Symposium Introduction
Metaphilosophical Skepticism and its Discontents
It is a common enough occurrence, whether between philosophy professors, in the graduate seminar, to open an introduction to philosophy class, or just as a cultural cliché, to observe that philosophers have been debating some topic for a long time, and they will continue to do so to no avail. But the question of what follows from this simple truism is rarely pursued. In this book, János Tőzsér argues that the continued disagreement between philosophers defeats their claims to know philosophical truths.
A good deal of this line of argument is posited on the commitment that philosophy’s main objective is to know deep realities about ourselves and the world. Surely, philosophy could have other goals—to merely express oneself, to think otherwise, or to be a cultural gewgaw of novelty or pretense. But assuming that philosophers are out to figure things out, the persistence of disagreement is a problem. For sure, there have been some trivial progress in improved cases for some views and some more devastating refutations, and some new views and alternatives have emerged. But this is not the relevant sense of progress knowledge-seekers are after.
One could be steadfast in one’s philosophical commitments and hold, as Tőzsér puts it, “I am the only one” to get things right. One would have to then hold that despite the fact that the philosophers one dismisses were overwhelmingly geniuses and impressive arguers, you are the one who cut through it all. The trouble, of course, is that from the outside (say, if one heard another say this), it is more likely that one is suffering from a form of belief-bias or worse than has truly cut clear of the fray.
One could, alternately, adopt a kind of diffident view of the philosophical landscape and hold that the various alternatives are each appealing in virtue of how they achieve internal equilibrium between their pre-philosophical intuitions and the theories around them. But, as Tőzsér observes, not having room for commitment in the project strips philosophy of the value of knowledge it promised—the right to be sure and live in light of that commitment.
Tőzsér’s ultimate view to consider is that our position yields an aporia—we, as reflective beings interested in knowing the deep truths about ourselves and reality, are tragically caught. We cannot suspend our beliefs about our deep commitments, but it seems we must do so as rational creatures. But even this skeptical view is itself undercut by the disagreement problem. Skepticism (and meta-philosophical skepticism) is as controversial as any of the views the skeptic is skeptical about. What is the conscientious inquirer to do? We, as those who seek knowledge as philosophers, are tragically undercut by our own intellectual aspirations.
In this symposium, we will engage with János Tőzsér’s case on the merits of the various alternatives, and we will ask what the consequences are. Expect there to be further disagreements.
5.28.24 |
Response
Response to The Failure of Philosophical Knowledge
Breaking the Breakdown Down
The main achievement of Tőzsér’s book is the taxonomy of different metaphilosophical positions that attempt to deal with the problem of pervasive and permanent philosophical disagreement. It is true that many other philosophers have given a taxonomy, but they were either incomplete, undetailed or both. Tőzsér’s taxonomy seems to be complete with regard to how philosophers can react to the fact that they, during the whole history of philosophy, could not consensually establish substantive philosophical truths. No-one can write an “official” philosophy college textbook about how the world is or which are the norms that we must follow (in contrast, physicists can write textbooks about how the physical world is). Rather, philosophical textbooks can summarize the arguments for and against different positions and can give “if… then…”-type claims about how the different philosophical propositions relate to each other. Tőzsér sets out four types of reactions (which list seems to be exhaustive for me). The advocates of Wittgensteinian therapeutic philosophy claim that philosophical problems are meaningless so we should (after proper therapy) abandon philosophy in the face of the epistemic failure of philosophy and the lack of consensus. The proponents of meta-skepticism argue that philosophers must abandon forming philosophical beliefs about how the world is and which norms we should follow. Other philosophers who accept the so-called equilibrism insists that philosophers should abandon the aim of providing compelling arguments (a.k.a. arguments that would compel any sufficiently rational agent to believe in the substantive philosophical claim in question); and last but not least there are philosophers who believe that one should not abandon anything that is integral to the (classic) epistemic tradition of philosophy that aims at providing compelling justification for substantive philosophical propositions.
Tőzsér describes all metaphilosophical position shrewdly and elegantly so much so that the text is both illuminative, argumentative, and entertaining. The flipside of these virtues are that it is difficult to see what the problems with the arguments are, one has to step back from the creative and detailed descriptions of these positions, and critically detach the argumentation from its charming form. It is especially difficult to philosophically evaluate the very last part of the book which is a poignant confession about that in philosophy—for Tőzsér—was nothing left but a painful and daunting intellectual breakdown that is silent about what Tőzsér (or anyone) should do in philosophy after recognizing the failure of all reaction to the epistemic failure of philosophy. Yet, I think one has to try to go beyond the surface level of this book to see what is happening in the deep. One way to do this is to read the book not in the way that is suggested by the book’s elegant structure, but reading it in the opposite direction, reading backward so to speak, especially because it is a backward-looking book.
The text is written as if philosophers have done everything that is possible to do in order to provide compelling arguments for establishing substantive philosophical truths. Before the description of the breakdown, Tőzsér already showed that (i) the arguments for the claim that philosophical problems are meaningless are empty, (ii) meta-sceptics refute themselves because they should be skeptical also about whether everyone should suspend her substantive philosophical beliefs, and (iii) equilibrists should drop their beliefs in the truth of any substantive philosophical propositions if they can produce arguments which tell nothing more than that the proposition in question fits well with this or that other (unjustified) proposition. And what about those who Tőzsér calls “I’m the only one” philosophers? It is a bit trickier because Tőzsér does admittedly not provide such strong arguments as he does against the other three positions. Rather, he appeals to his moral aversions toward “I’m the only one” philosophers:
May I say, I don’t feel it right to become a man who takes views with absolute self-confidence on questions surrounded with permanent dissent, and doesn’t have the slightest doubt about things not being the way he believes them to be—who imagines himself to be epistemically superior to everybody else. And I don’t feel it right to become a man who thinks that all his interlocutors are unable to recognize the compelling force of his arguments, thinks that their “philosophical device” and “epistemic equipment” are faulty, and simply declares that their intuitions and fundamental pre-philosophical convictions are deceptive—who considers everybody disagreeing with him his epistemic inferior. I feel that it would be wrong—not just a bit, but very wrong—to become a man like this, and that’s why I reject the “I’m the only one” view. (116)
You can see that this confessional part of the text—as, in fact, the whole book—is written from the backward-looking perspective of the (confessional) end of the book. What this brief quote (and the whole book) presupposes that a philosopher who aims at providing a compelling justification for a substantive philosophical belief does basically the same thing as all the other philosophers of the past and the present, and proposes more or less the same type of arguments as everyone before her. If this were the only one perspective that is available for the “I’m the only one” philosophers, then it would be pathetic and even intellectually abhorrent to be such a philosopher because in this case the whole position would be nothing else than pure narcissism based on the unjustified belief that she, the philosopher, is special—an intellectual superhero so to speak.
However, this is not the only perspective that is available for the “I’m the only one” philosopher. What is more, the numerous quotations that can be found in Tőzsér’s book show that this is never the perspective that the “I’m the only one” thinkers actually adopt. Rather, they adopt a forward-looking perspective. They are not preoccupied by the past (even if they are dissatisfied with its lack of philosophical results), but they focus on the future as an open field with full of philosophical potentials that are waiting for someone to exploit them. They do typically not regard themselves as special epistemic agents (with the possible exception of Nietzsche who explicitly praises his intellectual virtues in Ecce Homo); on the opposite, they see themselves as ordinary rational agents whose only advantage to other philosophers is that they have a better access to the field of philosophical possibilities. Most probably (but not necessarily) because they think they found a new method to see and capture these possibilities. And how do they explain that they are the ones who found the new revolutionary method? If they were to think that it is because they are exceptional geniuses with special epistemic properties, then it would be in tension with their belief that they, eventually, will persuade other philosophers about the truths that they hope to establish. Instead, it is much more rational to them to explain this by sheer luck or some external circumstances. For example, Descartes believed that the combination of three circumstances led him to find his method: first, he had exceptional education which showed the permanent and pervasive disagreement between philosophers and, second, he had a character from the beginning that did not let him to think that he has better epistemic qualities than others, and last but not least, he did not have a personal tutor who persuaded him that one of traditions of philosophers better than any other ones (Descartes 1637/2006, 15–16). This combination of circumstances forced him to develop a new philosophical method. Because one needs nothing special to use his new method, Descartes could hope that everyone, who has the opportunity and disposition to diligently using his method, would arrive the very same conclusions as he did regardless of one is a genius or not. Moreover, it seems to me, Descartes’ hope was not irrational at all because he did something that none other did before: systematically using radical skepticism in order to map what the most solid substantive philosophical propositions are. Based on all that he knew, it could be the case that using his method slowly persuades every expert to accept his conclusions. It has not happened this way, and his failure to persuade everybody might have been necessary, but Descartes was not a philosophical narcissist for not knowing that well before he tried to persuade other philosophers.
Under the surface, Tőzsér’s book is based on the conviction that nothing fundamentally novel can be done in philosophy. The huge problem with this conviction—and this is my main issue with this otherwise outstanding monography—that the book does not justify it at all. Tőzsér seems to think that if we could not establish substantive philosophical truths until now, it is reasonable to suppose that we will be unable to do that in the future. Tőzsér’s favorite formulation of this inductive pessimism is that the failure of philosophy in the past shows that “philosophy’s epistemic failure is that its truth-seeking and justificatory tools are inadequate and unsuitable for establishing substantive philosophical truths” (7). Nevertheless, this induction heavily relies on the presupposition that the tools of philosophy will be the same in the future as it were in the past. And Tőzsér’s book does not give a detailed picture on what the tools of philosophy are and why they should be the same forever.
Tőzsér could answer to all of this that his main concern is, in fact, not the sub specie aeternitatis insufficiency of philosophy, but its inability to justify our substantive philosophical beliefs right now. And this is why he has the intellectual breakdown at the end of the book, because he thinks that he has no reason to maintain any of his substantial philosophical beliefs. However, we could ask why he believed also that his intellectual breakdown is so interesting that it is not a waste of time to read a whole book about setting up this breakdown. I cannot imagine any other possible answer that Tőzsér has to believe deep down that he recognizes the insufficiency of philosophy and its relevance from a novel perspective. Even if the intellectual breakdown does not presuppose the belief in the novelty of the description of the properties and/or the origin of the breakdown, confessing it to the public arguably does.
Furthermore, it is interesting how much of an impact the failure of philosophy to produce compelling justifications has on Tőzsér. Most philosophers and other intellectuals, I hate to admit, just don’t care at all. They just believe whatever seems to be true for them based on their instincts or pet theories. Tőzsér’s whole book tries to shout to these nonchalant intellectuals that they should care about the fact that our dearest and deepest convictions are heavily debated and not justified at all. Nevertheless, this “should” can have a normative weight only if there is a robust ethics of belief in the background. Interestingly, the book has close to nothing to say about why we should care so much about insufficiency of philosophy, not to mention why we should care about that Tőzsér had an intellectual breakdown because of his diligent focus on the epistemic failure of philosophy. Perhaps breaking the breakdown down could be the breakout of philosophy from the prison of its past failures.
References
Descartes, René. 1637/2006. A Discourse on the Method. Translated by Ian Maclean. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1908/2007. Ecce homo. Translated by Duncan Large. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
6.4.24 |
Response
Evidences Beyond Conversation
Rethinking Phenomenological Evidence in János Tőzsér’s The Failure of Philosophical Knowledge: Why Philosophers are not Entitled to their Beliefs
In section 2.3 of chapter five of his The Failure of Philosophical Knowledge: Why Philosophers are not Entitled to their Beliefs, János Tőzsér describes a problem he calls “epistemic schizophrenia.” It entails these three dissonant claims: (1) S’s philosophical views are built on unjustified pre-philosophical convictions; (2) in light of (1), S is skeptical about her own ability to maintain her beliefs in epistemic good faith; and, (3) S recognizes that they are unable to give up their ungrounded pre-philosophical beliefs lest they fall into cognitive collapse (142). One way of responding to this problem is to see private evidences as phenomenological evidences mainly in an attempt to validate (1).
Tőzsér casts appeals to “private evidence” as appeals to “phenomenological evidence” as a possible vindication of the legitimacy of private evidence. The “specific phenomenology” Tőzsér describes is one of an “inner voice” inhabiting a knower which compels belief. According to Tőzsér, “private evidence” phenomenologically construed raises the following two problems: (a) what if one’s interlocutors make the same appeals to “private evidence?” Are not their appeals to their own private evidence just as legitimate as my own? Without any epistemic common ground to appeal to, it seems that no one can be justified in their belief if all we must rely on is testimony to some personal, incommunicable experience. (b) Why should I think that my inner voice is reliable? It is possible that one may fall into self-deceptive tendencies, in which case one’s truth-tracking capacity is perverted. Tőzsér suggests that there are no “right criteria” to tell apart the difference between “truth” reached through bias processes and truth proper. Therefore, the problem of epistemic schizophrenia still stands. In what follows, I will make explicit what I take to be some questionable implicit assumptions Tőzsér makes. For brevity’s sake, I shall call (a) the “commensuration problem” and (b) the “reliability problem.” I begin with a criticism of (b) which should nicely segue into the criticism of (a).
The problem I see with (b) is that Tőzsér’s understanding of “phenomenological evidence” as mere appeals to conscience is that self-trust (or, self-deception) becomes a problem only if we assume that that the truth idea is located squarely within the domain of cognitive processes. And, relatedly, this is why I think Tőzsér interprets “phenomenology” as “inner monologue”: it is the internal parallel to the reason-giving and asking model we do in conversation. When Tőzsér criticizes the reliability of first-person “inner voices” as lacking any “right criteria” for proper truth-tracking, I do not think that he has a model of mind and rationality which sees mind as some truth-tracking faculty. Rather, I think he assumes a conversationalist view of mind and rationality which takes communicability of reasons to be the hallmark of epistemic propriety, a view resembling Rortian conversationalism. Unlike private evidences for which there seems to be no “right criteria” for distinguishing good knowing from bad knowing, there is, I presume for Tőzsér, right criteria for distinguishing good knowing from bad knowing in the public space: it is presumably what survives intense rational criticism by one’s epistemic peers. Conversation seen as the space of rational criticism, of reason-giving and asking practices, is the ultimate tribunal for what shall come (or not) to pass for properly justified true belief. Thus, there are reliable belief-forming and reforming practices and methods we deploy when we are—and this is usually in fact the case—fraught with cognitive biases. We resort to rational criticism by our peers to serve as a corrective to potentially biased beliefs. I think that Tőzsér thinks that any suitable criteria for discriminating good knowing from bad knowing will turn to out to be an essentially public affair, a matter of conversation. Let me introduce a brief alternative way of thinking about phenomenological evidences to further draw out this point and underline one main problem with this assumption.
Tőzsér’s interpretation of “phenomenology” as “inner consciences” is optional. Use of the term “phenomenology” in analytic philosophy typically means “what it is like to be a such and so.”1 Under that description, Tőzsér’s criticism of private evidence as phenomenological evidence might be more problematic because certain people and groups of people do occupy epistemically privileged positions in relation to some others. This is the basic insight of standpoint epistemology. One could say this. In virtue of being located in the social space in a certain way, one thereby has certain experiences which confer legitimate knowledge and evidence to that knower which is, in principle, inaccessible to those who do not occupy that same position.2 To be sure, while such experiences are in some sense “private,” they are shared with others belonging to that same group. In turn, this means that concepts of reasons and evidences will become audience-relative. Thereby, experiences gain conceptual priority over reasons because reasons become accessible only if one has had the relevant experiences. If that is true, then I want to say that there is a “truthiness of experience” as such which is warranted and need make no appeals to some “inner conscience.” If the conversationalist view of rationality I have attributed to Tőzsér is right, we might ask these questions: “Why should I trust my ‘epistemic peers’ more than I trust myself if the basic insight of standpoint theory is true?” “What if what I take to be good reason does not register with my interlocutor? Are interlocutors who cannot see each other’s reasons as reasons ‘epistemic peers’ at all? Does this situation not undercut the idea of indiscriminate evidence and, further, to any claim to a single, unified epistemic community?” That was a brief excursion to show that appeals to phenomenological evidence made in a certain way do provide the epistemic assurance that Tőzsér thinks “inner voices” lack but this is not to be understood simply as a matter of cognitive bias. I will now connect these thoughts to say that Tőzsér’s thought that phenomenological evidences cannot solve the problems attached to “epistemic schizophrenia” might be implausible.
The reliability problem at its most basic poses the question “Can I trust myself?” I claim that this question is the internalized version of the question “Can I trust others?” To the extent that conversationalist views of mind and rationality entail a commitment to the idea that inquirers and knowers are bound by some sense of implicit trust, this seems not too far of an interpretive stretch. It is, then, the internalization of what we do in conversational practices which, to be sure, does have certain proper criteria we can and do appeal to in order to ensure that we “get it right.” The reason motivating Tőzsér to construe phenomenological evidences as “inner voices” rather than, say, the “what it is to be like a such and so” way is Tőzsér’s presumption of a roughly conversationalist view of mind and rationality. So, this is why “private justification” rings as an oxymoron. The problem with exorcising justification from the first-personal altogether was alluded to earlier in the context of the insight of standpoint theory. This leads nicely to why I think that the commensuration problem is also misguided.
The assumption motivating the commensuration problem is the assumption of a common ground for knowledge. That assumption might be redescribed as the assumption of the universal accessibility of warrant.3 Ideas and ideals of conversation, community, and commensuration form a triad whose mutual shared assumptions underwrite one another. Tőzsér’s criticism of “phenomenological evidence” as “inner monologue” goes through only if we assume that social justification is the only epistemically legitimate kind of justification. Otherwise put, it is the assumption that the communicability of reasons which is meant to ensure maximally democratic warrant is the sole locus of epistemic entitlement. Further, the implication is that only justification that is subject to rational criticism by one’s epistemic peers is the proper candidate for suitably trustworthy justification. I claim that there may be evidences beyond conversation and these are ones that phenomenological thinking seeks to vindicate.
I conclude by making a broader point about what I see as the potential stakes of my intervention. One lesson we might take from my understanding of Tőzsér is that we need not and in fact cannot jettison the private/public distinction. “Overcoming distinctions” moves are fashionable today, but we need not succumb to such intellectual trends. Thoughts such as Rortian conversationalism and Habermas’s theory of communicative rationality serve us well in the project of naturalizing mind and rationality, but they arguably leave us with an impoverished conception of mind and rationality. Rethinking the ideas of evidence, privacy, and publicity (qua criterion) as I have suggested might lead us in a different direction. The singular insight of phenomenological thinking is that first-person experience is philosophically indispensable and irreducible because we have reason to grant conceptual priority to experiences over reasons. Phenomenological thinking properly understood might provide us with a richer, more expansive conception of rationality and evidence beyond what passes muster in the normative space of giving and asking for reasons.
In the Continental tradition, one frequently finds phenomenological descriptions which make use of, as Tőzsér does, appeals to inner conscience, notably, for instance, in §56 of Heidegger’s Being and Time. At times, there seems to be terminological and conceptual slippage between use of the term “phenomenology” and its meaning between the two traditions.↩
See my “The Zetetic and Non-Ideal Epistemology” (2023). Also, see Rebecca Kukla, “Objectivity and Perspective in Empirical Knowledge,” Episteme: A Journal of Social Epistemology 3, no. 1 (2006): 80–95.↩
I take this redescription from Quill (writing under Rebecca) Kukla’s “Objectivity and Perspective in Empirical Knowledge” (2006).↩
6.11.24 |
Response
Putting Intuitions in Their Place
János Tőzsér’s book The Failure of Philosophical Knowledge is a somber reflection on the fact that philosophy is characterized by constant and all-encompassing disagreements between philosophers, and thus has failed to produce positive and substantive answers to philosophical questions. Tőzsér investigates the possible attitudes philosophers can have towards their own philosophical beliefs in light of this failure, but his sobering conclusion is that he can’t, in good intellectual conscience, identify with any of them.
Although I found myself agreeing with much of what Tőzsér says in this book, and his portrayal of metaphilosophical attitudes is both entertaining and illuminating, there is one point where I’m not satisfied with his picture of philosophy. I think that the role intuitions play in philosophy is more complex than he portrays it, and this threatens to undermine his objections to the metaphilosophical attitude he calls equilibrism (ch 5). Many contemporary philosophers do philosophy with the equilibrist attitude (121), and probably a great portion of Tőzsér’s readers identify with it, so it matters a lot whether it’s an adequate picture of what philosophers do, and whether it’s really as unjustifiable of an attitude towards our philosophical beliefs as he claims.
According to Tőzsér, philosophers with the equilibrist attitude accept the fact that philosophy is a failed epistemic enterprise, in the sense that it can’t give us knock-down arguments whose truth we can’t doubt and thus would force consensus. Equilibrists react to this fact by settling for more modest goals. They aim for developing well-formulated and consistent theories that are in harmony with their pre-philosophical intuitions and protecting them against counterarguments. According to the equilibrists, as long as a philosopher does this, they can rationally stick to their philosophical beliefs (124–25).
Tőzsér sympathizes with equilibrism, but he is unable to commit to it. His main complaint is that it doesn’t justify believing in the truth of our philosophical views about factual (as opposed to conceptual) questions (130), because the starting points of our theories—our intuitions—aren’t truth tracking. Tőzsér thinks our intuitions are biased—they are influenced by our upbringing, experiences and epistemic character—and so we can never be sure if the theories built on them are true (138–42).
I’m not convinced by this critique, because I think Tőzsér overgeneralizes what philosophers with this attitude do. He seems to think that (1) they always start theorizing with premises that come from pre-philosophical intuitions (122), that (2) those premises don’t need and can’t have justification (119; 134–36), and that (3) the intuitions behind them are biased, because the plausible explanation for people having different intuitions is that intuitions are influenced by factors that aren’t truth-tracking (139, 166–71). I don’t think this description is completely wrong, but it doesn’t apply to all cases. I doubt there is a unified way of using intuitions in philosophy, even among people with the same metaphilosophical attitude, and I suspect it greatly varies from subfield to subfield. I will only attempt to show one type of counterexample to Tőzsér’s description: arguments that draw a metaphysical conclusion from interpretations of scientific theories or, more generally, of what goes on in the sciences.
A representative example is Russell’s claim that there are no causal laws in physics. Here is a simplified reconstruction of one of his arguments (Russell 1913, 4–9):
P1: Causal laws connect types of events e1 and e2 such that given any event e1, there is an event e2 and a time interval τ, such that whenever e1 occurs e2 always follows after time interval τ, and events of type e1 occur more than once.
P2: There are no laws in current physics that connect types of events like e1 and e2.
K: There are no causal laws in current physics.
Another example is Brown’s argument (1984, 100–11) against the causal theory of knowledge based on experimental findings in quantum mechanics. His argument looks like this:
P1*: According to the causal theory of knowledge, knowledge of any x is based on sensory experience that causally connects the knower with x.
P2*: In the experiments of Aspect et al.1 we have knowledge of the measurement result at the far wing of the apparatus that isn’t based on causal contact.
K*: The causal theory of knowledge is wrong.
I take these arguments to be examples where the opponents agree on the formulation of the theory or concept in question (causal law, causal theory of knowledge) and what they disagree about is whether science actually confirms or disconfirms it. For example, Russell takes P1 to be a common view of causal laws that we can find both in everyday language and in the work of philosophers who believe there are such laws. Of course, it’s possible that Russell attributes views to his opponents they don’t actually hold, and I doubt that many contemporary philosophers would agree to this definition of causal laws. But even if someone thinks P1 and P1* aren’t good examples of common grounds between the arguing parties, what matters to my argument is that we grant that there exist arguments with such common grounds. For example, I think we could take any metaphysical theory of causal laws and construct an argument for or against it based on whether we think it fits the laws in physics (e.g. Norton 2006; 2.2).
My point is that if there are such arguments, then they don’t fit the mold of Tőzsér’s description. Let’s look at the premises in the examples! First, I take P1 and P1* to be articulations of philosophical concepts. Their role isn’t to be unjustified starting points of the authors’ philosophical equilibrium, rather, they are possible formulations of certain concepts and the assumed common ground between the arguing parties. Second, these are just one possible formulation of the concepts in question. And even if Tőzsér is right that the concepts in P1 and P1* have originated from pre-philosophical intuitions, it doesn’t matter to my current line of argument, because I think the question of which formulation of “causal law” we should accept is a conceptual one, and Tőzsér’s critique about the use of intuitions only targets factual questions.
Let’s examine P2 and P2*! It’s evident that they aren’t pre-philosophical convictions. Furthermore, they are justifiable—we can give arguments for why we interpret physical laws or experiments in a certain way, and both authors do that. The tricky question is whether these interpretations are influenced by biased intuitions. I deliberately choose examples where it’s really hard to construct a plausible explanation of how upbringing or life experiences influence Russell or Brown to interpret physics the way they do. If someone disagrees with the second premises, their disagreement probably comes from their belief that Russell and Brown made mistakes in interpreting the parts of physics in question, either because physics is neutral towards these metaphysical theses, or because it supports the opposite conclusion.
That leaves the vague notion of “epistemic character” or personal taste as possible bias factors in the justification of the second premises. And I’m happy to concede that they come into play in these type of premises (although it’s really difficult to show how exactly), precisely because our current scientific knowledge seems to be compatible with different competing ontologies (see French 2011, Musgrave 1992). In cases like that, it’s natural to include extra-theoretical criteria like parsimony, elegance or fit with our other theories in evaluating competing interpretations, and our judgement about those criteria are probably influenced by our taste and epistemic character.
That being said, this fact alone isn’t enough to conclude—as Tőzsér would have it—that we can’t believe in our philosophical theories, because these kinds of “bias” aren’t unique to philosophy. If the type of arguments I showed use intuitive judgements when interpreting scientific theories and drawing metaphysical claims from them, and if those scientific theories really underdetermine those metaphysical claims, then the situation is analogous to choosing between empirically equivalent theories in science (see Farr & Ivanova 2020; Ivanova 2017). So, contrary to Tőzsér’s aim (170), his criticism isn’t confined to philosophy. This allows the equilibrist to argue that their use of intuitions (at least this specific type) isn’t problematic, because the legitimation of the sciences extend to philosophy in these cases. Of course, one can reply that both cases are equally problematic and demand that scientists too stop believing in the truth of those theories where they appealed to intuitions. But they need more detailed argumentation for that.
So for Tőzsér to establish that the use of intuitions in philosophy (and only in philosophy) is so problematic that philosophers should stop believing in the truth of their theories about factual questions, he needs to say something about the analogous situations in the sciences. And to conclude that the use of intuitions makes equilibrism completely untenable, he needs to show that there is a uniform way philosophers use intuitions, or that all ways are equally problematic.
References
Brown, J. R. (1994). Smoke and Mirrors: How Science Reflects Reality. New York: Routledge.
Farr, M. & Ivanova, M. (2020). “Methods in Science and Metaphysics.” In The Routledge Handbook of Metametaphysics, edited by Bliss, R. & Miller, J., 447–58. New York: Routledge.
French, S. (2011). “Metaphysical underdetermination: why worry?” Synthese 180 (2): 205–21.
Ivanova, M. (2017). “Aesthetic values in science.” Philosophy Compass 12: e124–33.
Musgrave, A. (1992). “Discussion: Realism About What?” Philosophy of Science 59: 691–97
Norton, J. D. (2006). “Causation as folk science.” In Causation, Physics, and the Constitution of Reality: Russell’s Republic Revisited, edited by Price, H. & Corry, R., 11–44. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Russell, B. (1913). “On the Notion of Cause.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 13: 1–26.
Brown refers to the following papers in his argument: Aspect, A. et al. (1981). „Experimental tests of realistic theories via Bell’s theorem.” Physical Review Letters 47 (7), 460–3.; Aspect, A. et al. (1982a). „Experimental realization of Einstein—Podolsky—Rosen Gedankenexperiment: a new violation of Bell’s inequalities.” Physical Review Letters 49, (2).; Aspect, A. et al. (1982b). „Experimental test of Bell’s inequalities using timevarying analyzers.” Physical Review Letters 49 (25).↩
Jennifer Lowell
Response
Philosophical Failure
A Case in Point of Epistemic Injustice?
Tőzsér’s chapter “Philosophy With (Intended-To-Be) Compelling Justification” presents what he terms the “I’m the only one” response to philosophy’s pervasive failure to settle questions and find stable and genuine truths. Tőzsér points to this continual failure as manifesting in self-centered, almost messianic language that many ambitious philosophers have used to assert their projects as decisive accounts that trump (but rarely resolve or acknowledge) their predecessors’ and peers’ theories. The epistemic hubris that Tőzsér identifies in the history of philosophy, and which he demonstrates through his Platonic-style interlocutors’ dialogue, corresponds to failures to acknowledge others’ worth and value as truth-makers or truth-tellers. In short, the failure of the “I’m the only one” approach to philosophy’s intractable issues is a matter of epistemic prejudice and may even support the insights and enduring accuracy of philosophies of epistemic (in)justice, perception, and standpoint theory.
Epistemic Injustice as an Underlying Truth
Examining a brief history of western philosophers, Tőzsér observes that in the face of intractable disagreements over questions of value and issues, from constructing an accurate system of metaphysics to agreeing on the nature of meaning and ordinary language, many thinkers have declared themselves the discoverers or reinventors of a philosophy that really and uniquely expresses the truth of the state of reality or major question at hand. To this end, Tőzsér calls upon (and calls out) Hume, Kant, Husserl, and, less severely, Descartes and Schlick, who each describe their philosophical projects as ultimate and decisive elucidations of philosophical truth that their predecessors and peers each failed to realize.
Certainly, the tendency of philosophers to declare themselves, with rhetoric ranging from assertive to arrogant, the resolvers of rampant philosophical disagreement and the synthesizers, qua Kant, of conflicting approaches to major questions, runs well past the selection of epistemology-inclined projects that Tőzsér samples. Indeed, Heidegger, who drew heavily from his predecessor Husserl, commenced his seminal work Being and Time by announcing the end of philosophy. Tőzsér, by way of a Platonic-style dialogue, elucidates that these self-proclaimed bright minds all suffer from epistemic blindness (114), or biased epistemologies that falsely privilege their own philosophical arguments as compelling over and against their peers’ and predecessors’ philosophical systems and answers.
Tőzsér’s interlocutors are Sophie, who acknowledges the epistemic worth of various thinkers’ conflicting philosophical systems, and Philonous, who exemplifies the epistemic arrogance of those philosophers who declare their work to be the only true and accurate philosophical projects, point to a failure in epistemic capacity. Philonous, while asserting his internally sound metaphysical philosophy ersatz-realism (107–8) that is incompatible and in conflict with all other philosophical views, fails to realize that he does not possess a privileged epistemic position. This failure renders Philonous blind to the worth of and compelling challenges raised by his peers’ and predecessors’ philosophies. Like so many thinkers before him, Philonous insists that his metaphysical system presents a unique and comprehensive philosophy that speaks to unanswered philosophical questions; moreover, rather than resolving debates left standing by other philosophies, Philonous’ philosophical system labels these projects as mistaken and irrational (108), and therefore unworthy of acknowledging and addressing. Philonous’ insistence on his epistemic privilege results in an unfortunately predictable pattern of arrogance, bias, and prejudice that prevents him from meaningfully acknowledging, rather than nominally attending to, other philosophies as compelling and comprising equal status worth grappling with.
Tőzsér’s close examination of the rhetoric that fictional Philonous and the real and revered declarations of philosophical triumph found in Kant, Husserl, and others’ works is telling: the notably self-centered language that these thinkers employ to assert the accuracy and supremacy of their accounts belies an ignorance and unwillingness to engage seriously with other philosophers’ works. Acknowledging others’ accounts fully would result in what Sophie names as the failure to “realize [that one] doesn’t have a privileged status” (109) among thinkers as the discoverer of comprehensive philosophical truth. In other words, these thinkers refuse to take seriously, i.e. acknowledge and attend to, other philosophers’ approaches to intractable problems. The tradition of dismissing peers’ and predecessors’ claims as confused (poorly crafted), logically unsound (irrational), historically bound (limited to irrelevant context), or incomplete (in need of a total overhaul), exemplifies the kind of epistemic injustice and willful ignorance that epistemologists have been rather successful at locating as problematic and the basis of systemic oppression of peoples and suppression of ideas.
If epistemic injustice, qua Fricker and McKinnon, comprises misvaluing, whether by dismissing others’ views or preferencing one’s own, a thinker’s capacity as a knower and worth as asserting truth, the philosophical failure that this chapter examines presents a case in point. Philonous, who balks at Sophie’s attempts to point out philosophies that contract Philonous’ view by also presenting internally sound arguments, is best described as an “epistemic narcissist” (115) who “is unable to do anything against [his ignorance], as he is unaware of it” (115). The western philosophical tradition of continually asserting that the history of philosophy has been incorrect, that the end of philosophy has arrived, and that a thinker’s original account may serve as the deliverer from these philosophical failures and un-truths, appears to suffer from the same epistemic blindness borne of hubristic self-assertion. Willful ignorance of the epistemic worth and call to consider and meaningfully respond to other philosophers’ conflicting interventions and philosophical systems unites each thinker’s distinct and purportedly ultimate solution to philosophical questions.
Since Tőzsér offers the apt diagnosis of epistemic blindness, and even creates a character whose epistemic narcissism is altogether measured with regard to western philosophers’ leading projects, it seems worthwhile to look at view on epistemic injustice and epistemologies of ignorance as offering treatment. To be certain, Tőzsér presents a compelling argument throughout his book project as to why philosophy’s continual failure to resolve significant questions is essential, and devastating, to philosophy itself. At the same time, turning to these epistemic theories, and especially contemporary works on bias and the role of acknowledgment in promoting epistemic justice rather than willful ignorance, might offer Tőzsér a resource for resolving, or at least speaking to, these disagreements.
Though this chapter presents a compelling assessment of and farewell to (116–18) the epistemically unjust “I’m the only one” view, I wonder if this chapter’s dismissal of what Tőzsér rightfully identifies as the wrong approach to philosophy’s failure is also a bit guilty of a failure to acknowledge possibilities for responding to them. Perhaps epistemologies of ignorance and theories of epistemic (in)justice would keep the conversation going and even offer paths toward resolution.
5.21.24 | János Tőzsér
Reply
Is Individual Philosophical Knowledge Possible?
If there’s permanent dissensus on an issue, we’re not willing to trust those philosophers who assert with full confidence that they have knowledge (they have justified the truth of their substantive philosophical theses with knock-down arguments), and explain the dissensus by saying that their interlocutors are unable to see the compelling force of their arguments. In Chapter 4 of my book, I sarcastically call these thinkers “I’m the only one” philosophers and depict them as figures who are unable to put themselves into others’ perspective, are wholly insensitive to the epistemic attraction of others’ pre-philosophical convictions, resistant to the convincing force of others’ arguments, and suffer from epistemic blindness.
Jennifer Lowell reconstructs the line of thought in this chapter precisely (and largely concurs with it), but she isn’t completely satisfied with my solution. As she puts it, “[t]hough this chapter presents a compelling assessment of and farewell to the epistemic unjust ‘I’m the only one’ view, I wonder if this chapter’s dismissal of what Tőzsér rightfully identifies as the wrong approach to philosophy’s failure is also a bit guilty of a failure to acknowledge possibilities for responding to them.” So, let me take another shot to the problem in a wider context, picking up the thread at the introductory line of thought in Chapter 2 of my book.
* * *
Let’s suppose that Tom and Steve disagree with each other. Tom thinks that p is true, while Steve thinks that not-p is true. There may be two things in the background of this disagreement. Either it is that while one of them has knowledge, the other is mistaken, or it is that neither Tom nor Steve has knowledge (at most one of them has true belief). Generally speaking, we can explain all disagreements with two things. Either it is the case that one of the participants of a debate knows something while others don’t know it, or it is the case that none of the participants know the thing under debate (at most one of them has true belief). In a word, we can safely say that if there is permanent dissensus in a question, then either all interlocutors of the debate save one or all of them without exception have beliefs about the subject of the debate that have been shaped by factors that don’t track the truth.
Now, if it doesn’t follow from the fact of given dissensus that nobody has knowledge, then the question arises: why do we strongly tend to think that none of the sides to the debate has knowledge? Why are we reluctant to accept the possibility of individual (or “small-community”) philosophical knowledge—why do we think that philosophical knowledge can only be consensual (or collective)?
We can conceive three scenarios in which S knows some substantive philosophical truths. In the first one, S has a compelling argument for the truth of p—an argument whose conclusive (truth-conducive) nature is questioned by no rational person. An argument which takes away our cognitive freedom for believing otherwise than what the conclusion of the argument asserts. The second case is when S’s argument for the truth of p doesn’t have compelling force, but S’s belief p is in a proper relationship with the truth at issue—p is caused, in an appropriate way, by a fact or state of affairs that makes p true. That is, S’s belief p is produced by a reliable (truth-conducive) belief-producing process, but—and this is what distinguishes this case from the previous one—from her subjective perspective, S doesn’t have access to every factor which is responsible for the reliability (truth-tracking feature) of her argument. In the third case, S’s argument for the truth of p is not a knock-down one, but beyond/above her arguments, she has some further private evidence for the truth of her belief. This evidence is private because it is ineffable (S cannot build it into her argumentation), and yet it reliably indicates to S that her reasoning tracks the truth. This third scenario is akin to the first one and differs from the second in that from her subjective perspective, S has access to every element of her argumentation—her justification is internalist, although she’s unable to make every element of it public. And it is akin to the second one and differs from the first in that the argument itself doesn’t have compelling force—the credibility of the conclusion depends on something that is not part of the argument itself.
As for the first case: if S has knock-down arguments for the truth of p, but there’s permanent dissensus on the issue among philosophers, then it means (it cannot mean anything else) that those who disagree with S don’t understand S’s arguments—they’re unable to see their conclusive nature. As for the second case: if S knows that p in an externalist sense, but there’s permanent dissensus on the issue among philosophers, then it means (it cannot mean anything else) that those who disagree with S are unable to recognize S’s epistemic excellence—the fact that S is a person with a “blessed” belief-producing process. And as for the third case: if S knows p in the sense that she has some further reliable private evidence for the truth of p over and above her arguments, but there’s permanent dissensus on the issue among philosophers, then it means (it cannot mean anything else) that those who disagree with S are unable to recognize S’s exceptional insight force—the fact that S is a person who has come into possession of such experience which show her the truth.
To sum up, although we can conceive three epistemic scenarios in which a philosopher has substantive knowledge, we don’t put our trust in her in light of the permanent dissensus. Nor do we trust those who are convinced that they have gotten into the possession of arguments with compelling force. Nor those who see themselves as epistemically “favored”—the Holy Spirit has restored their minds, restituting their innate but corrupted sensus divinitatis (e.g. Plantinga 2015); their moral greatness leads to their epistemic greatness (while the flaccid and non-autonomous spirits are empiricists, the free and autonomous ones are idealists, see Fichte 1797/1994) or they’re just the lucky winners of the epistemic lottery. And, we don’t trust those, either, who vindicate themselves of philosophical knowledge by citing their private evidence—be it some phenomenologically vivid (visionary or ecstatic) experience or a quiet signal (inner voice or inner compass), which “assures” them of the rock-solid fundamentals of each premise and step in their argument. The question that arises again: why don’t we trust any of them?
* * *
I think this is what most of us have on our mind:
It is true indeed that it does not follow from any permanent philosophical dissensus that nobody has knowledge—every dissensus can be just as well explained by saying that S knows something that the others don’t know as with saying that nobody knows anything. It is also true that we cannot rule out any of the above three epistemic scenarios—for how on earth could we justify this decision of ours beyond all doubt? At the same time, we still have more reason to interpret the fact of permanent dissensus to mean that there’s no individual knowledge than to interpret it to mean that while some know some things, others are mistaken. In a word, we have more reason to distrust those who claim to know substantive philosophical propositions than to trust them.
Let’s take a look at the first scenario. Why do we consider the fact of permanent philosophical dissensus as a sign that philosophers haven’t come up with knock-down arguments? It is because if philosophers have not been able to come up with philosophical arguments in which no points could be disputed by other philosophers (and they haven’t), then we have every reason to suspect that they have not produced any compelling philosophical arguments—similarly, if the community of mathematicians judges a mathematical proof not to be conclusive, then we have every reason to suspect that it actually isn’t. In other words, insofar as there were compelling philosophical arguments, then we would recognize their compelling force—similarly to the community of mathematicians recognizing the conclusive force of conclusive mathematical proofs. Or, as Peter van Inwagen puts it: “[i]f any reasonably well-known philosophical argument for a substantive conclusion had the power to convert an unbiased ideal audience to its conclusion (given that it was presented to the audience under ideal conditions), then, to a high probability, assent to the conclusion of that argument would be more widespread among philosophers than assent to any substantive philosophical thesis actually is” (2006, 52–53).
Let’s now turn to the second and the third scenarios. Why do we consider the fact of permanent philosophical dissensus as indicating that there are no philosophers who are epistemically favored and have special insight force? The reasoning is similar: if there were such philosophers, then we’d recognize them. We’d accept them as epistemic authorities and would give credence to their word—we’d believe them that things stand the way they say they stand. (Just like we’d believe God or angels whatever they say). Of course, it isn’t easy to precisely specify the conditions under which we’d recognize Mary or Esther as epistemic authorities—what matters is that we’d recognize their epistemically privileged position. Just as we recognize someone as a good chicken sexer (as he regularly asserts of male chickens to be male and female to be female), we’d recognize (even if it’d take much more complex weighing) those philosophers who regularly hold true propositions to be true (due to their epistemically favored status or special insight force) and regularly hold false propositions to be false.
I think that considerations like the above are on our mind when we want to give reasons for why we don’t believe in individual philosophical knowledge. Our distrust rests on our trust that we’re able to recognize compelling arguments (we can distinguish them from non-compelling ones) and we’re able to recognize true epistemic authorities (we can distinguish them from false prophets).
* * *
However, we may have some residual bad feeling about the foregoing. For, after all, what if we’re wrong, and our belief in this ability of ours is false? What if there are knock-down philosophical arguments and philosophers who are epistemically favored or have special insight force, and it’s just that we blindly pass them by? As these doubts may arise in us from time to time, we need to say something about them—preferably something reassuring.
Here’s what I can say by way of reassurance. Let’s suppose that we don’t have the ability to recognize arguments with compelling force (whose conclusions we must believe) and epistemic authorities (whose words we must heed). If this is how things stand (we don’t have this ability), then our unease and doubt are meaningless: we’re not to blame for not having recognized the ones with compelling force from among the lots of arguments, and the epistemic authorities from among the lots of philosophers. Our unease and doubt are meaningful only if we have this ability—if we’d recognize knock-down arguments and epistemic authorities (provided there were any).
In another approach, we’re entitled to hold the belief in this ability of us because the call for giving up, suspending or just tempering our belief in this ability has normative weight (regardless of uttered by others or a doubtful inner voice) only if we have the ability that we’re called to give up. Namely, only if we’re able to recognize an argument as one whose conclusion we must believe, and a person as one whose words we must give credence to. In the opposite case, if we’re unable to do so, we are free to believe anything.
Thus, there are two possible cases. Either we’re unable to distinguish between knock-down and non-knock-down arguments as well as between true epistemic authorities and false epistemic prophets—in this case, we’re not open to criticism by others or by ourselves if we continue to hold our belief that we’re able to do so. Or we’re able to distinguish between the above mentioned—and that’s why we’re entitled to believe that we do the right thing when we maintain distrust in those arguments and assertions whose conclusiveness and authority are surrounded by permanent disagreement. In a word, there can be no epistemic situations in which our belief in this ability of us could be shaken—our doubt has epistemic-normative weight only if the object of doubt is true. If you wish, we are entitled to hold this belief under all circumstances—this belief of ours is a hinge belief that is given to us gratis.
References