluriform flavour imaginable—though of course unimaginable for us. This must surely contrast with a pagan or modern atheist perspective for which indeed death must define life, and life is given shape only by its whole course in time. Rather, a religious perspective (of almost any kind) can more readily face up to the fact that lives often or perhaps always end prematurely, leaving behind much unfinished business, many loose ends, irresolutions of character and unmended relationships. The heart of a person can therefore often seem to lie more in the threnody of their best aspirations, their stuttering commencements, than in their life-story seen as a rounded whole.
In this sense, therefore, to deny that death is the true “edge” of life is to allow its interruptive gravity, on which Adam so rightly insists, and about which I may well not have said enough in this particular book. If life, as a gift from the God of infinite, super-abundant life, is inherently undying, then its horror consists partially in a rebellion against God, and so an attempted denial of reality. Yet it still more consists in the fact that, in some fashion, this rebellion succeeds; reality is indeed thwarted or apparently re-arranged.
Here, for me, is the hub of the issue which Adam raises. She rightly insists both on the undeniable reality and the undeniable terror of death. But my main response to her would consist in the counter-question: does not insisting on the one tend to downplay the other? In other words, the more one says that death is so unavoidably real that it is final and unalterable, the more one can reduce its character as terrible: it may sink to the level of simply a natural, biological fact to which we can be resigned by saying that one will never live to suffer one’s own death, and one can find ritual and substitutionary ways to deal with the loss of others. But the more one says that death is terrible, then the more one actually starts to think of it as unnatural and in a way uncannily unreal; it scarcely squares with the infinite value of a beloved and ontologically irreplaceable person that they should just, on one particular day, vanish, never to reappear on earth again. Thus, when one sees a body in a morgue, one’s spontaneous phenomenological reaction, like that of any “primitive” person, is to see a body from whom the life, the spirit, has fled to an unknown elsewhere, rather than to see a mere body that has simply come to a full stop.
It is religious belief, rather than atheism, which tends to sustain this experience of death as horror, as something that should not be, something that cannot be squared with the dignity of a conscious, feeling, reasoning mode of existence. Hence, within Christian theology, death as we know it is regarded as a violation of the originally intended created order and so in some sense as unnatural and even as unreal. To think otherwise would be to over-positivise death, in a way that also runs against its phenomenological manifestation as uncanny absence and ellipsis.
It is here notable that where theology has seen death as fully natural and real, it has not seen it as terrible. This would be the death that never occurred of an unfallen Adam which would simply (according to Patristic and Mediaeval theology) denote his passage from the earthly paradise to eternal beatitude. But the post-fall death which he does suffer, is, for the tradition, bound up with his wilful fault and the consequences of that fault: by trying to be autonomous in terms of a secure identical repetition, humanity has cut itself off from the divine and vital source of self-renewal. So, static identity turns out to be termination—whether the sterile acts of possessive evil or the sterility of bodily death. Adam has here very well understood my claim that, in our own time, this sterility tends especially to be enacted by men as violence against women: a negative attempt to assert individuality in the face of identically repeated flattening, which ironically takes the form of trying to control and obliterate female difference and personal specificity.
So for the ancient tradition, as for my perspective, the key tension is that death both is and yet cannot be—without the latter qualification it would be real and yet not terrible. However, Adam rightly insists that it is both. My only qualification of her insistence is that it cannot be fully terrible if it is an unambiguous natural terminus, or something which just as fully exists as does life. And the latter is not the case even in biological terms (since biology as yet still knows of no “reason” for death), nor philosophically, since death is not a “something,” not even an event (as Wittgenstein rightly realised), but merely the absence of something.
Theology has read this negativity of death in terms of an aberrance: spiritual creatures and even (as for Origen) all creatures whatsoever are destined to “crown” their wavering repeated continuity in an eternal repetition which will lie unchangeably beyond our normal contract of the dynamic with the static (since this can only apply to the finite). Death is an interruption of this crowning. Yet, since the divine reality and the divine will (which is at one with this reality) cannot truly be frustrated, there has to be a sense in which this interruption is an illusion. As soon as Adam and Eve have departed from the garden, the process of restoring them to garden in the midst of the descended heavenly city has begun. Otherwise, there could be no life or continuing creation at all. Just because life is inherently auto-sustaining, the mark of the limit of death as catastrophe is the very continuance of life. In a similar way, the fall cannot issue (as some Reformers supposed) in total depravity, for otherwise there would be no continued specifically human existence whatsoever. To think otherwise would falsely be to suppose a possible human existence without ethics, without some attempt to define the good, just as to imagine that the reign of death over life is total would be to reduce life to a mechanism which eventually winds down, and indeed both Protestantism and Jansenism encouraged just such philosophies at certain points.
To the extent that death is not just an illusion, but all too real a rupture, often heralded and echoed by great pain, as Adam rightly says, then this, for theology, is paradoxically because it is not just negative. Death is indeed the result of sin, but it is also a partial remedy for sin. In every sphere, the inadequate and flawed come to an end just by that token of partiality, through a grim kind of homeopathy. Identical repetition is sinister, but has also a limited capacity for self-renewing. It will eventually halt itself or be halted. Similarly, mortals will die a death they cannot see beyond and in this way their fallen and damaging lack of vision has a terminus.
Suffering this terminus in part gives us a chance to repent of the death we have dealt to others, and even more to ourselves by this very dealing. The development of Kierkegaardian repetition into Pauline recapitulation in my book is supposed to indicate that one cannot blithely carry on as if nothing bad or terminal had ever happened, nor sustain the originally innocent serpentine impulse of life without now being back upon or “working through” past rupture. Hence, with Irenaeus and Origen, I was trying to insist on the need to pass through rupture, to relive Adam’s desecration of the tree of life by participating in the cross of Christ. Loss, death, tragic sundering (and Adam does not mention my discussion of the tragic in Kierkegaard) and mourning must all be passed through, if life is non-identically to renew itself. On the other hand, it is just because this possibility of self-renewal has not really been killed—just as God has not been killed, even though he has undergone death as Man—that one can indeed pass through and beyond death. Otherwise, its victory would be total and we would know nothing of it, including its horror, because, along with everything else, we simply would not be at all.
So in formal terms, I think that my book sufficiently recognises the instance of death, though in terms of substantive tonality, more might have been intimated concerning the experience of anguish and discontinuity. There is also more to be developed on the matter of the relation between the continued life of a species and the death of an individual, as Adam suggests. However, the point made by Paul Griffiths, as quoted, would not seem to be quite right. Christian tradition has not asserted that personal existence unambiguously comes to an end with the sundering of soul from body at death, implying thereby that immortality and resurrection would be a fresh and miraculous creation ex nihilo of the “same” person by a mere divine fiat. This would surely imply an invidious and arbitrary “identical repetition” of the highest metaphysical register, where, on the contrary, theology has insisted on both the immortality of the soul and the resurrection of the body, just because the divine eternal intention of our eventual beatitude cannot be either changed or thwarted.
It is true that there have been different opinions about whether personhood resides in the soul or in the soul-body compound, but even Aquinas, who argues the latter position, allows that the soul can exist and know, albeit imperfectly, without the body after death, even though the strange circumstance that the very immortality of the rational soul that is also the “form” of a body, requires ineluctably the eventual resurrection of the body. (See the highly sophisticated discussions of these points in Marie de L’Assomption, L’Homme, Personne Corporelle: La spécificité de la personne humanine chez Thomas d’Aquin). Of course, one can find this account of eschatological timing a little odd and awkward, and in Repetition and Identity I leant more towards Origen’s affirmation of the immortality of the body also.
In summary, it is just because life and rational creatures cannot die that death is such an abyssal horror and contradiction. And Adam is right: its moment cannot be evaded and there is for us no renewal of growth without suffering its thwarting. But life and death, growth and decay do not lie on a single flattened and positively univocal ontological level, any more than victory and defeat, good and evil or God and the lure of nullity.